Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. WHAT CAN A CATEGORICITY THEOREM TELL US?Toby Meadows - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic (3):524-544.
    f The purpose of this paper is to investigate categoricity arguments conducted in second order logic and the philosophical conclusions that can be drawn from them. We provide a way of seeing this result, so to speak, through a first order lens divested of its second order garb. Our purpose is to draw into sharper relief exactly what is involved in this kind of categoricity proof and to highlight the fact that we should be reserved before drawing powerful philosophical conclusions (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Sets and supersets.Toby Meadows - 2016 - Synthese 193 (6):1875-1907.
    It is a commonplace of set theory to say that there is no set of all well-orderings nor a set of all sets. We are implored to accept this due to the threat of paradox and the ensuing descent into unintelligibility. In the absence of promising alternatives, we tend to take up a conservative stance and tow the line: there is no universe. In this paper, I am going to challenge this claim by taking seriously the idea that we can (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Expressibility of propositions in -languages.Pavel Materna - 1974 - Studia Logica 33 (3):259 - 271.
  • Computers as Interactive Machines: Can We Build an Explanatory Abstraction?Alice Martin, Mathieu Magnaudet & Stéphane Conversy - 2023 - Minds and Machines 33 (1):83-112.
    In this paper, we address the question of what current computers are from the point of view of human-computer interaction. In the early days of computing, the Turing machine (TM) has been the cornerstone of the understanding of computers. The TM defines what can be computed and how computation can be carried out. However, in the last decades, computers have evolved and increasingly become interactive systems, reacting in real-time to external events in an ongoing loop. We argue that the TM (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Higher-Order Theory of Presupposition.Scott Martin & Carl Pollard - 2012 - Studia Logica 100 (4):727-751.
    So-called 'dynamic' semantic theories such as Kamp's discourse representation theory and Heim's file change semantics account for such phenomena as cross-sentential anaphora, donkey anaphora, and the novelty condition on indefinites, but compare unfavorably with Montague semantics in some important respects (clarity and simplicity of mathematical foundations, compositionality, handling of quantification and coordination). Preliminary efforts have been made by Muskens and by de Groote to revise and extend Montague semantics to cover dynamic phenomena. We present a new higher-order theory of discourse (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Visions of Henkin.María Manzano & Enrique Alonso - 2015 - Synthese 192 (7):2123-2138.
    Leon Henkin (1921–2006) was not only an extraordinary logician, but also an excellent teacher, a dedicated professor and an exceptional person. The first two sections of this paper are biographical, discussing both his personal and academic life. In the last section we present three aspects of Henkin’s work. First we comment part of his work fruit of his emphasis on teaching. In a personal communication he affirms that On mathematical induction, published in 1969, was the favourite among his articles with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Identity, Equality, Nameability and Completeness.María Manzano & Manuel Crescencio Moreno - 2017 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 46 (3/4).
    This article is an extended promenade strolling along the winding roads of identity, equality, nameability and completeness, looking for places where they converge. We have distinguished between identity and equality; the first is a binary relation between objects while the second is a symbolic relation between terms. Owing to the central role the notion of identity plays in logic, you can be interested either in how to define it using other logical concepts or in the opposite scheme. In the first (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hybrid Partial Type Theory.María Manzano, Antonia Huertas, Patrick Blackburn, Manuel Martins & Víctor Aranda - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-43.
    In this article we define a logical system called Hybrid Partial Type Theory ( $\mathcal {HPTT}$ ). The system is obtained by combining William Farmer’s partial type theory with a strong form of hybrid logic. William Farmer’s system is a version of Church’s theory of types which allows terms to be non-denoting; hybrid logic is a version of modal logic in which it is possible to name worlds and evaluate expressions with respect to particular worlds. We motivate this combination of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Completeness: from Gödel to Henkin.Maria Manzano & Enrique Alonso - 2014 - History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (1):1-26.
    This paper focuses on the evolution of the notion of completeness in contemporary logic. We discuss the differences between the notions of completeness of a theory, the completeness of a calculus, and the completeness of a logic in the light of Gödel's and Tarski's crucial contributions.We place special emphasis on understanding the differences in how these concepts were used then and now, as well as on the role they play in logic. Nevertheless, we can still observe a certain ambiguity in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Much Ado About the Many.Jonathan Mai - 2021 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 25 (1).
    English distinguishes between singular quantifiers like "a donkey" and plural quantifiers like "some donkeys". Pluralists hold that plural quantifiers range in an unusual, irreducibly plural, way over common objects, namely individuals from first-order domains and not over set-like objects. The favoured framework of pluralism is plural first-order logic, PFO, an interpreted first-order language that is capable of expressing plural quantification. Pluralists argue for their position by claiming that the standard formal theory based on PFO is both ontologically neutral and really (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logical constants.John MacFarlane - 2008 - Mind.
    Logic is usually thought to concern itself only with features that sentences and arguments possess in virtue of their logical structures or forms. The logical form of a sentence or argument is determined by its syntactic or semantic structure and by the placement of certain expressions called “logical constants.”[1] Thus, for example, the sentences Every boy loves some girl. and Some boy loves every girl. are thought to differ in logical form, even though they share a common syntactic and semantic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Alonzo church:his life, his work and some of his miracles.Maía Manzano - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (4):211-232.
    This paper is dedicated to Alonzo Church, who died in August 1995 after a long life devoted to logic. To Church we owe lambda calculus, the thesis bearing his name and the solution to the Entscheidungsproblem.His well-known book Introduction to Mathematical LogicI, defined the subject matter of mathematical logic, the approach to be taken and the basic topics addressed. Church was the creator of the Journal of Symbolic Logicthe best-known journal of the area, which he edited for several decades This (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Formal semantics in modern type theories with coercive subtyping.Zhaohui Luo - 2012 - Linguistics and Philosophy 35 (6):491-513.
    In the formal semantics based on modern type theories, common nouns are interpreted as types, rather than as predicates of entities as in Montague’s semantics. This brings about important advantages in linguistic interpretations but also leads to a limitation of expressive power because there are fewer operations on types as compared with those on predicates. The theory of coercive subtyping adequately extends the modern type theories and, as shown in this paper, plays a very useful role in making type theories (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • On church's formal theory of functions and functionals.Giuseppe Longo - 1988 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 40 (2):93-133.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On church's formal theory of functions and functionals: The λ-calculus: connections to higher type recursion theory, proof theory, category theory.Giuseppe Longo - 1988 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 40 (2):93-133.
  • Intertheoretic Reduction, Confirmation, and Montague’s Syntax-Semantics Relation.Kristina Liefke & Stephan Hartmann - 2018 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 27 (4):313-341.
    Intertheoretic relations are an important topic in the philosophy of science. However, since their classical discussion by Ernest Nagel, such relations have mostly been restricted to relations between pairs of theories in the natural sciences. This paper presents a case study of a new type of intertheoretic relation that is inspired by Montague’s analysis of the linguistic syntax-semantics relation. The paper develops a simple model of this relation. To motivate the adoption of our new model, we show that this model (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Carnap, Goguen, and the hyperontologies: Logical pluralism and heterogeneous structuring in ontology design. [REVIEW]Dominik Lücke - 2010 - Logica Universalis 4 (2):255-333.
    This paper addresses questions of universality related to ontological engineering, namely aims at substantiating (negative) answers to the following three basic questions: (i) Is there a ‘universal ontology’?, (ii) Is there a ‘universal formal ontology language’?, and (iii) Is there a universally applicable ‘mode of reasoning’ for formal ontologies? To support our answers in a principled way, we present a general framework for the design of formal ontologies resting on two main principles: firstly, we endorse Rudolf Carnap’s principle of logical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Programs, grammars and arguments: A personal view of some connections between computation, language and logic.J. Lambek - 1997 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 3 (3):312-328.
    As an undergraduate I was taught to multiply two numbers with the help of log tables, using the formulaHaving graduated to teach calculus to Engineers, I learned that log tables were to be replaced by slide rules. It was then that Imade the fateful decision that there was no need for me to learn how to use this tedious device, as I could always rely on the students to perform the necessary computations. In the course of time, slide rules were (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Functional completeness of cartesian categories.J. Lambek - 1974 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 6 (3):259.
  • A modern elaboration of the ramified theory of types.Twan Laan & Rob Nederpelt - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (2-3):243 - 278.
    The paper first formalizes the ramified type theory as (informally) described in the Principia Mathematica [32]. This formalization is close to the ideas of the Principia, but also meets contemporary requirements on formality and accuracy, and therefore is a new supply to the known literature on the Principia (like [25], [19], [6] and [7]).As an alternative, notions from the ramified type theory are expressed in a lambda calculus style. This situates the type system of Russell and Whitehead in a modern (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Looking backwards in type logic.Jan Köpping & Thomas Ede Zimmermann - 2021 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 64 (5-6):646-672.
    ABSTRACT Backwards-looking operators Saarinen, E. [1979. “Backwards-Looking Operators in Tense Logic and in Natural Language.” In Essays on Mathematical and Philosophical Logic, edited by J. Hintikka, I. Niiniluoto, and E. Saarinen, 341–367. Dordrecht: Reidel] that have the material in their scope depend on higher intensional operators, are known to increase the expressivity of some intensional languages and have thus played a central role in debates about approaches to intensionality in terms of implicit parameters vs. variables explicitly quantifying over them. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Substitution contradiction, its resolution and the Church-Rosser Theorem in TIL.Miloš Kosterec - 2020 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 49 (1):121-133.
    I present an analysis according to which the current state of the definition of substitution leads to a contradiction in the system of Transparent Intensional Logic. I entail the contradiction using only the basic definitions of TIL and standard results. I then analyse the roots of the contradiction and motivate the path I take in resolving the contradiction. I provide a new amended definition of collision-less substitution which blocks the contradiction in a non-ad hoc way. I elaborate on the consequences (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On the number of types.Miloš Kosterec - 2017 - Synthese 194 (12):5005-5021.
    In this paper, I investigate type theories from several perspectives. First, I present and elaborate the philosophical and technical motivations for these theories. I then offer a formal analysis of various TTs, focusing on the cardinality of the set of types contained in each. I argue that these TTs can be divided into four formal categories, which are derived from the cardinality of the set of their basic elementary types and the finiteness of the lengths of their molecular types. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Cooper Storage Idiom.Gregory M. Kobele - 2018 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 27 (2):95-131.
    Cooper storage is a widespread technique for associating sentences with their meanings, used in diverse linguistic and computational linguistic traditions. This paper encodes the data structures and operations of cooper storage in the simply typed linear \-calculus, revealing the rich categorical structure of a graded applicative functor. In the case of finite cooper storage, which corresponds to ideas in current transformational approaches to syntax, the semantic interpretation function can be given as a linear homomorphism acting on a regular set of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The difficulty with the well-formedness of ontological statements.Guido Küng - 1983 - Topoi 2 (1):111-119.
    When Russell argued for his ontological convictions, for instance that there are negative facts or that there are universals, he expressed himself in English. But Wittgenstein must have noticed that from the point of view of Russell's ideal language these ontological statements appear to be pseudo-propositions. He believed therefore that what these statements pretend to say, could not really be said but only shown. Carnap discovered a way out of this mutism: what in the material mode of speech of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The paradoxes and Russell's theory of incomplete symbols.Kevin C. Klement - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 169 (2):183-207.
    Russell claims in his autobiography and elsewhere that he discovered his 1905 theory of descriptions while attempting to solve the logical and semantic paradoxes plaguing his work on the foundations of mathematics. In this paper, I hope to make the connection between his work on the paradoxes and the theory of descriptions and his theory of incomplete symbols generally clearer. In particular, I argue that the theory of descriptions arose from the realization that not only can a class not be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The concept horse is a concept.Ansten Klev - 2018 - Review of Symbolic Logic 11 (3):547-572.
    I offer an analysis of the sentence "the concept horse is a concept". It will be argued that the grammatical subject of this sentence, "the concept horse", indeed refers to a concept, and not to an object, as Frege once held. The argument is based on a criterion of proper-namehood according to which an expression is a proper name if it is so rendered in Frege's ideography. The predicate "is a concept", on the other hand, should not be thought of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Spiritus Asper versus Lambda: On the Nature of Functional Abstraction.Ansten Klev - 2023 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 64 (2):205-223.
    The spiritus asper as used by Frege in a letter to Russell from 1904 bears resemblance to Church’s lambda. It is natural to ask how they relate to each other. An alternative approach to functional abstraction developed by Per Martin-Löf some thirty years ago allows us to describe the relationship precisely. Frege’s spiritus asper provides a way of restructuring a unary function name in Frege’s sense such that the argument place indicator occurs all the way to the right. Martin-Löf’s alternative (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Russell's 1903 - 1905 Anticipation of the Lambda Calculus.Kevin Klement - 2003 - History and Philosophy of Logic 24 (1):15-37.
    It is well known that the circumflex notation used by Russell and Whitehead to form complex function names in Principia Mathematica played a role in inspiring Alonzo Church's “lambda calculus” for functional logic developed in the 1920s and 1930s. Interestingly, earlier unpublished manuscripts written by Russell between 1903–1905—surely unknown to Church—contain a more extensive anticipation of the essential details of the lambda calculus. Russell also anticipated Schönfinkel's combinatory logic approach of treating multiargument functions as functions having other functions as value. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Identity in Martin‐Löf type theory.Ansten Klev - 2021 - Philosophy Compass 17 (2):e12805.
    The logic of identity contains riches not seen through the coarse lens of predicate logic. This is one of several lessons to draw from the subtle treatment of identity in Martin‐Löf type theory, to which the reader will be introduced in this article. After a brief general introduction we shall mainly be concerned with the distinction between identity propositions and identity judgements. These differ from each other both in logical form and in logical strength. Along the way, connections to philosophical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Identity and Sortals.Ansten Klev - 2017 - Erkenntnis 82 (1):1-16.
    According to the sortal conception of the universe of individuals every individual falls under a highest sortal, or category. It is argued here that on this conception the identity relation is defined between individuals a and b if and only if a and b fall under a common category. Identity must therefore be regarded as a relation of the form \, with three arguments x, y, and Z, where Z ranges over categories, and where the range of x and y (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Husserl's Logical Grammar.Ansten Klev - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (3):232-269.
    Lecture notes from Husserl's logic lectures published during the last 20 years offer a much better insight into his doctrine of the forms of meaning than does the fourth Logical Investigation or any other work published during Husserl's lifetime. This paper provides a detailed reconstruction, based on all the sources now available, of Husserl's system of logical grammar. After having explained the notion of meaning that Husserl assumes in his later logic lectures as well as the notion of form of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mechanizing principia logico-metaphysica in functional type-theory.Daniel Kirchner, Christoph Benzmüller & Edward N. Zalta - 2018 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (1):206-218.
    Principia Logico-Metaphysica contains a foundational logical theory for metaphysics, mathematics, and the sciences. It includes a canonical development of Abstract Object Theory [AOT], a metaphysical theory that distinguishes between ordinary and abstract objects.This article reports on recent work in which AOT has been successfully represented and partly automated in the proof assistant system Isabelle/HOL. Initial experiments within this framework reveal a crucial but overlooked fact: a deeply-rooted and known paradox is reintroduced in AOT when the logic of complex terms is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Standard Formalization.Jeffrey Ketland - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (3):711-748.
    A standard formalization of a scientific theory is a system of axioms for that theory in a first-order language (possibly many-sorted; possibly with the membership primitive $$\in$$ ). Suppes (in: Carvallo M (ed) Nature, cognition and system II. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1992) expressed skepticism about whether there is a “simple or elegant method” for presenting mathematicized scientific theories in such a standard formalization, because they “assume a great deal of mathematics as part of their substructure”. The major difficulties amount to these. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Foundations of applied mathematics I.Jeffrey Ketland - 2021 - Synthese 199 (1-2):4151-4193.
    This paper aims to study the foundations of applied mathematics, using a formalized base theory for applied mathematics: ZFCAσ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$ \mathsf {ZFCA}_{\sigma }$$\end{document} with atoms, where the subscript used refers to a signature specific to the application. Examples are given, illustrating the following five features of applied mathematics: comprehension principles, application conditionals, representation hypotheses, transfer principles and abstract equivalents.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Variants of Gödel’s Ontological Proof in a Natural Deduction Calculus.B. Woltzenlogel Paleo & Annika Kanckos - 2017 - Studia Logica 105 (3):553-586.
    This paper presents detailed formalizations of ontological arguments in a simple modal natural deduction calculus. The first formal proof closely follows the hints in Scott’s manuscript about Gödel’s argument and fills in the gaps, thus verifying its correctness. The second formal proof improves the first one, by relying on the weaker modal logic KB instead of S5 and by avoiding the equality relation. The second proof is also technically shorter than the first one, because it eliminates unnecessary detours and uses (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Types in logic and mathematics before 1940.Fairouz Kamareddine, Twan Laan & Rob Nederpelt - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (2):185-245.
    In this article, we study the prehistory of type theory up to 1910 and its development between Russell and Whitehead's Principia Mathematica ([71], 1910-1912) and Church's simply typed λ-calculus of 1940. We first argue that the concept of types has always been present in mathematics, though nobody was incorporating them explicitly as such, before the end of the 19th century. Then we proceed by describing how the logical paradoxes entered the formal systems of Frege, Cantor and Peano concentrating on Frege's (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A correspondence between Martin-löf type theory, the ramified theory of types and pure type systems.Fairouz Kamareddine & Twan Laan - 2001 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10 (3):375-402.
    In Russell''s Ramified Theory of Types RTT, two hierarchical concepts dominate:orders and types. The use of orders has as a consequencethat the logic part of RTT is predicative.The concept of order however, is almost deadsince Ramsey eliminated it from RTT. This is whywe find Church''s simple theory of types (which uses the type concept without the order one) at the bottom of the Barendregt Cube rather than RTT. Despite the disappearance of orders which have a strong correlation with predicativity, predicative (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Completeness and Herbrand Theorems for Nominal Logic.James Cheney - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (1):299 - 320.
    Nominal logic is a variant of first-order logic in which abstract syntax with names and binding is formalized in terms of two basic operations: name-swapping and freshness. It relies on two important principles: equivariance (validity is preserved by name-swapping), and fresh name generation ("new" or fresh names can always be chosen). It is inspired by a particular class of models for abstract syntax trees involving names and binding, drawing on ideas from Fraenkel-Mostowski set theory: finite-support models in which each value (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Probabilities on Sentences in an Expressive Logic.Marcus Hutter, John W. Lloyd, Kee Siong Ng & William T. B. Uther - 2013 - Journal of Applied Logic 11 (4):386-420.
    Automated reasoning about uncertain knowledge has many applications. One difficulty when developing such systems is the lack of a completely satisfactory integration of logic and probability. We address this problem directly. Expressive languages like higher-order logic are ideally suited for representing and reasoning about structured knowledge. Uncertain knowledge can be modeled by using graded probabilities rather than binary truth-values. The main technical problem studied in this paper is the following: Given a set of sentences, each having some probability of being (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why Ramify?Harold T. Hodes - 2015 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 56 (2):379-415.
    This paper considers two reasons that might support Russell’s choice of a ramified-type theory over a simple-type theory. The first reason is the existence of purported paradoxes that can be formulated in any simple-type language, including an argument that Russell considered in 1903. These arguments depend on certain converse-compositional principles. When we take account of Russell’s doctrine that a propositional function is not a constituent of its values, these principles turn out to be too implausible to make these arguments troubling. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Lambda‐Calculus Models and Extensionality.R. Hindley & G. Longo - 1980 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 26 (19-21):289-310.
  • CERES in higher-order logic.Stefan Hetzl, Alexander Leitsch & Daniel Weller - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (12):1001-1034.
    We define a generalization of the first-order cut-elimination method CERES to higher-order logic. At the core of lies the computation of an set of sequents from a proof π of a sequent S. A refutation of in a higher-order resolution calculus can be used to transform cut-free parts of π into a cut-free proof of S. An example illustrates the method and shows that can produce meaningful cut-free proofs in mathematics that traditional cut-elimination methods cannot reach.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Simplified Proof of the Epsilon Theorems.Stefan Hetzl - forthcoming - Review of Symbolic Logic:1-16.
    We formulate Hilbert’s epsilon calculus in the context of expansion proofs. This leads to a simplified proof of the epsilon theorems by disposing of the need for prenexification, Skolemisation, and their respective inverse transformations. We observe that the natural notion of cut in the epsilon calculus is associative.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reasoning about conditional probabilities in a higher-order-logic theorem prover.Osman Hasan & Sofiène Tahar - 2011 - Journal of Applied Logic 9 (1):23-40.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Formal reliability analysis of combinational circuits using theorem proving.Osman Hasan, Jigar Patel & Sofiène Tahar - 2011 - Journal of Applied Logic 9 (1):41-60.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Book review. [REVIEW]John Hale - 2007 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 16 (2):217-220.
    This is a good book. Its main message is that a particular approach to natural language called type-logical grammar can, in-principle, be equipped with a learning theory. In this review, I first identify what type-logical grammar is, then outline what the learning theory is. Then I try to articulate why this message is important for the logical, linguistic and information-theoretic parts of cognitive science. Overall, I think the book’s main message is significant enough to warrant patience with its scientific limitations.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The systems of Leśniewski in relation to contemporary logical research.Andrzej Grzegorczyk - 1955 - Studia Logica 3 (1):77-95.
  • Semantics with Dependent Types for Indefinites.Justyna Grudzińska - 2016 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 46 (1):173-192.
    The paper proposes a new semantics with dependent types for indefinites, encompassing both the data related to their exceptional scopal behavior and the data related to their anaphoric properties. The proposal builds on the formal system combining generalized quantifiers with dependent types in [Grudzińska & Zawadowski 2014] and [Grudzińska & Zawadowski 2016].
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the termination of russell’s description elimination algorithm.Clemens Grabmayer, Joop Leo, Vincent van Oostrom & Albert Visser - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):367-393.
    In this paper we study the termination behavior of Russell’s description elimination rewrite system. We discuss certain claims made by Kripke (2005) in his paper concerning the possible nontermination of elimination of descriptions.
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations