Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Reaching Transparent Truth.Pablo Cobreros, Paul Égré, David Ripley & Robert van Rooij - 2013 - Mind 122 (488):841-866.
    This paper presents and defends a way to add a transparent truth predicate to classical logic, such that and A are everywhere intersubstitutable, where all T-biconditionals hold, and where truth can be made compositional. A key feature of our framework, called STTT (for Strict-Tolerant Transparent Truth), is that it supports a non-transitive relation of consequence. At the same time, it can be seen that the only failures of transitivity STTT allows for arise in paradoxical cases.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Monotone inductive definitions over the continuum.Douglas Cenzer - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (1):188-198.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Notes on Formal Theories of Truth.Andrea Cantini - 1989 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 35 (2):97-130.
  • Levels of implication and type free theories of classifications with approximation operator.Andrea Cantini - 1992 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 38 (1):107-141.
    We investigate a theory of Frege structures extended by the Myhill-Flagg hierarchy of implications. We study its relation to a property theory with an approximation operator and we give a proof theoretical analysis of the basic system involved. MSC: 03F35, 03D60.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Extending the first-order theory of combinators with self-referential truth.Andrea Cantini - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (2):477-513.
    The aim of this paper is to introduce a formal system STW of self-referential truth, which extends the classical first-order theory of pure combinators with a truth predicate and certain approximation axioms. STW naturally embodies the mechanisms of general predicate application/abstraction on a par with function application/abstraction; in addition, it allows non-trivial constructions, inspired by generalized recursion theory. As a consequence, STW provides a smooth inner model for Myhill's systems with levels of implication.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The truth is never simple.John P. Burgess - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):663-681.
    The complexity of the set of truths of arithmetic is determined for various theories of truth deriving from Kripke and from Gupta and Herzberger.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • A note on theories for quasi-inductive definitions.Riccardo Bruni - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):684-699.
    This paper introduces theories for arithmetical quasi-inductive definitions (Burgess, 1986) as it has been done for first-order monotone and nonmonotone inductive ones. After displaying the basic axiomatic framework, we provide some initial result in the proof theoretic bounds line of research (the upper one being given in terms of a theory of sets extending Kripke–Platek set theory).
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The logic of choice.Andreas Blass & Yuri Gurevich - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1264-1310.
    The choice construct (choose x: φ(x)) is useful in software specifications. We study extensions of first-order logic with the choice construct. We prove some results about Hilbert's ε operator, but in the main part of the paper we consider the case when all choices are independent.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On Moschovakis closure ordinals.Jon Barwise - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (2):292-296.
  • Global inductive definability.Jon Barwise & Yiannis N. Moschovakis - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (3):521-534.
    We show that several theorems on ordinal bounds in different parts of logic are simple consequences of a basic result in the theory of global inductive definitions.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ultimate truth vis- à- vis stable truth.P. D. Welch - 2008 - Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (1):126-142.
    We show that the set of ultimately true sentences in Hartry Field's Revenge-immune solution model to the semantic paradoxes is recursively isomorphic to the set of stably true sentences obtained in Hans Herzberger's revision sequence starting from the null hypothesis. We further remark that this shows that a substantial subsystem of second-order number theory is needed to establish the semantic values of sentences in Field's relative consistency proof of his theory over the ground model of the standard natural numbers: -CA0 (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Axiomatizing Kripke’s Theory of Truth.Volker Halbach & Leon Horsten - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (2):677 - 712.
    We investigate axiomatizations of Kripke's theory of truth based on the Strong Kleene evaluation scheme for treating sentences lacking a truth value. Feferman's axiomatization KF formulated in classical logic is an indirect approach, because it is not sound with respect to Kripke's semantics in the straightforward sense: only the sentences that can be proved to be true in KF are valid in Kripke's partial models. Reinhardt proposed to focus just on the sentences that can be proved to be true in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Omega‐ and Beta‐Models of Alternative Set Theory.Athanassios Tzouvaras - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (4):547-569.
    We present the axioms of Alternative Set Theory in the language of second-order arithmetic and study its ω- and β-models. These are expansions of the form , M ⊆ P, of nonstandard models M of Peano arithmetic such that ⊩ AST and ω ϵ M. Our main results are: A countable M ⊩ PA is β-expandable iff there is a regular well-ordering for M. Every countable β-model can be elementarily extended to an ω-model which is not a β-model. The Ω-orderings (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On expandability of models of peano arithmetic to models of the alternative set theory.Athanassios Tzouvaras - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (2):452-460.
    We give a sufficient condition for a countable model M of PA to be expandable to an ω-model of AST with absolute Ω-orderings. The condition is in terms of saturation schemes or, equivalently, in terms of the ability of the model to code sequences which have some kind of definition in (M, ω). We also show that a weaker scheme of saturation leads to the existence of wellorderings of the model with nice properties. Finally, we answer affirmatively the question of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Classifying the computational complexity of problems.Larry Stockmeyer - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):1-43.
  • ŁΠ logic with fixed points.Luca Spada - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (7-8):741-763.
    We study a system, μŁΠ, obtained by an expansion of ŁΠ logic with fixed points connectives. The first main result of the paper is that μŁΠ is standard complete, i.e., complete with regard to the unit interval of real numbers endowed with a suitable structure. We also prove that the class of algebras which forms algebraic semantics for this logic is generated, as a variety, by its linearly ordered members and that they are precisely the interval algebras of real closed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intrinsically Hyperarithmetical Sets.Ivan N. Soskov - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):469-480.
    The main result proved in the paper is that on every recursive structure the intrinsically hyperarithmetical sets coincide with the relatively intrinsically hyperarithmetical sets. As a side effect of the proof an effective version of the Kueker's theorem on definability by means of infinitary formulas is obtained.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Intrinsically II 11 Relations.Ivan N. Soskov - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):109-126.
    An external characterization of the inductive sets on countable abstract structures is presented. The main result is an abstract version of the classical Suslin-Kleene characterization of the hyperarithmetical sets.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A guide to truth predicates in the modern era.Michael Sheard - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (3):1032-1054.
  • Some Notes on Truths and Comprehension.Thomas Schindler - 2018 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 47 (3):449-479.
    In this paper we study several translations that map models and formulae of the language of second-order arithmetic to models and formulae of the language of truth. These translations are useful because they allow us to exploit results from the extensive literature on arithmetic to study the notion of truth. Our purpose is to present these connections in a systematic way, generalize some well-known results in this area, and to provide a number of new results. Sections 3 and 4 contain (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Ordinal spectra of first-order theories.John Stewart Schlipf - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (4):492-505.
  • A Unified Theory of Truth and Paradox.Lorenzo Rossi - 2019 - Review of Symbolic Logic 12 (2):209-254.
    The sentences employed in semantic paradoxes display a wide range of semantic behaviours. However, the main theories of truth currently available either fail to provide a theory of paradox altogether, or can only account for some paradoxical phenomena by resorting to multiple interpretations of the language. In this paper, I explore the wide range of semantic behaviours displayed by paradoxical sentences, and I develop a unified theory of truth and paradox, that is a theory of truth that also provides a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Adding a Conditional to Kripke’s Theory of Truth.Lorenzo Rossi - 2016 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 45 (5):485-529.
    Kripke’s theory of truth, 690–716; 1975) has been very successful but shows well-known expressive difficulties; recently, Field has proposed to overcome them by adding a new conditional connective to it. In Field’s theories, desirable conditional and truth-theoretic principles are validated that Kripke’s theory does not yield. Some authors, however, are dissatisfied with certain aspects of Field’s theories, in particular the high complexity. I analyze Field’s models and pin down some reasons for discontent with them, focusing on the meaning of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Revision Without Revision Sequences: Circular Definitions.Edoardo Rivello - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (1):57-85.
    The classical theory of definitions bans so-called circular definitions, namely, definitions of a unary predicate P, based on stipulations of the form $$Px =_{\mathsf {Df}} \phi,$$where ϕ is a formula of a fixed first-order language and the definiendumP occurs into the definiensϕ. In their seminal book The Revision Theory of Truth, Gupta and Belnap claim that “General theories of definitions are possible within which circular definitions [...] make logical and semantic sense” [p. IX]. In order to sustain their claim, they (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Monotone inductive definitions in explicit mathematics.Michael Rathjen - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (1):125-146.
    The context for this paper is Feferman's theory of explicit mathematics, T 0 . We address a problem that was posed in [6]. Let MID be the principle stating that any monotone operation on classifications has a least fixed point. The main objective of this paper is to show that T 0 + MID, when based on classical logic, also proves the existence of non-monotone inductive definitions that arise from arbitrary extensional operations on classifications. From the latter we deduce that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How to develop Proof‐Theoretic Ordinal Functions on the basis of admissible ordinals.Michael Rathjen - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):47-54.
    In ordinal analysis of impredicative theories so-called collapsing functions are of central importance. Unfortunately, the definition procedure of these functions makes essential use of uncountable cardinals whereas the notation system that they call into being corresponds to a recursive ordinal. It has long been claimed that, instead, one should manage to develop such functions directly on the basis of admissible ordinals. This paper is meant to show how this can be done. Interpreting the collapsing functions as operating directly on admissible (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Explicit mathematics with the monotone fixed point principle.Michael Rathjen - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (2):509-542.
    The context for this paper is Feferman's theory of explicit mathematics, a formal framework serving many purposes. It is suitable for representing Bishop-style constructive mathematics as well as generalized recursion, including direct expression of structural concepts which admit self-application. The object of investigation here is the theory of explicit mathematics augmented by the monotone fixed point principle, which asserts that any monotone operation on classifications (Feferman's notion of set) possesses a least fixed point. To be more precise, the new axiom (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ordinals connected with formal theories for transfinitely iterated inductive definitions.W. Pohlers - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (2):161-182.
  • Uniform inductive definability and infinitary languages.Anders M. Nyberg - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (1):109-120.
  • Models for recursion theory.Johan Moldestad & Dag Normann - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (4):719-729.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Infinitary tableau for semantic truth.Toby Meadows - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (2):207-235.
  • Field’s logic of truth.Vann McGee - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 147 (3):421-432.
  • Some restrictions on simple fixed points of the integers.G. L. McColm - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1324-1345.
    A function is recursive (in given operations) if its values are computed explicitly and uniformly in terms of other "previously computed" values of itself and (perhaps) other "simultaneously computed" recursive functions. Here, "explicitly" includes definition by cases. We investigate those recursive functions on the structure $\mathbf{N} = \langle \omega, 0, \operatorname{succ,pred}\rangle$ that are computed in terms of themselves only, without other simultaneously computed recursive functions.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dimension Versus Number of Variables, and Connectivity, too.Gregory L. McColm - 1995 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 41 (1):111-134.
    We present game-theoretic characterizations of the complexity/expressibility measures “dimension” and “the number of variables” as Least Fixed Point queries. As an example, we use these characterizations to compute the dimension and number of variables of Connectivity and Connectivity.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Μ-definable sets of integers.Robert S. Lubarsky - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (1):291-313.
  • Supervaluation fixed-point logics of truth.Philip Kremer & Alasdair Urquhart - 2008 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 37 (5):407-440.
    Michael Kremer defines fixed-point logics of truth based on Saul Kripke’s fixed point semantics for languages expressing their own truth concepts. Kremer axiomatizes the strong Kleene fixed-point logic of truth and the weak Kleene fixed-point logic of truth, but leaves the axiomatizability question open for the supervaluation fixed-point logic of truth and its variants. We show that the principal supervaluation fixed point logic of truth, when thought of as consequence relation, is highly complex: it is not even analytic. We also (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Invisible Ordinals and Inductive Definitions.Evangelos Kranakis - 1982 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 28 (8‐12):137-148.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Recursion in a quantifier vs. elementary induction.Phokion G. Kolaitis - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (2):235-259.
  • Barwise: Infinitary logic and admissible sets.H. Jerome Keisler & Julia F. Knight - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (1):4-36.
    §0. Introduction. In [16], Barwise described his graduate study at Stanford. He told of his interactions with Kreisel and Scott, and said how he chose Feferman as his advisor. He began working on admissible fragments of infinitary logic after reading and giving seminar talks on two Ph.D. theses which had recently been completed: that of Lopez-Escobar, at Berkeley, on infinitary logic [46], and that of Platek [58], at Stanford, on admissible sets.Barwise's work on infinitary logic and admissible sets is described (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The mathematical import of zermelo's well-ordering theorem.Akihiro Kanamori - 1997 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 3 (3):281-311.
    Set theory, it has been contended, developed from its beginnings through a progression ofmathematicalmoves, despite being intertwined with pronounced metaphysical attitudes and exaggerated foundational claims that have been held on its behalf. In this paper, the seminal results of set theory are woven together in terms of a unifying mathematical motif, one whose transmutations serve to illuminate the historical development of the subject. The motif is foreshadowed in Cantor's diagonal proof, and emerges in the interstices of the inclusion vs. membership (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Minimal predicates, fixed-points, and definability.Johan van Benthem - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):696-712.
    Minimal predicates P satisfying a given first-order description φ(P) occur widely in mathematical logic and computer science. We give an explicit first-order syntax for special first-order ‘PIA conditions’ φ(P) which guarantees unique existence of such minimal predicates. Our main technical result is a preservation theorem showing PIA-conditions to be expressively complete for all those first-order formulas that are preserved under a natural model-theoretic operation of ‘predicate intersection’. Next, we show how iterated predicate minimization on PIA-conditions yields a language MIN(FO) equal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • A proof-theoretic framework for logic programming.Gerhard Jäger & Robert F. Stärk - 1998 - In Samuel R. Buss (ed.), Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. Elsevier. pp. 639--682.
  • About the proof-theoretic ordinals of weak fixed point theories.Gerhard Jäger & Barbara Primo - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):1108-1119.
    This paper presents several proof-theoretic results concerning weak fixed point theories over second order number theory with arithmetic comprehension and full or restricted induction on the natural numbers. It is also shown that there are natural second order theories which are proof-theoretically equivalent but have different proof-theoretic ordinals.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Number of variables is equivalent to space.Neil Immerman, Jonathan F. Buss & David A. Mix Barrington - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1217-1230.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Finite level borel games and a problem concerning the jump hierarchy.Harold T. Hodes - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1301-1318.
  • Selection in abstract recursion theory.L. A. Harrington & D. B. Macqueen - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (1):153-158.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Refinements of Vaught's normal from theorem.Victor Harnik - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (3):289-306.
  • On characterizing Spector classes.Leo A. Harrington & Alexander S. Kechris - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (1):19-24.
  • Tarskian and Kripkean truth.Volker Halbach - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (1):69-80.
    A theory of the transfinite Tarskian hierarchy of languages is outlined and compared to a notion of partial truth by Kripke. It is shown that the hierarchy can be embedded into Kripke's minimal fixed point model. From this results on the expressive power of both approaches are obtained.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Necessities and Necessary Truths: A Prolegomenon to the Use of Modal Logic in the Analysis of Intensional Notions.V. Halbach & P. Welch - 2009 - Mind 118 (469):71-100.
    In philosophical logic necessity is usually conceived as a sentential operator rather than as a predicate. An intensional sentential operator does not allow one to express quantified statements such as 'There are necessary a posteriori propositions' or 'All laws of physics are necessary' in first-order logic in a straightforward way, while they are readily formalized if necessity is formalized by a predicate. Replacing the operator conception of necessity by the predicate conception, however, causes various problems and forces one to reject (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations