Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. What about pictures?J. B. Deregowski - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):757-758.
  • Why creative intelligence is hard to find.Daniel Dennett - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):253-253.
  • Taking the intentional stance seriously.Daniel C. Dennett - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):379-390.
  • The milk of human intentionality.Daniel Dennett - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):428-430.
  • Science, philosophy, and interpretation.Daniel C. Dennett - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):535.
  • Precis of the intentional stance.Daniel C. Dennett - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):495-505.
    The intentional stance is the strategy of prediction and explanation that attributes beliefs, desires, and other states to systems and predicts future behavior from what it would be rational for an agent to do, given those beliefs and desires. Any system whose performance can be thus predicted and explained is an intentional system, whatever its innards. The strategy of treating parts of the world as intentional systems is the foundation of but is also exploited in artificial intelligence and cognitive science (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: The 'panglossian paradigm' defended.Daniel C. Dennett - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):343-90.
    Ethologists and others studying animal behavior in a spirit are in need of a descriptive language and method that are neither anachronistically bound by behaviorist scruples nor prematurely committed to particular Just such an interim descriptive method can be found in intentional system theory. The use of intentional system theory is illustrated with the case of the apparently communicative behavior of vervet monkeys. A way of using the theory to generate data - including usable, testable data - is sketched. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   595 citations  
  • On not having a theory of mind.Beatrice de Gelder - 1987 - Cognition 27 (3):285-290.
  • Above suspicion: Cognitive and intentional aspects of the ability to lie.Beatrice De Gelder - 1988 - Argumentation 2 (1):77-87.
    This paper looks at the attribution of the ability to lie and not at lying or lies. It also departs from more familiar approaches by focussing on the appraisal of an ability and not on the ability in itself. We believe that this attribution perspective is required to bring out the cognitive and intentional basis of the ability to lie.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adaptationism was always predictive and needed no defense.Richard Dawkins - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):360-361.
  • Skinner as conceptual analyst.Lawrence H. Davis - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):623.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The use and mention of terms and the simulation of linguistic understanding.Arthur C. Danto - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):428-428.
  • The notional world of D. C. Dennett.Arthur C. Danto - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):509.
  • Science as an international system.Arthur C. Danto - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):359-360.
  • Deception and explanatory economy.Arthur C. Danto - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):252-253.
  • Ethological foxes and cognitive hedgehogs.Jeffrey Cynx & Stephen J. Clark - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):756-757.
  • Dennett's realisation theory of the relation between folk and scientific psychology.Adrian Cussins - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):508.
  • Evidence for the innateness of deontic reasoning.Denise Dellarosa Cummins - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (2):160-90.
    When reasoning about deontic rules (what one may, should, or should not do in a given set of circumstances), reasoners adopt a violation‐detection strategy, a strategy they do not adopt when reasoning about indicative rules (descriptions of purported state of affairs). I argue that this indicative‐deontic distinction constitutes a primitive in the cognitive architecture. To support this claim, I show that this distinction emerges early in development, is observed regardless of the cultural background of the reasoner, and can be selectively (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Dominance hierarchies and the evolution of human reasoning.Denise Dellarosa Cummins - 1996 - Minds and Machines 6 (4):463-480.
    Research from ethology and evolutionary biology indicates the following about the evolution of reasoning capacity. First, solving problems of social competition and cooperation have direct impact on survival rates and reproductive success. Second, the social structure that evolved from this pressure is the dominance hierarchy. Third, primates that live in large groups with complex dominance hierarchies also show greater neocortical development, and concomitantly greater cognitive capacity. These facts suggest that the necessity of reasoning effectively about dominance hierarchies left an indelible (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Human evolution: Emergence of the group-self.Vilmos Csányi - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):755-756.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the dangers of oversimulation.Gergely Csibra & György Gergely - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):127-128.
    Barresi & Moore fail to provide a satisfactory account for the development of social understanding because of (1) their ambiguous characterization of the relationship between the intentional schema and shared intentional activities, (2) their underestimation of the representational capacities of infants, and (3) their overreliance on the simulationist assumption that understanding others is tantamount to sharing their experience.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The place of cognition in human evolution.Alan Costall - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):755-755.
  • Social versus ecological intelligence.Marina Cords - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):151-151.
  • Science, objectivity and moral values.Alberto Cordero - 1992 - Science & Education 1 (1):49-70.
  • From mouth to hand: Gesture, speech, and the evolution of right-handedness.Michael C. Corballis - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (2):199-208.
    The strong predominance of right-handedness appears to be a uniquely human characteristic, whereas the left-cerebral dominance for vocalization occurs in many species, including frogs, birds, and mammals. Right-handedness may have arisen because of an association between manual gestures and vocalization in the evolution of language. I argue that language evolved from manual gestures, gradually incorporating vocal elements. The transition may be traced through changes in the function of Broca's area. Its homologue in monkeys has nothing to do with vocal control, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Whence the motive for collaboration?John Collier - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):517-518.
  • Symbolic invention: The missing (computational) link?Andy Clark - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):753-754.
  • A natural history of the mind: A guide for cognitive science.Thomas L. Clarke - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):754-755.
  • The ontological status of intentional states: Nailing folk psychology to its perch.Paul M. Churchland - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):507.
  • Dennett' instrumentalism: A frog at the bottom of the mug.Patricia Smith Churchland - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):358-359.
  • An ambiguity.Jennifer Church - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):126-127.
    The difference between first and third person information may be thought of as a difference in either informationalcontentor informationalmodality. Each option faces some problems. I try to sort out some of these issues and raise a question about the explanatory force of the notion of a schema.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Précis of How monkeys see the world.Dorothy L. Cheney & Robert M. Seyfarth - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):135-147.
  • Characterizing the mind of another species.Dorothy L. Cheney & Robert M. Seyfarth - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):172-182.
  • Classification of deceptive behavior according to levels of cognitive complexity.Suzanne Chevalier-Skolnikoff - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):249-251.
  • Another “Just So” story: How the leopardguarders spot.Dorothy Cheney & Robert Seyfarth - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):506.
  • Archaeology and the cognitive sciences in the study of human evolution.Philip G. Chase - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):752-753.
  • The Return of the Arbitrary: Peikoff's Trinity, Binswanger's Inferno, Unwanted Possibilities—and a Parrot for President.Robert L. Campbell - 2019 - Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 19 (1):83-134.
    Leonard Peikoff brought into Objectivist epistemology the doctrine that what is asserted arbitrarily cannot be true or false. In 2008 the author gave a detailed critique of the doctrine; it has not received a published response. But there have been restatements by Harry Binswanger, Ben Bayer, and Gregory Salmieri. Their re-presentations do not refute any old arguments; their new arguments make the doctrine worse. The doctrine is being used to justify ignoring known possibilities, and to “prove” that the current president (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Toward the next generation in data quality: A new survey of primate tactical deception.R. W. Byrne & A. Whiten - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):267-273.
  • Hierarchical levels of imitation.R. W. Byrne - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):516-517.
  • Looking inside monkey minds: Milestone or millstone.Gordon M. Burghardt - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):150-151.
  • Anecdotes and critical anthropomorphism.Gordon M. Burghardt - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):248-249.
  • Language and its role in understanding intentional relations: Research tool or mechanism of development?Nancy Budwig & Michael Bamberg - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):125-126.
    In our commentary we elaborate on Barresi & Moore's use of language as a tool. In particular, we highlight the importance of cognitive linguistic research with its emphasis on the relation between morpnosyntax and intentional schemes. We also speculate about how language itself might play a role in children's integration of first and third person knowledge.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Do we “acquire” culture or vice versa?Jerome Bruner - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):515-516.
  • Mimetic culture and modern sports: A synthesis.Bruce Bridgeman & Margarita Azmitia - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):751-752.
  • Brains + programs = minds.Bruce Bridgeman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):427-428.
  • When is a pattern a pattern?Marc N. Branch - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):123-124.
  • Social-emotional and auto-operational roots of cultural (peer) learning.Stein Braten - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):515-515.
  • “Pop science” versus understanding the emergence of the modern mind.C. Loring Brace - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):750-751.
  • Towards a new image of culture in wild chimpanzees?Christophe Boesch - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):514-515.
  • New elements of a theory of mind in wild chimpanzees.Christophe Boesch - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):149-150.