Results for ' Musement'

36 found
Order:
  1.  25
    Musement: The activity of the brain’s default mode network.Antonio Duarte - 2020 - Semiotica 2020 (233):145-158.
    The main purpose of this article is to identify the inner human activity Peirce calls musement with the mental processes that arise through the workings of the brain’s default mode network. This network is a specific, recently anatomically defined brain system, which is most active when individuals are not focused on the external environment. In doing so, musement, which was defined by Peirce over a hundred years ago, will finally be situated within what today we understand as its (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Le musement, de Peirce à Lacan.Michel Balat - 1992 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 46.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Le musement de Peirce à Lacan.Balat Michel - 1992 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 46.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  62
    Musement as Listening: Daoist Perspectives on Peirce.Michael L. Raposa - 2012 - Journal of Chinese Philosophy 39 (2):207-221.
    Certain Daoist ideas explored here are compared with features of Peirce's philosophy, supplying a helpful perspective on the latter. In particular, I examine Zhuangzi's instruction about “listening” with one's spirit, along with certain discussions of “listening energy” drawn from texts dealing with the Daoist martial arts. I argue that Daoist “listening” and Peirce's concept of “musement” are both to be regarded as a disciplined form of attentiveness. By attending to no predetermined thing, a person thus disciplined is “ready” for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  34
    "Musement on the Whole"... An Attitude Toward Space.R. Patton Howell & Richard Dale McBride - 1981 - Semiotics:399-414.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  57
    Peirce’s Musement in Joyce’s Ulysses.Mary Libertin - 1994 - American Journal of Semiotics 11 (3/4):61-85.
    Charles Peirce's semiotics explains James Joyce's Ulysses' cognitive process, as it demonstrates triadic rather than dyadic representation. Joyce parodies the "foolhardy" laws of narrative (Gerard Genette) found in Proust by using mediating representation found in Peircean semiotics, which begins with the "play of musement," otherwise known as abduction (a form of induction). The three part sequence of musement (abduction, deduction, and induction) provides a means of understanding the three-part structure of Ulysses.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  27
    Peirce on Musement.Elizabeth F. Cooke - 2018 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 10 (2).
    An apparent tension persists in Peirce’s philosophy between the purpose-driven nature of inquiry, destined to achieve truth in the long run, on the one hand, and, on the other hand, the fact that inquiry depends upon musement (or the free play of ideas), which is purposeless. If there is no purpose in musement then it would appear there is no rational self-control in musement, and thus, irrationality lies at the center of Peirce’s theory of inquiry. I argue (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  40
    Art, religion and musement.Michael L. Raposa - 1984 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 42 (4):427-437.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  27
    Peirce’s Musement in Joyce’s Ulysses.Mary Libertin - 1994 - American Journal of Semiotics 11 (3/4):61-85.
  10.  13
    Preface: The Play of Musement.Jamin Pelkey & Geoffrey Ross Owens - 2017 - Semiotics:v-viii.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  9
    The Humble Argument is Musement on God's Great Argument.David Rohr - 2019 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 55 (4):429-453.
    C.S. Peirce's "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God" [NA] has always baffled its readers. Its publishing editor needed to ask, "[W]hat, then, precisely, is your neglected argument?", and EP 2's editors observe that "[t]his is one of Peirce's most enigmatic writings". First-time readers will likely concur with the underwhelmed theologian who told Michael Raposa that NA "ought to remain neglected". Early Peirce scholars did neglect the essay, regarding it as an "anomalous sideshow to Peirce's more important concern with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  72
    Abduction and the Origin of “Musement”: Peirce’s “Neglected Argument for the Reality of God”.Elizabeth Salas - 2009 - International Philosophical Quarterly 49 (4):459-471.
    This paper is an evaluation of C. S. Peirce’s late essay “A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God”, based on the two logical values that he calls “productiveness” and “security.” After reviewing the unique logical form of “abduction” and noting that it is a formal fallacy—and so enjoys less “security” than deduction or induction—I turn to the extraordinary case of abduction that is found in “A Neglected Argument.” I argue that the productiveness of the Neglected Argument is found in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  13
    Design Thinking as Play of Musement.Román Esqueda - 2017 - Semiotics:95-104.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Semiotics 2017: The Play of Musement.Jamin Pelkey & Geoffrey Ross Owens Pelkey & Owens (ed.) - 2017 - Puebla - Mexico: Semiotic Society of America.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  11
    Intentionally Going Through Percolations of Mazes - Weaving Together the Play of Musement and the Logic of Abduction Within Processes of Creation.Tiago da Costa E. Silva - forthcoming - Semiotics:83-101.
  16.  30
    The Varieties of Abductive Experience.Antonio Duarte - 2022 - Human Review. International Humanities Review / Revista Internacional de Humanidades 11 (1):23-36.
    Following the Peirce’s proposal drawn in the Neglected Argument, here we focus on the equivalence, from the generative and methodological point of view, of what we will call the religious and scientific abductive experiences. To articulate these connections, we also rely on William James's Gifford Lectures collected under the title The Varieties of Religious Experience. Moreover, we study extensively the universality of the Musement which is related to the mental processes that lead to the generation of the most creative (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  96
    Dewey's art as experience : The psychological background.Richard Shusterman - 2010 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 44 (1):pp. 26-43.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Dewey's Art as ExperienceThe Psychological BackgroundRichard Shusterman (bio)IThe year 2009 marks the 150th anniversary of John Dewey's birth and also the 75th anniversary of the publication of his aesthetic masterpiece Art as Experience—a book that has been extremely influential within the field of aesthetics, not only in philosophical aesthetics and aesthetic education but also in the arts themselves.1 I am honored to commemorate this double Deweyan anniversary with an (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18.  27
    Do not Block the Path of Inquiry!Wendy Wheeler - 2008 - American Journal of Semiotics 24 (1-3):171-187.
    Drawing on biosemiotic theory and the Peircean idea of ‘abduction’, I shall propose the idea of a layered structure of bio / semiotic evolution, in which humanknowledge is systemic and recursive — and thus emergent both from what is forgotten and from earlier evolutionary strata. I will argue that abductions are those processes by which we move creatively between often unacknowledged types of knowledge which are rooted in our natural and cultural evolutionary past (e.g., unconscious, preconscious, or tacit knowledge; knowledge (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19. The Being of Nature: Dewey, Buchler, and the Prospect for an Eco-Ontology.Thomas Alexander - 2010 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 46 (4):544-569.
    American philosophy has been dominated by the theme of "Nature."1 From Edwards to Emerson to Dewey to Dennett, American thought has variously invoked Nature. But to articulate a philosophy of Nature is not thereby to espouse a form of "naturalism." In fact, philosophies undertaken in the name of "naturalism" seem to have a different temperament than those that begin with the thought of Nature as such. As a theme, "Nature" invites an expansive mood for reflection, while "naturalism" sounds constrictive and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  47
    The Structure of C. S. Peirce's Neglected Argument for the Reality of God: A Critical Assessment.ClantonJ Caleb - forthcoming - .
    Despite the attention it has received in recent years, C. S. Peirce's so-called neglected argument for God's reality remains somewhat obscure. The aim of this essay is to clarify the basic structure of Peirce's three-part argument and to show how it falls prey to several objections. I argue that his overall argument is ultimately unsuccessful in demonstrating the reality of God, even if it provides some degree of warrant for the belief in God's reality to those who are uncontrollably drawn (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  30
    On the Logic of Idealism and Peirce’s Neglected Argument.Richard M. Martin - 1979 - Idealistic Studies 9 (1):22-32.
    The N.A., as Peirce somewhat affectionately called it, consists of a “nest of three arguments for the Reality of God.” The first arises from “Musement” and is perhaps best described in terms of the psychology of discovery. Yet musement “inevitably” leads to “the hypothesis of God’s Reality.” Thus this, the “Humble Argument,” then gives way to the N.A. proper, which is in part reminiscent of the traditional argument from design. Also every human heart “will be ravished by the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  2
    Aesthetic experience and the neurobiology of inquiry.Jay Schulkin - 2006 - In John R. Shook & Joseph Margolis (eds.), A Companion to Pragmatism. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 361–368.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Aesthetics Musical Syntax, Discrepancy and Activation Probability, Expectations, and Learning Dopamine, Discrepancy and the Prediction of Reward Musement and the Play of Ideas Conclusion.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  46
    The Vagueness of the Muse—The Logic of Peirce’s Humble Argument for the Reality of God.Cassiano Terra Rodrigues - 2017 - Sophia 56 (2):163-182.
    Published in 1908, C.S. Peirce’s ‘A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God’ is one of his most difficult articles. Presenting a peculiar entanglement of scientific method and theology, it sketches a ‘humble’ argument for the reality—and not the existence—of God for Musers, that is, those who pursue the activity he calls ‘Musement’. In Musement, Peirce claims, we can achieve a kind of perception of the intertwinement of the three universes of experience: of feeling, of brute fact, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  7
    Theosemiotic: Religion, Reading, and the Gift of Meaning by Michael L. Raposa.Brandon Daniel-Hughes - 2021 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 57 (2):292-295.
    Michael Raposa's long career as a preeminent interpreter of Peirce's writings on religion has taken a surprising turn and he has done what Peirce, in his most famous essays from 1877–78, suggested could not be done. Though Peirce early on cautioned against construing thought as having any legitimate function beyond the fixation of belief and the production of "thought at rest," and warned explicitly against thinking as a form of amusement,1 throughout Theosemiotic Raposa highlights an additional dimension of thought as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  30
    A sketch of Peirce’s Firstness and its significance to art.Dinda L. Gorlée - 2009 - Sign Systems Studies 37 (1-2):205-268.
    This essay treats the growth and development of Charles S. Peirce’s three categories, particularly studying the qualities of Peirce’s Firstness, a basic formula of “airy-nothingness” (CP: 6.455) serving as fragment to Secondness and Thirdness. The categories of feeling, willing, and knowing are not separate entities but work in interaction within the three interpretants. Interpretants are triadomaniac elements through the adopted, revised, or changed habits of belief. In works of art, the first glance of Firstness arouses the spontaneous responses of (...), expressing emotions without the struggle and resistance of factual Secondness, and not yet involving logical Thirdness. The essential qualities of a loose or vague word, color, or sound give the fugitive meanings in Firstness. The flavor, brush, timbre, color, point, line, tone or touch of the First qualities of an aesthetic object is too small a base to build the logic of aesthetic judgment. The genesis art is explained by Peirce’s undegeneracy growing into group and individual interpretants and building into the passages and whole forms of double and single forms of degeneracy. The survey of the flash of Firstness is exemplified in a variety of artworks in language, music, sculpture, painting, and film. This analysis is a preliminary aid to further studies of primary Firstness in the arts. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  18
    Visand Peirce'i Esmasuse kategooriast ja selle tahendusest kunstidele. Kokkuvõte.Dinda L. Gorlée - 2009 - Sign Systems Studies 37 (1/2):269-269.
    This essay treats the growth and development of Charles S. Peirce’s three categories, particularly studying the qualities of Peirce’s Firstness, a basic formula of “airy-nothingness” serving as fragment to Secondness and Thirdness. The categories of feeling, willing, and knowing are not separate entities but work in interaction within the three interpretants. Interpretants are triadomaniac elements through the adopted, revised, or changed habits of belief. In works of art, the first glance of Firstness arouses the spontaneous responses of musement, expressing (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  10
    Garroni, the late Peirce, and the issue of creativity.Giacinto Davide Guagnano & Eduardo Grillo - 2020 - Semiotica 2020 (235):165-184.
    The iconic and diagrammatic features of abduction, as expressed in Peirce’s works after 1890, allow one to re-read the Kantian concept of schema. By means of this new reading, it is possible to consider the dynamics between legality and creative acts, which, according to Emilio Garroni, keep cultures alive. This process can be analysed by a semiotic theory that could combine the features of Kant’s Aesthetic Judgment (as an answer to schema’s problems) and Peirce’s last theory of abduction. In this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  12
    Abduction as Regulation: An Input from Epigenetics: Peirce Essay Prize Winner, 2018.Simon Levesque - 2019 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 55 (2):119-137.
    The comprehension of abduction put forward in this essay is compatible with the contemporary biosemiotics consensus. Moreover, it coincides with the evolutionary framework Peirce has developed in its time.Biosemiotics is being developed since the 1980’s and is characterized by a growing interest for its body of works. It is now a major field in general semiotics throughout the world. We owe to Thomas A. Sebeok to have paved the way for this new science to emerge and develop from a synthesis (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  19
    The Semiotic Structure of Peirce's Humble Argument, with Brief Remarks on Different Kinds of Abducent Signs.Gesche Linde - 2018 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 54 (4):515.
    Peirce's "Neglected Argument" uses more or less standard logical vocabulary, such as "argument," "retroduction," "premise," "conclusion," and "hypothesis." There cannot be any doubt, however, that the musement process as he characterizes it must be regarded as a semiotic process—that is, one that relates a sign to an object by way of forming an interpretant. This assumption follows from the simple observation that, according to Peirce, all processes of thought are semiotically structured. What is more, Peirce quite often uses the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  61
    The normative sciences at work and play.Charles G. Conway - 2008 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (2):pp. 288-311.
    This essay posits that Peirce puts the Normative Sciences implicitly to work at three junctures of his Neglected Argument for the Reality of God (NARG): (1) in the distinguishing of musement from play; (2) in the generation of the Humble Argument via musement; and (3) in the portrayal of the Humble Argument as the first stage of an inquiry into its confirmability. Then, focus shifts to Peirce’s notions of the initiating “play” and the “plausibility” of the God-hypothesis, as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  39
    Charles S. Peirce and the Neglected Argument for the Reality of God.Jaime Nubiola - 2022 - Human Review. International Humanities Review / Revista Internacional de Humanidades 11 (1):11-21.
    This paper aims, above all, to invite a direct reading of the article that Charles S. Peirce published in 1908 with the title “A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God.” More than a century after its original publication, that article by Peirce has not lost its relevance: its careful reading continues to provide a lot to think about. To this end, my presentation is organized in six sections: 1) introduction; 2) presentation of “A Neglected Argument for the Reality of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  18
    Significs, Pragmatism and Mother-Sense.Susan Petrilli - 2023 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 15 (1).
    Welby’s correspondence with Peirce began with his review of What is Meaning? (1903), a contribution not only to spreading Peirce’s later thinking, but also to reproposing Welby’s “significs.” This is encounter between the pragmatist Peirce’s approach to semiotic and Welby’s significs oriented by mother-sense. A dialogue between two conceptions of meaning which, notwithstanding differences, meet in a participative contribution to constructing the sign sciences – from Peirce to semiotics, from Welby to significs. Their focus does not only concern signs but (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  10
    Who’s, What’s, I Don’t Know.Lucio Privitello - 2018 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 10 (1).
    This study is a three-part play of musement on a few details in the potentially infinite landscape of Umberto Eco’s turn to, relations with, and adaptations of Pragmatism. This three-part guess was product of an abandoned first guess-attempt entitled: “Who’s on First(ness)?” The present title ensued naturally, and with some laughter, in recalling and using the play on words and names made famous by Abbott and Costello. Section 1 will mention two uncles of American Pragmatism. Section 2 will engage (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  51
    A fallible groom in the religious thought of C.s. Peirce – a centenary revisitation.Jeffrey H. Sims - 2008 - Sophia 47 (2):91-105.
    Under the general tutelage of Kant, Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) introduced American pragmatism to yet another philosophical dialectic: between a neglected transcendental instinct and earthly authorities. The dialectic became Peirce’s response to various evolutionary schemes in the 19th century. Guided by the recollected voices of Socrates, Jesus, St. John, Anselm, and Kant, as well as his own brand of pragmatism, Peirce eventually developed a “Neglected Argument for the Reality of God” a century ago, in 1908. Here, Peirce endorsed a more (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  20
    Playing peripatos: Creativity and abductive inference in religion, art and war.Katya Mandoki - 2019 - Semiotica 2019 (230):369-387.
    Peirce proposed the concept of abductive inference to inquire into the generation of new hypotheses and defined it as another term for pragmatism, no less (Admitting, then, that the question of Pragmatism is the question of Abduction, let us consider it under that form. What is good abduction? What should an explanatory hypothesis be to be worthy to rank as a hypothesis? Of course, it must explain the facts. But what other conditions ought it to fulfill to be good? The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. How Can “The Play of Signs and The Signs of Play” Become an Attractive Model for Dealing with Eidetic and Empirical Research?William Gomes - 2017 - In Jamin Pelkey & Geoffrey Ross Owens Pelkey & Owens (ed.), Semiotics 2017: The Play of Musement. Puebla - Mexico: Semiotic Society of America. pp. 1-19.
    The title of this presentation encompasses three issues: (1) an enigmatic theme (the play of signs and signs of play); (2) a model of doing something, such as unraveling a puzzle; and (3) a methodology dealing with a probable case. Considering that the order of analysis runs in the opposite direction to the order of experience, my first task is to reverse the title. Then, its three parts become: (1) an eidetic and empirical conjunction that implies a taste for evidence; (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark