Results for ' predicative descriptions'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Descriptions as predicates.Delia Graff Fara - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 102 (1):1-42.
    Although Strawson’s main aim in “On Referring” was to argue that definite descriptions can be used referentially – that is, “to mention or refer to some individual person or single object . . . , in the course of doing what we should normally describe as making a statement about that person [or] object” (1950, p. 320) – he denied that definite descriptions are always used referentially. The description in ‘Napoleon was the greatest French soldier’ is not used (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  2. Descriptions: Predicates or quantifiers?Berit Brogaard - 2007 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85 (1):117 – 136.
    In this paper I revisit the main arguments for a predicate analysis of descriptions in order to determine whether they do in fact undermine Russell's theory. I argue that while the arguments without doubt provide powerful evidence against Russell's original theory, it is far from clear that they tell against a quantificational account of descriptions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  3.  33
    The descriptive content of names as predicate modifiers.Olga Poller - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (9):2329-2360.
    In this paper I argue that descriptive content associated with a proper name can serve as a truth-conditionally relevant adjunct and be an additional contribution of the name to the truth-conditions. Definite descriptions the so-and-so associated by speakers with a proper name can be used as qualifying prepositional phrases as so-and-so, so sentences containing a proper name NN is doing something could be understood as NN is doing something as NN (which means as so-and-so). Used as an adjunct, the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. Russell's theory of descriptions vs. the predicative analysis: A reply to Graff.Berit Brogaard - unknown
    I. Descriptions in Predicative Position The predicative analysis and Russell’s theory part company when it comes to the argument structure assigned to sentences like (1). (1) Washington is the greatest French soldier. On a standard Russellian analysis, (1) has the following (a) logical form and (b) truth conditions.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  44
    Predicates: External description or neural reality?Michael A. Arbib - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (3):285-286.
    Hurford argues that propositions of the form PREDICATE(x) represent conceptual structures that predate language and that can be explicated in terms of neural structure. I disagree, arguing that such predicates are descriptions of limited aspects of brain function, not available as representations in the brain to be exploited in the frog or monkey brain and turned into language in the human.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  39
    The predicate calculus with extra-logical constants as an instrument of semantic description.Olgierd Adrian Wojtasiewicz - 1978 - Studia Logica 37 (1):103 - 114.
  7.  78
    A predicate logic based on indefinite description and two notions of identity.Robert A. Alps & Robert C. Neveln - 1981 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22 (3):251-263.
  8. Undefined descriptive predicates.Gustav Bergmann - 1947 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 8 (1):55-82.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  10
    Undefined Descriptive Predicates.Arthur Francis Smullyan & Gustav Bergmann - 1948 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):121.
  10. Names Are Predicates.Delia Graff Fara - 2015 - Philosophical Review 124 (1):59-117.
    One reason to think that names have a predicate-type semantic value is that they naturally occur in count-noun positions: ‘The Michaels in my building both lost their keys’; ‘I know one incredibly sharp Cecil and one that's incredibly dull’. Predicativism is the view that names uniformly occur as predicates. Predicativism flies in the face of the widely accepted view that names in argument position are referential, whether that be Millian Referentialism, direct-reference theories, or even Fregean Descriptivism. But names are predicates (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  11.  41
    Nature and our descriptions of it: Predicate, function, symmetry.Sunny Auyang - manuscript
    Objectivity – to account for nature as it is, free from subjective biases – is a standard of science and commonsense. However, postmodernists distort it into God’s perspective. Because God’s position is beyond human reach, they dismiss objectivity as a sham and relegate all science and knowledge to be nothing but social constructions relative to specific cultures. Their forced choice between two polar options – an illusory absolute stance and arbitrary cultural fashions – is unwarranted. Objectivity has clear meaning within (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  27
    Concerning undefined descriptive predicates of higher levels.Julius R. Weinberg - 1954 - Mind 63 (251):338-344.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  27
    Erratum to: The descriptive content of names as predicate modifiers.Olga Poller - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (9):2361-2361.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  9
    Polynomial rewritings from expressive Description Logics with closed predicates to variants of Datalog.Shqiponja Ahmetaj, Magdalena Ortiz & Mantas Šimkus - 2020 - Artificial Intelligence 280 (C):103220.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15. Descriptions.Stephen Neale - 1990 - MIT Press.
    When philosophers talk about descriptions, usually they have in mind singular definite descriptions such as ‘the finest Greek poet’ or ‘the positive square root of nine’, phrases formed with the definite article ‘the’. English also contains indefinite descriptions such as ‘a fine Greek poet’ or ‘a square root of nine’, phrases formed with the indefinite article ‘a’ (or ‘an’); and demonstrative descriptions (also known as complex demonstratives) such as ‘this Greek poet’ and ‘that tall woman’, formed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   202 citations  
  16. Further Steps towards a Theory of Descriptions as Predicates.Delia Graff Fara - 2016 - Analytic Philosophy 57 (2):91-109.
    Descriptions are predicates. Here, I'll take this to mean either of two basically equivalent things: that they have extensions as their semantic values, sets of entities, in the broadest sense; or that they have type-〈e,t〉 functions as their semantic values, functions from entities, in the broadest sense, to truth values. An entity in the broadest sense is anything that can be the subject of a first-order predication. Examples are individuals, pluralities, masses, and kinds. Here I'm including entities in this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  23
    Second level descriptive predicates.L. E. Palmieri - 1955 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 16 (4):505-511.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  10
    On Descriptional Propositions in Ibn Sīnā: Elements for a Logical Analysis.Shahid Rahman & Mohammad Zarepour - 2019 - In Mojtaba Mojtahedi, Shahid Rahman & MohammadSaleh Zarepour (eds.), Mathematics, Logic, and their Philosophies: Essays in Honour of Mohammad Ardeshir. Springer. pp. 411-431.
    Employing Constructive Type Theory Constructive Type Theory, we provide a logical analysis of[aut]Ibn SīnāIbn Sīnā’sIbn Sīnā descriptional propositions. Compared to its rivals, our analysis is more faithful to the grammatical subject-predicate structure of propositions and can better reflect the morphological features of the verbs that extend time to intervals. We also study briefly the logical structure of some fallacious inferences that are discussed by Ibn Sīnā. The CTT-framework makes the fallacious nature of these inferences apparent.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  33
    Weather predicates, binding, and radical contextualism.Paul Elbourne - 2020 - Mind and Language 37 (1):56-72.
    The implicit content indicating location associated with “raining” and other weather predicates is a definite description meaning “the location occupied by x,” where the individual variable “x” can be referential or bound. This position has deleterious consequences for certain varieties of radical contextualism.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  30
    Ontology as a natural extension of predicate calculus with identity equipped with description.Toshiharu Waragai - 1990 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 7 (5):23-40.
  21. Verification and descriptive predicates.L. E. Palmieri - 1954 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 15 (4):548-550.
  22.  40
    Minimal predicates, fixed-points, and definability.Johan van Benthem - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):696-712.
    Minimal predicates P satisfying a given first-order description φ(P) occur widely in mathematical logic and computer science. We give an explicit first-order syntax for special first-order ‘PIA conditions’ φ(P) which guarantees unique existence of such minimal predicates. Our main technical result is a preservation theorem showing PIA-conditions to be expressively complete for all those first-order formulas that are preserved under a natural model-theoretic operation of ‘predicate intersection’. Next, we show how iterated predicate minimization on PIA-conditions yields a language MIN(FO) equal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  23.  86
    Higher level descriptive predicates.L. E. Palmieri - 1955 - Mind 64 (256):544-547.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  65
    Descriptions and Logical Form.Gary Ostertag - 2002 - In Dale Jacquette (ed.), A Companion to Philosophical Logic. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 177–193.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Preliminaries Descriptions and Quantification Descriptions and Predication Conclusion.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  92
    The Predicative Predicament.Anders J. Schoubye - 2016 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96 (3):571-595.
    The-Predicativism is the view that names are count nouns. For example, the meaning of the name ‘Louise’ is roughly the property of being called Louise. Moreover, proponents of this view maintain that names that are ostensibly in argument position of a predicate are covert definite descriptions. In recent years, The-Predicativism has acquired a number of new supporters, mainly Elbourne (), Matushansky (), and Fara (). And while it was pointed out by Kripke () that these kinds of views generally (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  26.  36
    Minimal Predicates. Fixed-Points, and Definability.Johan Van Benthem - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):696 - 712.
    Minimal predicates P satisfying a given first-order description ϕ(P) occur widely in mathematical logic and computer science. We give an explicit first-order syntax for special first-order 'PIA conditions' ϕ(P) which quarantees unique existence of such minimal predicates. Our main technical result is a preservation theorem showing PIA-conditions to be expressively complete for all those first-order formulas that are preserved under a natural model-theoretic operation of 'predicate intersection'. Next, we show how iterated predicate minimization on PIA-conditions yields a language MIN(FO) equal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  27. Existence Predicates.Friederike Moltmann - 2020 - Synthese 197 (1):311-335.
    Natural languages generally distinguishes among different existence predicates for different types of entities, such as English 'exist', 'occur', and 'obtain'. The paper gives an in-depth discussion and analysis of a range of existence predicates in natural language within the general project of descriptive metaphysics, or more specifically ‘natural language ontology’.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28. Carnap’s Theory of Descriptions and its Problems.Jan Heylen - 2010 - Studia Logica 94 (3):355-380.
    Carnap's theory of descriptions was restricted in two ways. First, the descriptive conditions had to be non-modal. Second, only primitive predicates or the identity predicate could be used to predicate something of the descriptum . The motivating reasons for these two restrictions that can be found in the literature will be critically discussed. Both restrictions can be relaxed, but Carnap's theory can still be blamed for not dealing adequately with improper descriptions.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  29. Descriptions with adverbs of quantification.Delia Graff Fara - 2006 - Philosophical Issues 16 (1):65–87.
    In “Descriptions as Predicates” (Fara 2001) I argued that definite and indefinite descriptions should be given a uniform semantic treatment as predicates rather than as quantifier phrases. The aim of the current paper is to clarify and elaborate one of the arguments for the descriptions-aspredicates view, one that concerns the interaction of descriptions with adverbs of quantification.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  30.  78
    Interpreting plural predication: homogeneity and non-maximality.Manuel Križ & Benjamin Spector - 2020 - Linguistics and Philosophy 44 (5):1131-1178.
    Plural definite descriptions across many languages display two well-known properties. First, they can give rise to so-called non-maximal readings, in the sense that they ‘allow for exceptions’. Second, while they tend to have a quasi-universal quantificational force in affirmative sentences, they tend to be interpreted existentially in the scope of negation. Building on previous works, we offer a theory in which sentences containing plural definite expressions trigger a family of possible interpretations, and where general principles of language use account (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  31.  37
    Definite descriptions, misdescriptions and semantic content: different ways to solve a tricky puzzle.Justina Diaz Legaspe - 2009 - Análisis Filosófico 29 (2):159-166.
    Michael Devitt claims that the predicative material that constitutes complex referential expressions makes a semantic contribution to the proposition expressed. He thus deviates from direct referentialism, according to which every referential expression -either simple or complex- contributes just with an object to the proposition expressed, leaving the predicative material out of the semantic content. However, when dealing with misdescriptions, Devitt has suggested a pragmatic way out: the audience can understand what the speaker is referring to even if the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Descriptions which have grown capital letters.Brian Rabern - 2015 - Mind and Language 30 (3):292-319.
    Almost entirely ignored in the linguistic theorising on names and descriptions is a hybrid form of expression which, like definite descriptions, begin with 'the' but which, like proper names, are capitalised and seem to lack descriptive content. These are expressions such as the following, 'the Holy Roman Empire', 'the Mississippi River', or 'the Space Needle'. Such capitalised descriptions are ubiquitous in natural language, but to which linguistic categories do they belong? Are they simply proper names? Or are (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  33.  49
    Definite descriptions: Language, logic, and elimination.Norbert Gratzl - 2009 - In Hieke Alexander & Leitgeb Hannes (eds.), Reduction, Abstraction, Analysis. Ontos Verlag. pp. 355.
    Definite descriptions are in the focus of philosophical discussion at least since Russell's famous paper "On Denoting". We present in this paper a logic with descriptions in Russell's spirit. The formulation, however, is closely related to Schütte's development of predicate logic, i.e. the formulation of the calculus uses positive- and negative-parts. With respect to this slightly more sophisticated formulation it is possible to formalize Russell's convention that is originally stated in the metalanguage of his theory of descriptions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  8
    On the relative expressiveness of description logics and predicate logics.Alex Borgida - 1996 - Artificial Intelligence 82 (1-2):353-367.
  35. Two Treatments of Definite Descriptions in Intuitionist Negative Free Logic.Nils Kürbis - 2019 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 48 (4):299-317.
    Sentences containing definite descriptions, expressions of the form ‘The F’, can be formalised using a binary quantifier ι that forms a formula out of two predicates, where ιx[F, G] is read as ‘The F is G’. This is an innovation over the usual formalisation of definite descriptions with a term forming operator. The present paper compares the two approaches. After a brief overview of the system INFι of intuitionist negative free logic extended by such a quantifier, which was (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. Descriptions with adverbs of quantification.Delia Graff Fara - 2006 - Philosophical Issues, Volume 16: Philosophy of Language 16:65–87.
    In “Descriptions as Predicates” (Graff 2001) I argued that definite and indefinite descriptions should be given a uniform semantic treatment as predicates rather than as quantifier phrases. The aim of the current paper is to clarify and elaborate one of the arguments for the descriptions-as-predicates view, one that concerns the interaction of descriptions with adverbs of quantification.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. Plural Predication.Agustin Rayo - 2000 - Dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
    My thesis consists of three self-contained but interconnected papers. In the first one, 'Word and Objects', I assume that it is possible to quantify over absolutely everything, and show that certain English sentences containing collective predicates resist paraphrase in first-order languages and even in first-order languages enriched with plural quantifiers. To capture such sentences I develop a language containing plural predicates . ;The introduction of plural predicates leads to an extension of Quine's criterion of ontological commitment. I argue that theories (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. The neural basis of predicate-argument structure.James R. Hurford - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (3):261-283.
    Neural correlates exist for a basic component of logical formulae, PREDICATE(x). Vision and audition research in primates and humans shows two independent neural pathways; one locates objects in body-centered space, the other attributes properties, such as colour, to objects. In vision these are the dorsal and ventral pathways. In audition, similarly separable “where” and “what” pathways exist. PREDICATE(x) is a schematic representation of the brain's integration of the two processes of delivery by the senses of the location of an arbitrary (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  39. Sharvy's theory of definite descriptions revisited.Berit Brogaard - 2007 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88 (2):160–180.
    The paper revisits Sharvy's theory of plural definite descriptions. An alternative account of plural definite descriptions building on the ideas of plural quantification and non-distributive plural predication is developed. Finally, the alternative is extrapolated to account for generic uses of definite descriptions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40. Categorial Description: Some Contemporary Metaphysical Issues.Brian Carr - 1987 - Dissertation, University of Exeter (United Kingdom)
    Available from UMI in association with The British Library. ;A form of metaphysical inquiry is in this thesis both illustrated in detail and defended against the charge of issuing in statements which lack cognitive content. 'Categorial description' concerns the fundamental features of our conceptual scheme: the categories described are those of substance, accident, cause, space and time. ;Following Aristotle's distinction between primary and secondary substances, these two notions are addressed as equivalent to those individual or particular things and their kinds. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  49
    Indeterminate Descriptions.G. W. Fitch - 1984 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (2):257 - 276.
    One of the most important insights that Russell had in presenting his philosophy of language was his view of singular definite descriptions. Russell held that singular phrases of the form ‘the so-and-so’ should not be viewed as names, but rather incomplete symbols which can be said to have meaning only in a context. We should not represent the sentence The inventor of bifocals is bald.as a simple subject-predicate sentence of the form ‘Fa.’ but rather as a complex existential sentence. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  56
    Necessarily Coextensive Predicates and Reduction.Philip Stratton-Lake - 2018 - International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 8 (4):282-299.
    _ Source: _Page Count 18 Bart Streumer argues that all normative properties are descriptive properties. His first argument is based on the principle that necessarily coextensive predicates ascribe the same property, and the claim that there is a descriptive predicate that is necessarily coextensive with normative predicates. From this Streumer concludes that normative properties are identical with descriptive properties. I argue that, even if we accept, this conclusion does not follow. Normative properties could only be descriptive properties if there is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  41
    On the predicate logics of finite Kripke frames.D. Skvortsov - 1995 - Studia Logica 54 (1):79-88.
    In [Ono 1987] H. Ono put the question about axiomatizing the intermediate predicate logicLFin characterized by the class of all finite Kripke frames. It was established in [ Skvortsov 1988] thatLFin is not recursively axiomatizable. One can easily show that for any finite posetM, the predicate logic characterized byM is recursively axiomatizable, and its axiomatization can be constructed effectively fromM. Namely, the set of formulas belonging to this logic is recursively enumerable, since it is embeddable in the two-sorted classical predicate (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44.  19
    Descriptions in Mathematical Logic.Gerard R. Renardel De Lavalette - 1984 - Studia Logica 43 (3):281 - 294.
    After a discussion of the different treatments in the literature of vacuous descriptions, the notion of descriptor is slightly generalized to function descriptor Ⅎ $\overset \rightarrow \to{y}(x)$ , so as to form partial functions φ = Ⅎ $y(\overset \rightarrow \to{x}).A(\overset \rightarrow \to{x},y)$ which satisfy $\forall \overset \rightarrow \to{x}z(z=\phi \overset \rightarrow \to{x}\leftrightarrow \forall y(A(\overset \rightarrow \to{x},y)\leftrightarrow y=z))$ . We use (intuitionistic, classical or intermediate) logic with existence predicate, as introduced by D. S. Scott, to handle partial functions, and prove that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  7
    Definite descriptions and hybrid tense logic.Andrzej Indrzejczak & Michał Zawidzki - 2023 - Synthese 202 (3):1-29.
    We provide a version of first-order hybrid tense logic with predicate abstracts and definite descriptions as the only non-rigid terms. It is formalised by means of a tableau calculus working on sat-formulas. A particular theory of DD exploited here is essentially based on the approach of Russell, but with descriptions treated as genuine terms. However, the reductionist aspect of the Russellian approach is retained in several ways. Moreover, a special form of tense definite descriptions is formally developed. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Strawson's descriptive metaphysics.Hans Johann Https://Orcidorg909X Glock - 2012 - In Glock, Hans Johann . Strawson's Descriptive Metaphysics. In: Haaparanta, Leila; Koskinnen, Heikki J. Categories of Being. Essays on Metaphysics and Logic. New York: Oxford University Press, 391-419.
    Strawson's descriptive metaphysics was the first explicit and elaborate rehabilitation of metaphysics within the analytic tradition. This chapter discusses Strawson's contributions to metaphysics with a particular view to his conception of the nature of metaphysics-cum-ontology. This chapter first dwells on the background of Strawson's metaphysics. Next it introduces Strawson's idea of descriptive metaphysics and of connective analysis. Sections 3–8 discuss Strawson's main claims: self-conscious experience presupposes a distinction between experience and its mind-independent objects, objective particulars must be situated in a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  60
    Necessarily Coextensive Predicates and Reduction.Philip Stratton-Lake - 2018 - Brill.
    _ Source: _Page Count 18 Bart Streumer argues that all normative properties are descriptive properties. His first argument is based on the principle that necessarily coextensive predicates ascribe the same property, and the claim that there is a descriptive predicate that is necessarily coextensive with normative predicates. From this Streumer concludes that normative properties are identical with descriptive properties. I argue that, even if we accept, this conclusion does not follow. Normative properties could only be descriptive properties if there is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  15
    Review: Hisao Tanaka, On Limits of Sequences of Hyperarithmetical Functionals and Predicates; Tosiyuki Tugue, Hisao Tanaka, A Note on the Effective Descriptive Set Theory. [REVIEW]Stephen J. Garland - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):344-345.
  49.  41
    Some remarks on vague predicates.Josep-María Terricabras & Enric Trillas - 1988 - Theoria 4 (1):1-12.
    This paper has a very limited scope: it just presents some eIements which may introduce us into a wider investigation on vague predicates. Thus, webegin by pointing out our general conception of Iogic (as a descriptive science of linguistic phenomena). After that, we build up our approach by considering characteristic functions and by trying to make useful the model of logical extension which applies to classical quantifiers.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  37
    Descriptive As Ifs.Justin Bledin & Sadhwi Srinivas - 2023 - Linguistics and Philosophy 46 (1):87-134.
    This is the first part of a larger project that aims to develop a cross-categorical semantic account of a broad range of _as if_ constructions in English. In this paper, we focus on descriptive uses of _as if_ with regular truth-conditional content. The core proposal is that _as if_-phrases contribute hypothetical (_if_-like) and comparative (_as_-like) properties of situations, which are instantiated by an event, state, or larger situation when it resembles in some relevant respect its counterparts in selected stereotypical worlds (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000