Results for 'Elementary submodel'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  10
    An elementary submodel never preserved by skolem expansions.T. H. Payne - 1969 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 15 (26‐29):435-436.
  2.  22
    An elementary submodel never preserved by skolem expansions.T. H. Payne - 1969 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 15 (26-29):435-436.
  3. The real line in elementary submodels of set theory.Kenneth Kunen & Franklin D. Tall - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (2):683-691.
    Keywords: Elementary Submodel; Real Line; Order-Isomorphic.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  18
    On the Number of Elementary Submodels of an Unsuperstable Homogeneous Structure.Tapani Hyttinen & Saharon Shelah - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (3):354-358.
    We show that if M is a stable unsuperstable homogeneous structure, then for most κ ⩽ |M|, the number of elementary submodels of M of power κ is 2κ.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5.  7
    On Nonstructure of Elementary Submodels of an Unsuperstable Homogeneous Structure.Tapani Hyttinen - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (1):134-142.
    In the first part of this paper we let M be a stable homogeneous model and we prove a nonstructure theorem for the class of all elementary submodels of M, assuming that M is ‘unsuperstable’ and has Skolem functions. In the second part we assume that M is an unstable homogeneous model of large cardinality and we prove a nonstructure theorem for the class of all elementary submodels of M.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  77
    Applications of elementary submodels in general topology.Stefan Geschke - 2002 - Synthese 133 (1-2):31 - 41.
    Elementary submodels of some initial segment of the set-theoretic universe are useful in order to prove certain theorems in general topology as well as in algebra. As an illustration we give proofs of two theorems due to Arkhangelskii concerning cardinal invariants of compact spaces.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  27
    Compact spaces, elementary submodels, and the countable chain condition.Lúcia R. Junqueira, Paul Larson & Franklin D. Tall - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 144 (1-3):107-116.
    Given a space in an elementary submodel M of H, define XM to be X∩M with the topology generated by . It is established, using anti-large-cardinals assumptions, that if XM is compact and its regular open algebra is isomorphic to that of a continuous image of some power of the two-point discrete space, then X=XM. Assuming in addition, the result holds for any compact XM satisfying the countable chain condition.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  52
    A rank for the class of elementary submodels of a superstable homogeneous model.Tapani Hyttinen & Olivier Lessmann - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (4):1469-1482.
    We study the class of elementary submodels of a large superstable homogeneous model. We introduce a rank which is bounded in the superstable case, and use it to define a dependence relation which shares many (but not all) of the properties of forking in the first order case. The main difference is that we do not have extension over all sets. We also present an example of Shelah showing that extension over all sets may not hold for any dependence (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  9.  9
    A rank for the class of elementary submodels of a superstable homogeneous model.Tapani Hyttinen & Olivier Lessmann - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (4):1469-1482.
    We study the class of elementary submodels of a large superstable homogeneous model. We introduce a rank which is bounded in the superstable case, and use it to define a dependence relation which shares many (but not all) of the properties of forking in the first order case. The main difference is that we do not have extension over all sets. We also present an example of Shelah showing that extension over all sets may not hold for any dependence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10.  32
    Main gap for locally saturated elementary submodels of a homogeneous structure.Tapani Hyttinen & Saharon Shelah - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1286-1302.
    We prove a main gap theorem for locally saturated submodels of a homogeneous structure. We also study the number of locally saturated models, which are not elementarily embeddable into each other.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  6
    Main gap for locally saturated elementary submodels of a homogeneous structure.Tapani Hyttinen & Saharon Shelah - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1286-1302.
    We prove a main gap theorem for locally saturated submodels of a homogeneous structure. We also study the number of locally saturated models, which are not elementarily embeddable into each other.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  26
    A. V. Arkhangel′skiĭ. O moshchnosti bikompaktov c pervoĭ aksiomoĭ schetnosti. Dok-lady Akademii Nauk SSSR, vol. 187 , pp. 967–970. - A. V. Arhangel′skiĭ. On the cardinality of bicompacta satisfying the first axiom of countability. English translation by Z. Skalsky of the preceding. Soviet mathematics, vol. 10 , pp. 951–955. - R. Pol. Short proofs of two theorems on cardinality of topological spaces. English with Russian summary. Bulletin de l'Académie Polonaise des Sciences Série des sciences mathématiques, astronomique et physiques, vol. 22 , pp. 1245–1249. - Alan Dow. An introduction to applications of elementary submodels to topology. Topology proceedings , vol. 13 , pp. 17–72. [REVIEW]Zoltan T. Balogh - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (4):537-537.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  25
    On Cofinal Submodels and Elementary Interstices.Roman Kossak & James H. Schmerl - 2012 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 53 (3):267-287.
    We prove a number of results concerning the variety of first-order theories and isomorphism types of pairs of the form $(N,M)$ , where $N$ is a countable recursively saturated model of Peano Arithmetic and $M$ is its cofinal submodel. We identify two new isomorphism invariants for such pairs. In the strongest result we obtain continuum many theories of such pairs with the fixed greatest common initial segment of $N$ and $M$ and fixed lattice of interstructures $K$ , such that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  22
    Stably embedded submodels of Henselian valued fields.Pierre Touchard - 2023 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 63 (3):279-315.
    We show a transfer principle for the property that all types realised in a given elementary extension are definable. It can be written as follows: a Henselian valued field is stably embedded in an elementary extension if and only if its value group is stably embedded in its corresponding extension, its residue field is stably embedded in its corresponding extension, and the extension of valued fields satisfies a certain algebraic condition. We show for instance that all types over (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  52
    Elementary embeddings and infinitary combinatorics.Kenneth Kunen - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (3):407-413.
    One of the standard ways of postulating large cardinal axioms is to consider elementary embeddings,j, from the universe,V, into some transitive submodel,M. See Reinhardt–Solovay [7] for more details. Ifjis not the identity, andκis the first ordinal moved byj, thenκis a measurable cardinal. Conversely, Scott [8] showed that wheneverκis measurable, there is suchjandM. If we had assumed, in addition, that, thenκwould be theκth measurable cardinal; in general, the wider we assumeMto be, the largerκmust be.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  16.  7
    Self-Embeddings of Models of Arithmetic; Fixed Points, Small Submodels, and Extendability.Saeideh Bahrami - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-23.
    In this paper we will show that for every cutIof any countable nonstandard model$\mathcal {M}$of$\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{1}$, eachI-small$\Sigma _{1}$-elementary submodel of$\mathcal {M}$is of the form of the set of fixed points of some proper initial self-embedding of$\mathcal {M}$iffIis a strong cut of$\mathcal {M}$. Especially, this feature will provide us with some equivalent conditions with the strongness of the standard cut in a given countable model$\mathcal {M}$of$ \mathrm {I}\Sigma _{1} $. In addition, we will find some criteria for extendability (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  14
    Unidimensional modules: uniqueness of maximal non-modular submodels.Anand Pillay & Philipp Rothmaler - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 62 (2):175-181.
    We characterize the non-modular models of a unidimensional first-order theory of modules as the elementary submodels of its prime pure-injective model. We show that in case the maximal non-modular submodel of a given model splits off this is true for every such submodel, and we thus obtain a cancellation result for this situation. Although the theories in question always have models whose maximal non-modular submodel do split off, they may as well have others where they don't. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  23
    As an abstract elementary class.John T. Baldwin, Paul C. Eklof & Jan Trlifaj - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 149 (1-3):25-39.
    In this paper we study abstract elementary classes of modules. We give several characterizations of when the class of modules A with is abstract elementary class with respect to the notion that M1 is a strong submodel M2 if the quotient remains in the given class.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  19.  18
    Finitely generated submodels of an uncountably categorical homogeneous structure.Tapani Hyttinen - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (1):77.
    We generalize the result of non-finite axiomatizability of totally categorical first-order theories from elementary model theory to homogeneous model theory. In particular, we lift the theory of envelopes to homogeneous model theory and develope theory of imaginaries in the case of ω-stable homogeneous classes of finite U-rank.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  10
    Coxeter Groups and Abstract Elementary Classes: The Right-Angled Case.Tapani Hyttinen & Gianluca Paolini - 2019 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 60 (4):707-731.
    We study classes of right-angled Coxeter groups with respect to the strong submodel relation of a parabolic subgroup. We show that the class of all right-angled Coxeter groups is not smooth and establish some general combinatorial criteria for such classes to be abstract elementary classes (AECs), for them to be finitary, and for them to be tame. We further prove two combinatorial conditions ensuring the strong rigidity of a right-angled Coxeter group of arbitrary rank. The combination of these (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  25
    Potential isomorphism of elementary substructures of a strictly stable homogeneous model.Sy-David Friedman, Tapani Hyttinen & Agatha C. Walczak-Typke - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (3):987 - 1004.
    The results herein form part of a larger project to characterize the classification properties of the class of submodels of a homogeneous stable diagram in terms of the solvability (in the sense of [1]) of the potential isomorphism problem for this class of submodels. We restrict ourselves to locally saturated submodels of the monster model m of some power π. We assume that in Gödel's constructible universe ������, π is a regular cardinal at least the successor of the first cardinal (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Amer. Math. Soc. Tnnil.A. Simplification of A. Selberg'S. Elementary & of Distribution of Prime Numbers - 1979 - In A. F. Lavrik (ed.), Twelve Papers in Logic and Algebra. American Mathematical Society. pp. 75.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  31
    Preservation theorems for Kripke models.Morteza Moniri & Mostafa Zaare - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (2):177-184.
    There are several ways for defining the notion submodel for Kripke models of intuitionistic first‐order logic. In our approach a Kripke model A is a submodel of a Kripke model B if they have the same frame and for each two corresponding worlds Aα and Bα of them, Aα is a subset of Bα and forcing of atomic formulas with parameters in the smaller one, in A and B, are the same. In this case, B is called an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  33
    Questions from Methow Valley Elementary.Methow Valley Elementary - 2010 - Questions 10:1-1.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  21
    Questions from Methow Valley Elementary.Methow Valley Elementary - 2010 - Questions: Philosophy for Young People 10:1-1.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  9
    Questions from Methow Valley Elementary.Methow Valley Elementary - 2010 - Questions 10:1-1.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. On the concept of proof in elementary geometry Pirmin stekeler-weithofer.Proof In Elementary - 1992 - In Michael Detlefsen (ed.), Proof and Knowledge in Mathematics. Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Boston colloquium for the philosophy of science. [REVIEW]What is Elementary Logic - 1991 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 22:201-204.
  29.  58
    Mathematical logic and foundations of set theory.Yehoshua Bar-Hillel (ed.) - 1970 - Amsterdam,: North-Holland Pub. Co..
    LN , so f lies in the elementary submodel M'. Clearly co 9 M' . It follows that 6 = {f(n): n em} is included in M'. Hence the ordinals of M' form an initial ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  36
    On the structure of kripke models of heyting arithmetic.Zoran Marković - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):531-538.
    Since in Heyting Arithmetic all atomic formulas are decidable, a Kripke model for HA may be regarded classically as a collection of classical structures for the language of arithmetic, partially ordered by the submodel relation. The obvious question is then: are these classical structures models of Peano Arithmetic ? And dually: if a collection of models of PA, partially ordered by the submodel relation, is regarded as a Kripke model, is it a model of HA? Some partial answers (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  31.  27
    Strong splitting in stable homogeneous models.Tapani Hyttinen & Saharon Shelah - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 103 (1-3):201-228.
    In this paper we study elementary submodels of a stable homogeneous structure. We improve the independence relation defined in Hyttinen 167–182). We apply this to prove a structure theorem. We also show that dop and sdop are essentially equivalent, where the negation of dop is the property we use in our structure theorem and sdop implies nonstructure, see Hyttinen.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  32.  12
    Infinite combinatorics plain and simple.Dániel T. Soukup & Lajos Soukup - 2018 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 83 (3):1247-1281.
    We explore a general method based on trees of elementary submodels in order to present highly simplified proofs to numerous results in infinite combinatorics. While countable elementary submodels have been employed in such settings already, we significantly broaden this framework by developing the corresponding technique for countably closed models of size continuum. The applications range from various theorems on paradoxical decompositions of the plane, to coloring sparse set systems, results on graph chromatic number and constructions from point-set topology. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  28
    Back and Forth Between First-Order Kripke Models.Tomasz Połacik - 2008 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 16 (4):335-355.
    We introduce the notion of bisimulation for first-order Kripke models. It is defined as a relation that satisfies certain zig-zag conditions involving back-and-forth moves between nodes of Kripke models and, simultaneously, between the domains of their underlying structures. As one of our main results, we prove that if two Kripke models bisimulate to a certain degree, then they are logically equivalent with respect to the class of formulae of the appropriate complexity. Two applications of the notion introduced in the paper (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34.  15
    Generalizing Morley's Theorem.Tapani Hyttinen - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (2):176-184.
    We study the categoricity of the classes of elementary submodels of a homogeneous structure.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  35.  56
    Power-like models of set theory.Ali Enayat - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (4):1766-1782.
    A model M = (M, E,...) of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory ZF is said to be θ-like, where E interprets ∈ and θ is an uncountable cardinal, if |M| = θ but $|\{b \in M: bEa\}| for each a ∈ M. An immediate corollary of the classical theorem of Keisler and Morley on elementary end extensions of models of set theory is that every consistent extension of ZF has an ℵ 1 -like model. Coupled with Chang's two cardinal theorem this (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36.  26
    A construction of superstable NDOP-NOTOP groups.Andreas Baudisch - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1385-1390.
    The paper continues [1]. Let S be a complete theory of ultraflat (e.g. planar) graphs as introduced in [4]. We show a strong form of NOTOP for S: The union of two models M1 and M2, independent over a common elementary submodel M0, is the primary model over M1 ∪ M2 of S. Then by results of [1] Mekler's construction [6] gives for such a theory S of nice ultraflat graphs a superstable 2-step-nilpotent group of exponent $p (>2)$ (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  17
    A test for expandability.Enrique Casanovas - 1998 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 37 (4):221-234.
    A model $M$ of countable similarity type and cardinality $\kappa$ is expandable if every consistent extension $T_{1}$ of its complete theory with $|T_{1}|\leq \kappa$ is satisfiable in $M$ and it is compactly expandable if every such extension which additionally is finitely satisfiable in $M$ is satisfiable in $M$ . In the countable case and in the case of a model of cardinality $\geq 2^{\omega}$ of a superstable theory without the finite cover property the notions of saturation, expandability and compactness for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  15
    New methods in forcing iteration and applications.Rahman Mohammadpour - 2023 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 29 (2):300-302.
    The Theme. Strong forcing axioms like Martin’s Maximum give a reasonably satisfactory structural analysis of $H(\omega _2)$. A broad program in modern Set Theory is searching for strong forcing axioms beyond $\omega _1$. In other words, one would like to figure out the structural properties of taller initial segments of the universe. However, the classical techniques of forcing iterations seem unable to bypass the obstacles, as the resulting forcings axioms beyond $\omega _1$ have not thus far been strong enough! However, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  15
    Covers of Abelian varieties as analytic Zariski structures.Misha Gavrilovich - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (11):1524-1548.
    We use tools of mathematical logic to analyse the notion of a path on a complex algebraic variety, and are led to formulate a “rigidity” property of fundamental groups specific to algebraic varieties, as well as to define a bona fide topology closely related to etale topology. These appear as criteria for ℵ1-categoricity, or rather stability and homogeneity, of the formal countable language we propose to describe homotopy classes of paths on a variety, or equivalently, its universal covering space.Technically, for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  15
    In memoriam: James Earl Baumgartner (1943–2011).J. A. Larson - 2017 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (7):877-909.
    James Earl Baumgartner (March 23, 1943–December 28, 2011) came of age mathematically during the emergence of forcing as a fundamental technique of set theory, and his seminal research changed the way set theory is done. He made fundamental contributions to the development of forcing, to our understanding of uncountable orders, to the partition calculus, and to large cardinals and their ideals. He promulgated the use of logic such as absoluteness and elementary submodels to solve problems in set theory, he (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  31
    Homomorphisms and chains of Kripke models.Morteza Moniri & Mostafa Zaare - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (3-4):431-443.
    In this paper we define a suitable version of the notion of homomorphism for Kripke models of intuitionistic first-order logic and characterize theories that are preserved under images and also those that are preserved under inverse images of homomorphisms. Moreover, we define a notion of union of chain for Kripke models and define a class of formulas that is preserved in unions of chains. We also define similar classes of formulas and investigate their behavior in Kripke models. An application to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  4
    Taking Reinhardt’s Power Away.Richard Matthews - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (4):1643-1662.
    We study the notion of non-trivial elementary embeddings under the assumption that V satisfies ZFC without Power Set but with the Collection Scheme. We show that no such embedding can exist under the additional assumption that it is cofinal and either is a set or that the scheme of Dependent Choices of arbitrary length holds. We then study failures of instances of Collection in symmetric submodels of class forcings.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  22
    Axiomatizability by \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${{\forall}{\exists}!}$$\end{document}-sentences. [REVIEW]Miguel Campercholi & Diego Vaggione - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (7-8):713-725.
    A \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\forall\exists!}$$\end{document}-sentence is a sentence of the form \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\forall x_{1}\cdots x_{n}\exists!y_{1}\cdots y_{m}O(\overline{x},\overline{y})}$$\end{document}, where O is a quantifier-free formula, and \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\exists!}$$\end{document} stands for “there exist unique”. We prove that if \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathcal{C}}$$\end{document} is (up to isomorphism) a finite class of finite models then \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  22
    Symmetric submodels of a cohen generic extension.Claude Sureson - 1992 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 58 (3):247-261.
    Sureson, C., Symmetric submodels of a Cohen generic extension, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 58 247–261. We study some symmetric submodels of a Cohen generic extension and the satisfaction of several properties ) which strongly violate the axiom of choice.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  37
    Submodels in Carnap’s Early Axiomatics Revisited.Iris Loeb - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (2):405-429.
    G. Schiemer has recently ascribed to Carnap the so-called domains-as-fields conception of models, which he subsequently used to defend Carnap’s treatment of extremal axioms against J. Hintikka’s criticism that the number of tuples in a relation, and not the domain of discourse, is optimised in Carnap’s treatment. We will argue by a careful textual analysis, however, that this domains-as-fields conception cannot be applied to Carnap’s early semantics, because it includes a notion of submodel and subrelation that is not only (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46.  30
    Submodels of Kripke models.Albert Visser - 2001 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 40 (4):277-295.
    A Kripke model ? is a submodel of another Kripke model ℳ if ? is obtained by restricting the set of nodes of ℳ. In this paper we show that the class of formulas of Intuitionistic Predicate Logic that is preserved under taking submodels of Kripke models is precisely the class of semipositive formulas. This result is an analogue of the Łoś-Tarski theorem for the Classical Predicate Calculus.In Appendix A we prove that for theories with decidable identity we can (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  47.  17
    Kripke submodels and universal sentences.Ben Ellison, Jonathan Fleischmann, Dan McGinn & Wim Ruitenburg - 2007 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 53 (3):311-320.
    We define two notions for intuitionistic predicate logic: that of a submodel of a Kripke model, and that of a universal sentence. We then prove a corresponding preservation theorem. If a Kripke model is viewed as a functor from a small category to the category of all classical models with morphisms between them, then we define a submodel of a Kripke model to be a restriction of the original Kripke model to a subcategory of its domain, where every (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48.  56
    Elementary logic.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1966 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Now much revised since its first appearance in 1941, this book, despite its brevity, is notable for its scope and rigor.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  49.  17
    Submodels and definable points in models of Peano arithmetic.Žarko Mijajlović - 1983 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24 (4):417-425.
  50.  23
    The finite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries.Marko Djordjević - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 139 (1):201-229.
    We prove, by a probabilistic argument, that a class of ω-categorical structures, on which algebraic closure defines a pregeometry, has the finite submodel property. This class includes any expansion of a pure set or of a vector space, projective space or affine space over a finite field such that the new relations are sufficiently independent of each other and over the original structure. In particular, the random graph belongs to this class, since it is a sufficiently independent expansion of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000