Results for 'Information Systems Applications (incl.Internet)'

100 found
Order:
  1.  29
    On $${{{\mathcal {F}}}}$$-Systems: A Graph-Theoretic Model for Paradoxes Involving a Falsity Predicate and Its Application to Argumentation Frameworks.Gustavo Bodanza - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (3):373-393.
    $${{{\mathcal {F}}}}$$ -systems are useful digraphs to model sentences that predicate the falsity of other sentences. Paradoxes like the Liar and the one of Yablo can be analyzed with that tool to find graph-theoretic patterns. In this paper we studied this general model consisting of a set of sentences and the binary relation ‘ $$\ldots $$ affirms the falsity of $$\ldots $$ ’ among them. The possible existence of non-referential sentences was also considered. To model the sets of all (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  10
    Adding a temporal dimension to a logic system.Dov M. Gabbay & Marcelo Finger - 1992 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 1 (3):203-233.
    We introduce a methodology whereby an arbitrary logic system L can be enriched with temporal features to create a new system T(L). The new system is constructed by combining L with a pure propositional temporal logic T (such as linear temporal logic with “Since” and “Until”) in a special way. We refer to this method as “adding a temporal dimension to L” or just “temporalising L”. We show that the logic system T(L) preserves several properties of the original temporal logic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  3.  32
    An Application of Peircean Triadic Logic: Modelling Vagueness.Asim Raza, Asim D. Bakhshi & Basit Koshul - 2019 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 28 (3):389-426.
    Development of decision-support and intelligent agent systems necessitates mathematical descriptions of uncertainty and fuzziness in order to model vagueness. This paper seeks to present an outline of Peirce’s triadic logic as a practical new way to model vagueness in the context of artificial intelligence. Charles Sanders Peirce was an American scientist–philosopher and a great logician whose triadic logic is a culmination of the study of semiotics and the mathematical study of anti-Cantorean model of continuity and infinitesimals. After presenting Peircean (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  12
    25th Workshop on Logic, Language, Information and Computation: WoLLIC 2018.Lawrence Moss & Ruy de Queiroz - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (4):525-527.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  39
    Revising System Specifications in Temporal Logic.Paulo T. Guerra & Renata Wassermann - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (4):591-618.
    Although formal system verification has been around for many years, little attention was given to the case where the specification of the system has to be changed. This may occur due to a failure in capturing the clients’ requirements or due to some change in the domain (think for example of banking systems that have to adapt to different taxes being imposed). We are interested in having methods not only to verify properties, but also to suggest how the system (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  24
    On the (Complete) Reasons Behind Decisions.Adnan Darwiche & Auguste Hirth - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (1):63-88.
    Recent work has shown that the input-output behavior of some common machine learning classifiers can be captured in symbolic form, allowing one to reason about the behavior of these classifiers using symbolic techniques. This includes explaining decisions, measuring robustness, and proving formal properties of machine learning classifiers by reasoning about the corresponding symbolic classifiers. In this work, we present a theory for unveiling the _reasons_ behind the decisions made by Boolean classifiers and study some of its theoretical and practical implications. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  17
    Possibility and Dyadic Contingency.Claudio E. A. Pizzi - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (3):451-463.
    The paper aims at developing the idea that the standard operator of noncontingency, usually symbolized by Δ, is a special case of a more general operator of dyadic noncontingency Δ(−, −). Such a notion may be modally defined in different ways. The one examined in the paper is __Δ__(B, A) = df ◊B ∧ (A ⥽ B ∨ A ⥽ ¬B), where ⥽ stands for strict implication. The operator of dyadic contingency __∇__(B, A) is defined as the negation of __Δ__(B, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  36
    The Effort of Reasoning: Modelling the Inference Steps of Boundedly Rational Agents.Anthia Solaki - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (4):529-553.
    In this paper we design a new logical system to explicitly model the different deductive reasoning steps of a boundedly rational agent. We present an adequate system in line with experimental findings about an agent’s reasoning limitations and the cognitive effort that is involved. Inspired by Dynamic Epistemic Logic, we work with dynamic operators denoting explicit applications of inference rules in our logical language. Our models are supplemented by (a) impossible worlds (not closed under logical consequence), suitably structured according (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9.  15
    A Logical Theory for Conditional Weak Ontic Necessity Based on Context Update.Fengkui Ju - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (5):777-807.
    Weak ontic necessity is the ontic necessity expressed by “should/ought to” in English. An example of it is “I should be dead by now”. A feature of this necessity is that whether it holds at the present world is irrelevant to whether its prejacent holds at the present world. In this paper, by combining premise semantics and update semantics for conditionals, we present a logical theory for conditional weak ontic necessity based on context update. A context is a set of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  13
    Monotonic Inference with Unscoped Episodic Logical Forms: From Principles to System.Gene Louis Kim, Mandar Juvekar, Junis Ekmekciu, Viet Duong & Lenhart Schubert - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 33 (1):69-88.
    We describe the foundations and the systematization of natural logic-like monotonic inference using unscoped episodic logical forms (ULFs) that as reported by Kim et al. (Proceedings of the 1st and 2nd Workshops on Natural Logic Meets Machine Learning (NALOMA), Groningen, 2021a, b) introduced and first evaluated. In addition to providing a more detailed explanation of the theory and system, we present results from extending the inference manager to address a few of the limitations that as reported by Kim et al. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  5
    Deciding Regular Grammar Logics with Converse Through First-Order Logic.Stéphane Demri & Hans Nivelle - 2005 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 14 (3):289-329.
    We provide a simple translation of the satisfiability problem for regular grammar logics with converse into GF2, which is the intersection of the guarded fragment and the 2-variable fragment of first-order logic. The translation is theoretically interesting because it translates modal logics with certain frame conditions into first-order logic, without explicitly expressing the frame conditions. It is practically relevant because it makes it possible to use a decision procedure for the guarded fragment in order to decide regular grammar logics with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  44
    Belief Revision and Computational Argumentation: A Critical Comparison.Pietro Baroni, Eduardo Fermé, Massimiliano Giacomin & Guillermo Ricardo Simari - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (4):555-589.
    This paper aims at comparing and relating belief revision and argumentation as approaches to model reasoning processes. Referring to some prominent literature references in both fields, we will discuss their (implicit or explicit) assumptions on the modeled processes and hence commonalities and differences in the forms of reasoning they are suitable to deal with. The intended contribution is on one hand assessing the (not fully explored yet) relationships between two lively research fields in the broad area of defeasible reasoning and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  14
    A Computational Treatment of Anaphora and Its Algorithmic Implementation.Jean-Philippe Bernardy, Stergios Chatzikyriakidis & Aleksandre Maskharashvili - 2020 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 30 (1):1-29.
    In this paper, we propose a framework capable of dealing with anaphora and ellipsis which is both general and algorithmic. This generality is ensured by the compination of two general ideas. First, we use a dynamic semantics which reperent effects using a monad structure. Second we treat scopes flexibly, extending them as needed. We additionally implement this framework as an algorithm which translates abstract syntax to logical formulas. We argue that this framework can provide a unified account of a large (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  24
    Feferman–Vaught Decompositions for Prefix Classes of First Order Logic.Abhisekh Sankaran - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (1):147-174.
    The Feferman–Vaught theorem provides a way of evaluating a first order sentence \(\varphi \) on a disjoint union of structures by producing a decomposition of \(\varphi \) into sentences which can be evaluated on the individual structures and the results of these evaluations combined using a propositional formula. This decomposition can in general be non-elementarily larger than \(\varphi \). We introduce a “tree” generalization of the prenex normal form (PNF) for first order sentences, and show that for an input sentence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  39
    Assessing the Strengths and Weaknesses of Large Language Models.Shalom Lappin - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 33 (1):9-20.
    The transformers that drive chatbots and other AI systems constitute large language models (LLMs). These are currently the focus of a lively discussion in both the scientific literature and the popular media. This discussion ranges from hyperbolic claims that attribute general intelligence and sentience to LLMs, to the skeptical view that these devices are no more than “stochastic parrots”. I present an overview of some of the weak arguments that have been presented against LLMs, and I consider several of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  16.  27
    Names and Quantifiers: Bringing Them Together in Classical Logic.Jacek Paśniczek - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (3):473-487.
    Putting individual constants and quantifiers into the same syntactic category within first-order language promises to have far-reaching consequences: a syntax of this kind can reveal the potential of any such language, allowing us to realize that a vast class of noun phrases, including non-denoting terms, can be accommodated in the new syntax as expressions suited to being subjects of sentences. In the light of this, a formal system that is an extension of classical first-order logic is developed here, and is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  43
    Filtered Belief Revision: Syntax and Semantics.Giacomo Bonanno - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (4):645-675.
    In an earlier paper [Rational choice and AGM belief revision, _Artificial Intelligence_, 2009] a correspondence was established between the set-theoretic structures of revealed-preference theory (developed in economics) and the syntactic belief revision functions of the AGM theory (developed in philosophy and computer science). In this paper we extend the re-interpretation of those structures in terms of one-shot belief revision by relating them to the trichotomous attitude towards information studied in Garapa (Rev Symb Logic, 1–21, 2020) where information may (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  25
    Some Notes on Dyadic Contingency.Jie Fan - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (2):209-217.
    In a recent work, Pizzi proposes a notion of dyadic non-contingency, and then gives an axiomatic system of dyadic non-contingency named \(\text {KD}\Delta ^2\), which is shown to be translationally equivalent to the deontic system KD and has the minimal system \(\text {K}\Delta \) of monadic contingency as a fragment. However, the reason why he defines dyadic non-contingency like that is unclear. In this article, inspired by the notion of relativized knowing-value in the literature, we give a plausible explanation for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  26
    An Epistemic Separation Logic with Action Models.Hans van Ditmarsch, Didier Galmiche & Marta Gawek - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (1):89-116.
    In this paper we present an extension of (bunched) separation logic, Boolean BI, with epistemic and dynamic epistemic modalities. This logic, called action model separation logic ( \(\mathrm {AMSL}\) ), can be seen as a generalization of public announcement separation logic in which we replace public announcements with action models. Then we not only model public information change (public announcements) but also non-public forms of information change, such as private announcements. In this context the semantics for the connectives (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  20
    Propositional Forms of Judgemental Interpretations.Tao Xue, Zhaohui Luo & Stergios Chatzikyriakidis - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (4):733-758.
    In formal semantics based on modern type theories, some sentences may be interpreted as judgements and some as logical propositions. When interpreting composite sentences, one may want to turn a judgemental interpretation or an ill-typed semantic interpretation into a proposition in order to obtain an intended semantics. For instance, an incorrect judgement $$a:A$$ may be turned into its propositional form $$\textsc {is}(A,a)$$ and an ill-typed application p(a) into $$\textsc {do}(p,a)$$, so that the propositional forms can take part in logical compositions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  12
    Formalizing GDPR Provisions in Reified I/O Logic: The DAPRECO Knowledge Base.Livio Robaldo, Cesare Bartolini, Monica Palmirani, Arianna Rossi, Michele Martoni & Gabriele Lenzini - 2020 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 29 (4):401-449.
    The DAPRECO knowledge base is the main outcome of the interdisciplinary project bearing the same name. It is a repository of rules written in LegalRuleML, an XML formalism designed to be a standard for representing the semantic and logical content of legal documents. The rules represent the provisions of the General Data Protection Regulation, the new Regulation that is significantly affecting the digital market in the European Union and beyond. The DAPRECO knowledge base builds upon the Privacy Ontology, which provides (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  5
    A “Maximal Exclusion” Approach to Structural Underspecification in Dynamic Syntax.Tohru Seraku - 2019 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 30 (2):407-428.
    ‘Case’ and ‘grammatical relations’ are central to syntactic theory, but rigorous treatments of these concepts in surface-oriented grammars such as Dynamic Syntax are pending. In this respect, Japanese is worthy of mention; in this language, the nominative case particle ga, which typically marks a subject, may mark an object in certain syntactic contexts, and more than one instance of ga may be present within a single clause. These patterns cannot be captured if we simply assume that ga marks a subject. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  12
    A “Maximal Exclusion” Approach to Structural Underspecification in Dynamic Syntax.Tohru Seraku - 2019 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 30 (2):407-428.
    ‘Case’ and ‘grammatical relations’ are central to syntactic theory, but rigorous treatments of these concepts in surface-oriented grammars such as Dynamic Syntax are pending. In this respect, Japanese is worthy of mention; in this language, the nominative case particle ga, which typically marks a subject, may mark an object in certain syntactic contexts, and more than one instance of ga may be present within a single clause. These patterns cannot be captured if we simply assume that ga marks a subject. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  7
    A “Maximal Exclusion” Approach to Structural Underspecification in Dynamic Syntax.Tohru Seraku - 2019 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 30 (2):407-428.
    ‘Case’ and ‘grammatical relations’ are central to syntactic theory, but rigorous treatments of these concepts in surface-oriented grammars such as Dynamic Syntax are pending. In this respect, Japanese is worthy of mention; in this language, the nominative case particle ga, which typically marks a subject, may mark an object in certain syntactic contexts, and more than one instance of ga may be present within a single clause. These patterns cannot be captured if we simply assume that ga marks a subject. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  94
    Prolegomena to a cognitive investigation of Euclidean diagrammatic reasoning.Yacin Hamami & John Mumma - 2013 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 22 (4):421-448.
    Euclidean diagrammatic reasoning refers to the diagrammatic inferential practice that originated in the geometrical proofs of Euclid’s Elements. A seminal philosophical analysis of this practice by Manders (‘The Euclidean diagram’, 2008) has revealed that a systematic method of reasoning underlies the use of diagrams in Euclid’s proofs, leading in turn to a logical analysis aiming to capture this method formally via proof systems. The central premise of this paper is that our understanding of Euclidean diagrammatic reasoning can be fruitfully (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  26.  46
    Deontic Paradoxes in Mīmāṃsā Logics: There and Back Again.Kees van Berkel, Agata Ciabattoni, Elisa Freschi, Francesca Gulisano & Maya Olszewski - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (1):19-62.
    Centered around the analysis of the prescriptive portion of the Vedas, the Sanskrit philosophical school of Mīmāṃsā provides a treasure trove of normative investigations. We focus on the leading Mīmāṃsā authors Prabhākara, Kumārila and Maṇḍana, and discuss three modal logics that formalize their deontic theories. In the first part of this paper, we use logic to analyze, compare and clarify the various solutions to the _śyena_ controversy, a two-thousand-year-old problem arising from seemingly conflicting commands in the Vedas. In the second (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  35
    Public Announcements, Public Lies and Recoveries.Kai Li & Jan van Eijck - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (3):423-450.
    The paper gives a formal analysis of public lies, explains how public lying is related to public announcement, and describes the process of recoveries from false beliefs engendered by public lying. The framework treats two kinds of public lies: simple lying update and two-step lying, which consists of suggesting that the lie may be true followed by announcing the lie. It turns out that agents’ convictions of what is true are immune to the first kind, but can be shattered by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  13
    Some Remarks on Semantics and Expressiveness of the Sentential Calculus with Identity.Steffen Lewitzka - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (3):441-471.
    R. Suszko’s Sentential Calculus with Identity \( SCI \) results from classical propositional calculus \( CPC \) by adding a new connective \(\equiv \) and axioms for identity \(\varphi \equiv \psi \) (which we interpret here as ‘propositional identity’). We reformulate the original semantics of \( SCI \) using Boolean prealgebras which, introduced in different ways, are known in the literature as structures for the modeling of (hyper-) intensional semantics. We regard intensionality here as a measure for the discernibility of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  23
    Kripke Contexts, Double Boolean Algebras with Operators and Corresponding Modal Systems.Prosenjit Howlader & Mohua Banerjee - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (1):117-146.
    The notion of a context in formal concept analysis and that of an approximation space in rough set theory are unified in this study to define a Kripke context. For any context (G,M,I), a relation on the set G of objects and a relation on the set M of properties are included, giving a structure of the form ((G,R), (M,S), I). A Kripke context gives rise to complex algebras based on the collections of protoconcepts and semiconcepts of the underlying context. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  18
    A Revised Projectivity Calculus for Inclusion and Exclusion Reasoning.Ka-fat Chow - 2020 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 29 (2):163-195.
    We present a Revised Projectivity Calculus that extends the scope of inclusion and exclusion inferences derivable under the Projectivity Calculus developed by Icard :705–725, 2012). After pointing out the inadequacies of C, we introduce four opposition properties which have been studied by Chow Proceedings of the 18th Amsterdam Colloquium, Springer, Berlin, 2012; Beziau, Georgiorgakis New dimensions of the square of opposition, Philosophia Verlag GmbH, München, 2017) and are more appropriate for the study of exclusion reasoning. Together with the monotonicity properties, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  21
    Non-transitive Correspondence Analysis.Yaroslav Petrukhin & Vasily Shangin - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (2):247-273.
    The paper’s novelty is in combining two comparatively new fields of research: non-transitive logic and the proof method of correspondence analysis. To be more detailed, in this paper the latter is adapted to Weir’s non-transitive trivalent logic \({\mathbf{NC}}_{\mathbf{3}}\). As a result, for each binary extension of \({\mathbf{NC}}_{\mathbf{3}}\), we present a sound and complete Lemmon-style natural deduction system. Last, but not least, we stress the fact that Avron and his co-authors’ general method of obtaining _n_-sequent proof systems for any _n_-valent (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  24
    Type Polymorphism, Natural Language Semantics, and TIL.Ivo Pezlar - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (2):275-295.
    Transparent intensional logic (TIL) is a well-explored type-theoretical framework for semantics of natural language. However, its treatment of polymorphic functions, which are essential for the analysis of various natural language phenomena, is still underdeveloped. In this paper, we address this issue and propose an extension of TIL that introduces polymorphism via type variables ranging over types and generalized variables ranging over constructions and types. Furthermore, we offer an analysis of sentences involving non-specific notional attitudes of the general form ‘_A_ considers (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  22
    Idempotency, Output-Drivenness and the Faithfulness Triangle Inequality: Some Consequences of McCarthy’s (2003) Categoricity Generalization.Giorgio Magri - 2018 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 27 (1):1-60.
    Idempotency requires any phonotactically licit forms to be faithfully realized. Output-drivenness requires any discrepancies between underlying and output forms to be driven exclusively by phonotactics. These formal notions are relevant for phonological theory and play a crucial role in learnability. Tesar and Magri provide tight guarantees for OT output-drivenness and idempotency through conditions on the faithfulness constraints. This paper derives analogous faithfulness conditions for HG idempotency and output-drivenness and develops an intuitive interpretation of the various OT and HG faithfulness conditions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  26
    The Epistemology of Nondeterminism.Adam Bjorndahl - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (4):619-644.
    This paper proposes new semantics for propositional dynamic logic (PDL), replacing the standard relational semantics. Under these new semantics, program execution is represented as fundamentally deterministic (i.e., functional), while nondeterminism emerges as an epistemic relationship between the agent and the system: intuitively, the nondeterministic outcomes of a given process are precisely those that cannot be ruled out in advance. We formalize these notions using topology and the framework of dynamic topological logic (DTL) (Kremer and Mints in Ann Pure Appl Logic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  20
    Modified Numerals and Split Disjunction: The First-Order Case.Maria Aloni & Peter van Ormondt - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (4):539-567.
    We present a number of puzzles arising for the interpretation of modified numerals. Following Büring and others we assume that the main difference between comparative and superlative modifiers is that only the latter convey disjunctive meanings. We further argue that the inference patterns triggered by disjunction and superlative modifiers are hard to capture in existing semantic and pragmatic analyses of these phenomena (neo-Gricean or grammatical alike), and we propose a novel account of these inferences in the framework of bilateral state-based (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  23
    Language Learnability in the Limit: A Generalization of Gold’s Theorem.Fernando C. Alves - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (3):363-372.
    In his pioneering work in the field of inductive inference, Gold (Inf Control 10:447–474, 1967) proved that a set containing all finite languages and at least one infinite language over the same fixed alphabet is not identifiable in the limit (learnable in the exact sense) from complete texts. Gold’s work paved the way for computational learning theories of language and has implications for two linguistically relevant classes in the Chomsky hierarchy (cf. Chomsky in Inf Control 2:137–167, 1959, Chomsky in Knowledge (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  14
    Combining Machine Learning and Semantic Features in the Classification of Corporate Disclosures.Stefan Evert, Philipp Heinrich, Klaus Henselmann, Ulrich Rabenstein, Elisabeth Scherr, Martin Schmitt & Lutz Schröder - 2019 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 28 (2):309-330.
    We investigate an approach to improving statistical text classification by combining machine learners with an ontology-based identification of domain-specific topic categories. We apply this approach to ad hoc disclosures by public companies. This form of obligatory publicity concerns all information that might affect the stock price; relevant topic categories are governed by stringent regulations. Our goal is to classify disclosures according to their effect on stock prices (negative, neutral, positive). In the study reported here, we combine natural language parsing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  7
    Special Issue of Natural Logic Meets Machine Learning (NALOMA): Selected Papers from the First Three Workshops of NALOMA.Aikaterini-Lida Kalouli, Lasha Abzianidze & Stergios Chatzikyriakidis - 2024 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 33 (1):1-7.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  12
    A Dynamic Analysis of Minimizers in Chinese lian…dou Construction.Xiaolong Yang & Yicheng Wu - 2021 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 30 (2):429-449.
    Minimizers are widely acknowledged cross-linguistically to denote a minimal quantity, extent or degree. With respect to minimizers in Mandarin Chinese, Shyu claims that their so-called negative polarity is purely syntactically determined and is facilitated by the lian…dou EVEN construction. Within the framework of Dynamic Syntax which allows for interaction between syntactic, semantic and pragmatic information, we demonstrate that the total negation is actually derived from the interaction between syntax, semantics and pragmatics, rather than being determined by purely syntactic means.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  48
    Language and proof theory.Dov Gabbay & Ruth Kempson - 1996 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 5 (3-4):247-251.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  18
    Temporal Logics of Agency.Johan Benthem & Eric Pacuit - 2010 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 19 (4):389-393.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  32
    A Reinterpretation of Beall’s ‘Off-Topic’ Semantics.Jeremiah Joven B. Joaquin - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (3):409-421.
    Jc Beall’s off-topic interpretation of Weak Kleene logic offers a logic of ‘true-and-topic’ preservation. However, Nissim Francez has recently argued that being ‘off-topic’ is a relational and not an _absolute_ semantic property; as such, it fails to satisfy the conditions of truth-functionality. For Francez, this means that it ‘cannot serve as an interpretation of a truth-value’. In this paper, I propose a two-layered _re_interpretation of Beall’s off-topic semantics. This two-layered framework has two crucial features: a sentential topic-tagging device and a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  13
    Multi-agent Logics for Reasoning About Higher-Order Upper and Lower Probabilities.Dragan Doder, Nenad Savić & Zoran Ognjanović - 2020 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 29 (1):77-107.
    We present a propositional and a first-order logic for reasoning about higher-order upper and lower probabilities. We provide sound and complete axiomatizations for the logics and we prove decidability in the propositional case. Furthermore, we show that the introduced logics generalize some existing probability logics.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  10
    Multi-agent Logics for Reasoning About Higher-Order Upper and Lower Probabilities.Dragan Doder, Nenad Savić & Zoran Ognjanović - 2020 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 29 (1):77-107.
    We present a propositional and a first-order logic for reasoning about higher-order upper and lower probabilities. We provide sound and complete axiomatizations for the logics and we prove decidability in the propositional case. Furthermore, we show that the introduced logics generalize some existing probability logics.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  14
    A Substructural Approach to Explicit Modal Logic.Shawn Standefer - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (2):333–362.
    In this paper, we build on earlier work by Standefer (Logic J IGPL 27(4):543–569, 2019) in investigating extensions of substructural logics, particularly relevant logics, with the machinery of justification logics. We strengthen a negative result from the earlier work showing a limitation with the canonical model method of proving completeness. We then show how to enrich the language with an additional operator for implicit commitment to circumvent these problems. We then extend the logics with axioms for D, 4, and 5, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  25
    Comparison Across Domains in Delineation Semantics.Heather Burnett - 2015 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 24 (3):233-265.
    This paper presents a new logical analysis of quantity comparatives (i.e. More linguists than philosophers came to the party.) within the Delineation Semantics approach to gradability and comparison (McConnell-Ginet in Comparison constructions in English. PhD thesis, University of Rochester, Rochester, 1973; Kamp in Formal semantics of natural language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1975; Klein in Linguist Philos 4:1–45, 1980) among many others. Along with the Degree Semantics framework (Cresswell in Montague grammar. Academic Press, New York, 1976; von Stechow in J (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  20
    Iterated AGM Revision Based on Probability Revision.Sven Ove Hansson - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (4):657-675.
    Close connections between probability theory and the theory of belief change emerge if the codomain of probability functions is extended from the real-valued interval [0, 1] to a hyperreal interval with the same limits. Full beliefs are identified as propositions with a probability at most infinitesimally smaller than 1. Full beliefs can then be given up, and changes in the set of full beliefs follow a pattern very close to that of AGM revision. In this contribution, iterated revision is investigated. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  24
    Adjectival and Adverbial Modification: The View from Modern Type Theories.Stergios Chatzikyriakidis & Zhaohui Luo - 2017 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 26 (1):45-88.
    In this paper we present a study of adjectival/adverbial modification using modern type theories, i.e. type theories within the tradition of Martin-Löf. We present an account of various issues concerning adjectival/adverbial modification and argue that MTTs can be used as an adequate language for interpreting NL semantics. MTTs are not only expressive enough to deal with a range of modification phenomena, but are furthermore well-suited to perform reasoning tasks that can be easily implemented given their proof-theoretic nature. In MTT-semantics, common (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  21
    A Four-Valued Dynamic Epistemic Logic.Yuri David Santos - 2020 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 29 (4):451-489.
    Epistemic logic is usually employed to model two aspects of a situation: the factual and the epistemic aspects. Truth, however, is not always attainable, and in many cases we are forced to reason only with whatever information is available to us. In this paper, we will explore a four-valued epistemic logic designed to deal with these situations, where agents have only knowledge about the available information, which can be incomplete or conflicting, but not explicitly about facts. This layer (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  23
    Nonmonotonic Reasoning, Expectations Orderings, and Conceptual Spaces.Matías Osta-Vélez & Peter Gärdenfors - 2021 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (1):77-97.
    In Gärdenfors and Makinson :197–245, 1994) and Gärdenfors it was shown that it is possible to model nonmonotonic inference using a classical consequence relation plus an expectation-based ordering of formulas. In this article, we argue that this framework can be significantly enriched by adopting a conceptual spaces-based analysis of the role of expectations in reasoning. In particular, we show that this can solve various epistemological issues that surround nonmonotonic and default logics. We propose some formal criteria for constructing and updating (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 100