Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Are spatial representations flattish?J. B. Deregowski - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):243-244.
  • Beyond the methodology of mathematics research programmes.Corfield David - 1998 - Philosophia Mathematica 6 (3):272-301.
    In this paper I assess the obstacles to a transfer of Lakatos's methodology of scientific research programmes to mathematics. I argue that, if we are to use something akin to this methodology to discuss modern mathematics with its interweaving theoretical development, we shall require a more intricate construction and we shall have to move still further away from seeing mathematical knowledge as a collection of statements. I also examine the notion of rivalry within mathematics and claim that this appears to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Semantic Verbs Are Intensional Transitives.Justin D’Ambrosio - 2019 - Mind 128 (509):213-248.
    In this paper I show that we have strong empirical and theoretical reasons to treat the verbs we use in our semantic theorizing—particularly ‘refers to ’, ‘applies to ’, and ‘is true of ’—as intensional transitive verbs. Stating our semantic theories with intensional vocabulary allows us to partially reconcile two competing approaches to the nature and subject-matter of semantics: the Chomskian approach, on which semantics is non-relational, internalistic, and concerns the psychology of language users, and the Lewisian approach, on which (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Innate knowledge and linguistic principles.Peter W. Culiover - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):615-616.
  • Language acquisition in the absence of experience.Stephen Crain - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):597-612.
    A fundamental goal of linguistic theory is to explain how natural languages are acquired. This paper describes some recent findings on how learners acquire syntactic knowledge for which there is little, if any, decisive evidence from the environment. The first section presents several general observations about language acquisition that linguistic theory has tried to explain and discusses the thesis that certain linguistic properties are innate because they appear universally and in the absence of corresponding experience. A third diagnostic for innateness, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • Charting the course of language development.Stephen Crain - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):639-650.
  • Generative versus nongenerative thought.Michael C. Corballis - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):242-243.
  • Methodology, not metaphysics: Against semantic externalism.John Collins - 2009 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 83 (1):53-69.
    Borg (2009) surveys and rejects a number of arguments in favour of semantic internalism. This paper, in turn, surveys and rejects all of Borg's anti-internalist arguments. My chief moral is that, properly conceived, semantic internalism is a methodological doctrine that takes its lead from current practice in linguistics. The unifying theme of internalist arguments, therefore, is that linguistics neither targets nor presupposes externalia. To the extent that this claim is correct, we should be internalists about linguistic phenomena, including semantics.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Visual Narrative Structure.Neil Cohn - 2013 - Cognitive Science 37 (3):413-452.
    Narratives are an integral part of human expression. In the graphic form, they range from cave paintings to Egyptian hieroglyphics, from the Bayeux Tapestry to modern day comic books (Kunzle, 1973; McCloud, 1993). Yet not much research has addressed the structure and comprehension of narrative images, for example, how do people create meaning out of sequential images? This piece helps fill the gap by presenting a theory of Narrative Grammar. We describe the basic narrative categories and their relationship to a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Sculptors, Architects, and Painters Conceive of Depicted Spaces Differently.Claudia Cialone, Thora Tenbrink & Hugo J. Spiers - 2018 - Cognitive Science 42 (2):524-553.
    Sculptors, architects, and painters are three professional groups that require a comprehensive understanding of how to manipulate spatial structures. While it has been speculated that they may differ in the way they conceive of space due to the different professional demands, this has not been empirically tested. To achieve this, we asked architects, painters, sculptors, and a control group questions about spatially complex pictures. Verbalizations elicited were examined using cognitive discourse analysis. We found significant differences between each group. Only painters (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Becoming syntactic.Franklin Chang, Gary S. Dell & Kathryn Bock - 2006 - Psychological Review 113 (2):234-272.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • Representational advantages.Roberto Casati - 2003 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (3):281–298.
    Descriptive metaphysics investigates our naïve ontology as this is articulated in the content of our perception or of our pre-reflective thought about the world. But is access to such content reliable? Sceptics about the standard modes of access (introspection, or language-driven intuitions) may think that investigations in descriptive metaphysics can be aided by the controlled findings of cognitive science. Cognitive scientists have studied a promising range of representational advantages, that is, ways in which cognition favours one type of entity over (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The cognitive functions of language.Peter Carruthers - 2002 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (6):657-674.
    This paper explores a variety of different versions of the thesis that natural language is involved in human thinking. It distinguishes amongst strong and weak forms of this thesis, dismissing some as implausibly strong and others as uninterestingly weak. Strong forms dismissed include the view that language is conceptually necessary for thought (endorsed by many philosophers) and the view that language is _de facto_ the medium of all human conceptual thinking (endorsed by many philosophers and social scientists). Weak forms include (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • What Do Words Do for Us?Ronnie Cann & Ruth Kempson - 2017 - Dialectica 71 (3):425-460.
    In this paper we adopt the hypothesis that languages are mechanisms for interaction, and that grammars encode the means by which such interaction may take place, by use of procedures that construct representations of meaning from strings of words uttered in context, and conversely strings of words are built up from representations of content in interaction with context. In a review of the systemic use of ellipsis in dialogue and associated split-utterance phenomena, we show how, in Dynamic Syntax, words give (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Not in the absence of experience.Helen Smith Caims - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):614-615.
  • Frames of reference in the spatial representation system.David J. Bryant - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):241-242.
  • The role of cerebral lateralization in expression of spatial cognition.Halle D. Brown - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):240-241.
  • Simians, space, and syntax: Parallels between human language and primate social cognition.Leslie Brothers & Michael J. Raleigh - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):613-614.
  • Spatial and cognitive vision differentiate at low levels, but not in language.Bruce Bridgeman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):240-240.
  • Yo no soy ilógico, simplemente sustituyo. Una reflexión y análisis del lenguaje en pacientes con diagnóstico de Trastorno del Pensamiento desde una Semántica Conceptualista.Diana Patricia Botero - 2015 - Logos: Revista de Lingüística, Filosofía y Literatura 25 (2):165-185.
    El discurso de individuos diagnosticados con trastorno del lenguaje como en el caso de la esquizofrenia, ha sido alta y comúnmente estudiado desde enfoques que observan el procesamiento cognitivo en la memoria, la atención o el acceso léxico o la localización y funcionamiento neuronal. El presente artículo en cambio, presenta y propone una reflexión y análisis de la forma de la información en las representaciones mentales a partir de una Semántica Conceptualista que incluye la combinatoria de interfaz físicas/perceptivas y de (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Grammar growth” – what does it really mean?Derek Bickerton - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):564-565.
  • In defense of development.Ruth A. Berman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):612-613.
  • Grammar growth and parameter setting: Computation and creoles.Robert C. Berwick - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):562-563.
  • There is more to location than prepositions.David C. Bennett - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):239-239.
  • Human kinship, from conceptual structure to grammar.Doug Jones - 2010 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (5):367-381.
    Research in anthropology has shown that kin terminologies have a complex combinatorial structure and vary systematically across cultures. This article argues that universals and variation in kin terminology result from the interaction of (1) an innate conceptual structure of kinship, homologous with conceptual structure in other domains, and (2) principles of optimal, “grammatical” communication active in language in general. Kin terms from two languages, English and Seneca, show how terminologies that look very different on the surface may result from variation (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • From Lot's Wife to a Pillar of Salt: Evidence that Physical Object is a Sortal Concept.Fei Xu - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (3-4):365-392.
    Abstract:A number of philosophers of language have proposed that people do not have conceptual access to‘bare particulars’, or attribute‐free individuals (e.g. Wiggins, 1980). Individuals can only be picked out under some sortal, a concept which provides principles of individuation and identity. Many advocates of this view have argued thatobjectis not a genuine sortal concept. I will argue in this paper that a narrow sense of‘object’, namely the concept of any bounded, coherent, three‐dimensional physical object that moves as a whole (Spelke, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Talking to yourself about what is where: What is the vocabulary of preattentive vision?Jeremy M. Wolfe - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):254-255.
  • “What” and “where” in spatial language and spatial cognition.Barbara Landau & Ray Jackendoff - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):217-238.
    Fundamental to spatial knowledge in all species are the representations underlying object recognition, object search, and navigation through space. But what sets humans apart from other species is our ability to express spatial experience through language. This target article explores the language ofobjectsandplaces, asking what geometric properties are preserved in the representations underlying object nouns and spatial prepositions in English. Evidence from these two aspects of language suggests there are significant differences in the geometric richness with which objects and places (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • The lithic technology of Cebus apella_ and its implications for brain evolution and the preconditions of language in _Homo habilis.Gregory Charles Westergaard - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):792-793.
    Wilkins & Wakefield (1995) provide a thoughtful contribution to our understanding of language origins. In this commentary I attempt to define the relationship between object-manipulation and primate brain function further by reviewing research on aimed throwing and the production and use of stone tools by tufted capuchin monkeys (Cebtis apella). I propose that examining the relation between brain function and object-manipulation inCebuswill provide insight into the preconditions of language in our hominid ancestors.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Locative and Directional Prepositions in Conceptual Spaces: The Role of Polar Convexity.Joost Zwarts & Peter Gärdenfors - 2016 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 25 (1):109-138.
    We approach the semantics of prepositions from the perspective of conceptual spaces. Focusing on purely spatial locative and directional prepositions, we analyze both types of prepositions in terms of polar coordinates instead of Cartesian coordinates. This makes it possible to demonstrate that the property of convexity holds quite generally in the domain of prepositions of location and direction, supporting the important role that this property plays in conceptual spaces.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Further issues in neurolinguistic preconditions.Wendy K. Wilkins & Jennie Wakefield - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):793-798.
    This response to continuing commentary addresses brain-hand relationships in Cebus apella (as introduced in West-ergaard's commentary), the evolutionary and acquisition parallels between music and language (suggested by Lynch), and the potential behavioral linguistic consequences of the evolutionary neurobiology in Australopithecus africanus and Homo habilis (discussed by Tobias). Finally, we reiterate the importance of well informed, multidisciplinary approaches to the study of the emergence of human species-specific cognition, especially linguistic capacity.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Autonomy and the nature of the input.Wendy Wilkins - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):638-638.
  • Words, Images and Concepts.Daniel A. Weiskopf - 2015 - Analysis 75 (1):99-109.
    Christopher Gauker proposes that all cognition can be divided into nonconceptual image-based thought and conceptual language-based thought. The division between the two hinges on the representational powers of their respective mediums. I argue that a richer variety of representational states and processes is necessary in order to explain both human and nonhuman cognition. There are aspects of nonhuman cognition that cannot be explained simply by images, and there are aspects of human conceptual thought, particularly those dealing with causal reasoning, that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The origins of concepts.Daniel A. Weiskopf - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 140 (3):359 - 384.
    Certain of our concepts are innate, but many others are learned. Despite the plausibility of this claim, some have argued that the very idea of concept learning is incoherent. I present a conception of learning that sidesteps the arguments against the possibility of concept learning, and sketch several mechanisms that result in the generation of new primitive concepts. Given the rational considerations that motivate their deployment, I argue that these deserve to be called learning mechanisms. I conclude by replying to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Parameter setting and early emergence.Amy Weinberg - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):637-638.
  • Embodied cognition and linguistic comprehension.Daniel A. Weiskopf - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (3):294-304.
    Traditionally, the language faculty was supposed to be a device that maps linguistic inputs to semantic or conceptual representations. These representations themselves were supposed to be distinct from the representations manipulated by the hearer’s perceptual and motor systems. Recently this view of language has been challenged by advocates of embodied cognition. Drawing on empirical studies of linguistic comprehension, they have proposed that the language faculty reuses the very representations and processes deployed in perceiving and acting. I review some of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Debatable constraints.Thomas Wasow - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):636-637.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From observations on language to theories of visual perception.Johan Wagemans - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):253-254.
  • Meaning, prototypes and the future of cognitive science.Jaap van Brakel - 1991 - Minds and Machines 1 (3):233-57.
    In this paper I evaluate the soundness of the prototype paradigm, in particular its basic assumption that there are pan-human psychological essences or core meanings that refer to basic-level natural kinds, explaining why, on the whole, human communication and learning are successful. Instead I argue that there are no particular pan-human basic elements for thought, meaning and cognition, neither prototypes, nor otherwise. To illuminate my view I draw on examples from anthropology. More generally I argue that the prototype paradigm exemplifies (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Prepositions aren't places.Barbara Tversky & Herbert H. Clark - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):252-253.
  • The dating of linguistic beginnings.Phillip V. Tobias - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):789-792.
    The problem of how certain structure–function composites of high complexity could have evolved gradually and by natural selection has been with us at least since Charles Darwin admitted how difficult it was to explain, “his” theory, the origins of “organs of extreme perfection and complication” – such as the eyes of higher animals. Human language capacity is another evolutionary achievement of extraordinary perfection and complexity. Like other skilled human activities, it involves both central (neural) and peripheral (vocal and respiratory) complexes. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From perception to cognition.Michael J. Tarr - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):251-252.
  • Force Dynamics in Language and Cognition.Leonard Talmy - 1988 - Cognitive Science 12 (1):49-100.
    Abstract“Force dynamics” refers to a previously neglected semantic category—how entities interact with respect to force. This category includes such concepts as: the exertion of force, resistance to such exertion and the overcoming of such resistance, blockage of a force and the removal of such blockage, and so forth. Force dynamics is a generalization over the traditional linguistic notion of “causative”: it analyzes “causing” into finer primitives and sets it naturally within a framework that also includes “letting,”“hindering,”“helping,” and still further notions. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   215 citations  
  • In defense of public languages.Robert J. Stainton - 2011 - Linguistics and Philosophy 34 (5):479-488.
    My modest aim in this note is to sketch three interrelated critiques of public languages, and to respond to them. All are broadly Chomskyan, and all support the same conclusion: that, insofar as they even exist, the study of public languages is not a viable scientific project. (Related critiques of semantics, understood as involving word–world relations, will be touched on as well).
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A premature retreat to nativism.Jeffrey L. Sokolov & Catherine E. Snow - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):635-636.
  • Is spatial language a special case?Dan I. Slobin - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):249-251.
  • Can Crain constrain the constraints?Dan I. Slobin - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):633-634.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A computational study of cross-situational techniques for learning word-to-meaning mappings.Jeffrey Mark Siskind - 1996 - Cognition 61 (1-2):39-91.
  • The neuropsychology of proper names.Carlo Semenza - 2009 - Mind and Language 24 (4):347-369.
    The difference between common and proper names seems to derive from specific semantic characteristics of proper names. In particular, proper names refer to specific individual entities or events, and unlike common names, rarely map onto more general semantic characteristics (attributes, concepts, categories). This fact makes the link proper names have with their reference particularly fragile. Processing proper names seems, as a consequence, to require special cognitive and neural resources. Neuropsychological findings show that proper names and common names follow functionally distinct (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Prolegomena to Music Semantics.Philippe Schlenker - 2019 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 10 (1):35-111.
    We argue that a formal semantics for music can be developed, although it will be based on very different principles from linguistic semantics and will yield less precise inferences. Our framework has the following tenets: Music cognition is continuous with normal auditory cognition. In both cases, the semantic content derived from an auditory percept can be identified with the set of inferences it licenses on its causal sources, analyzed in appropriately abstract ways. What is special about music semantics is that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations