Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Taking the intentional stance seriously.Daniel C. Dennett - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):379-390.
  • Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: The 'panglossian paradigm' defended.Daniel C. Dennett - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):343-90.
    Ethologists and others studying animal behavior in a spirit are in need of a descriptive language and method that are neither anachronistically bound by behaviorist scruples nor prematurely committed to particular Just such an interim descriptive method can be found in intentional system theory. The use of intentional system theory is illustrated with the case of the apparently communicative behavior of vervet monkeys. A way of using the theory to generate data - including usable, testable data - is sketched. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   595 citations  
  • Anatomy of hierarchical information processing.Terrence W. Deacon - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):555-557.
  • Adaptationism was always predictive and needed no defense.Richard Dawkins - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):360-361.
  • Numerical competence in animals: Definitional issues, current evidence, and a new research agenda.Hank Davis & Rachelle Pérusse - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):561-579.
  • Numerical competence: From backwater to mainstream of comparative psychology.Hank Davis & Rachelle Pérusse - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):602-615.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Science as an international system.Arthur C. Danto - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):359-360.
  • Sign language and the brain: Apes, apraxia, and aphasia.David Corina - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):633-634.
    The study of signed languages has inspired scientific' speculation regarding foundations of human language. Relationships between the acquisition of sign language in apes and man are discounted on logical grounds. Evidence from the differential hreakdown of sign language and manual pantomime places limits on the degree of overlap between language and nonlanguage motor systems. Evidence from functional magnetic resonance imaging reveals neural areas of convergence and divergence underlying signed and spoken languages.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to grow a human.Michael C. Corballis - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):632-633.
    I enlarge on the theme that the brain mechanisms required for languageand other aspects of the human mind evolved through selective changes in the regulatory genes governing growth. Extension of the period of postnatal growth increases the role of the environment in structuring the brain, and spatiotemporal programming (heterochrony) ofgrowth might explain hierarchical representation, hemispheric specialization, and perhaps sex differences.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hierarchies and tool-using strategies.Kevin J. Connolly & Edison de J. Manoel - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):554-555.
  • Dennett' instrumentalism: A frog at the bottom of the mug.Patricia Smith Churchland - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):358-359.
  • Human infants are perhaps not so gifted after all.Bernadette Chauvin - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):583-583.
  • What good is five percent of a language competence?A. Charles Catania - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):729-731.
  • Minds and Machines.Gerard Casey - 1992 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 66 (1):57-80.
    The emergence of electronic computers in the last thirty years has given rise to many interesting questions. Many of these questions are technical, relating to a machine’s ability to perform complex operations in a variety of circumstances. While some of these questions are not without philosophical interest, the one question which above all others has stimulated philosophical interest is explicitly non-technical and it can be expressed crudely as follows: Can a machine be said to think and, if so, in what (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A different view of numerical processes in animals.E. J. Capaldi & Daniel J. Miller - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):582-583.
  • Subitizing and rhythm in serial numerical investigations with animals.Richard A. Burns - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):581-582.
  • Double dissociation, modularity, and distributed organization.John A. Bullinaria & Nick Chater - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):632-632.
    Müller argues that double dissociations do not imply underlying modularity of the cognitive system, citing neural networks as examples of fully distributed systems that can give rise to double dissociations. We challenge this claim, noting that suchdouble dissociations typically do not “scale-up,” and that even some singledissociations can be difficult to account for in a distributed system.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Linguistic function and linguistic evolution.George A. Broadwell - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):728-729.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Protocounting as a last resort.Richard F. Braaten - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):581-581.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kanting processes in the chimpanzee: What really counts?Sarah T. Boysen - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):580-580.
  • What does language acquisition tell us about language evolution?Paul Bloom - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):553-554.
  • Syntax is not as simple as it seems.Derek Bickerton - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):552-553.
  • An innate language faculty needs neither modularity nor localization.Derek Bickerton - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):631-632.
    Müller misconstrues autonomy to mean strict locality of brain function, something quite different from the functional autonomy that linguists claim. Similarly, he misperceives the interaction of learned and innate components hypothesized in current generative models. Evidence from sign languages, Creole languages, and neurological studies of rare forms of aphasia also argues against his conclusions.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive Relatives yet Moral Strangers?Judith Benz-Schwarzburg & Andrew Knight - 2011 - Journal of Animal Ethics 1 (1):9-36.
    This article provides an empirically based, interdisciplinary approach to the following two questions: Do animals possess behavioral and cognitive characteristics such as culture, language, and a theory of mind? And if so, what are the implications, when long-standing criteria used to justify differences in moral consideration between humans and animals are no longer considered indisputable? One basic implication is that the psychological needs of captive animals should be adequately catered for. However, for species such as great apes and dolphins with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Cognitive ethology: Theory or poetry?Jonathan Bennett - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):356-358.
  • Rationality: putting the issue to the scientific community.John Beatty - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):355-356.
  • Welcome to functionalism.Elizabeth Bates & Brian MacWhinney - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):727-728.
  • Making the best use of primate tool use?James R. Anderson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):551-552.
  • Nonhuman intentional systems.H. S. Terrace - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):378-379.
  • A better way to deal with selection.B. F. Skinner - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):377-378.
  • Steps toward an ethological science.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):377-377.
  • Content and consciousness versus the International stance.Alexander Rosenberg - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):375-376.
  • Intentions and adaptations.H. L. Roitblat - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):375-375.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • International plovers or just dump brids?Carolyn A. Ristau - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):373-375.
  • The International stance faces backward.Howard Rachlin - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):373-373.
  • Dennett's rational animals: And how behavorism overlooked them.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):372-373.
  • Parlez-vous baboon, Bwana Sherlock?E. W. Menzel - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):371-372.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adaptation and satisficing.John Maynard Smith - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):370-371.
  • Intentions as goads.David McFarland - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):369-370.
  • The scope and ingenuity of evolutionary systems.Dan Lloyd - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):368-369.
  • Elementary errors about evolution.Richard C. Lewontin - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):367-368.
  • Dennett' “Panglossian paradigm”.Alison Jolly - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):366-367.
  • The adaptiveness_ of _mentalism?.Nicholas Humphrey - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):366-366.
  • Belief accripton, parsimony, and rationality.John Hell - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):365-366.
  • Adaptationist theorizing and intentional system theory.Gilbert Harman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):365-365.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thinking about animal thoughts.Donald R. Griffin - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):364-364.
  • Denoting and demoting international systems.George Graham - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):363-364.
  • Lloyd Morgan's canon in evolutionary context.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):362-363.
  • A la recherche du docteur Pangloss.Niles Eldredge - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):361-362.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The epigenesis of regional specificity.Ralph-Axel Müller - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):650-675.
    Chomskyian claims of a genetically hard-wired and cognitively autonomous “universal grammar” are being promoted by generative linguistics as facts about language to the present day. The related doctrine of an evolutionary discontinuity in language emergence, however, is based on misconceptions about the notions of homology and preadaptation. The obvious lack of equivalence between symbolic communicative capacities in existing nonhuman primates and human language does not preclude common roots. Normal and disordered language development is strongly influenced by the genome, but there (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark