Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Concepts of science.Peter Achinstein - 1968 - Baltimore,: Johns Hopkins University Press.
    In this systematic study, Professor Achinstein analyzes such concepts as definitions, theories, and models, and contrasts his view with currently held positions that he finds inadequate.
  • The Eighth Day of Creation: Makers of the Revolution in Biology.[author unknown] - 1980 - Journal of the History of Biology 13 (1):141-158.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • The Dappled World. A Study on the Boundaries of Science.[author unknown] - 1999 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 63 (1):209-209.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • Concepts of Science: A Philosophical Analysis.[author unknown] - 1971 - Synthese 22 (3-4):488-493.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Experiments, Models, Paper Tools: Cultures of Organic Chemistry in the Nineteenth Century.Ursula Klein - 2003 - Stanford: Stanford University Press.
    In the early nineteenth century, chemistry emerged in Europe as a truly experimental discipline. What set this process in motion, and how did it evolve? Experimentalization in chemistry was driven by a seemingly innocuous tool: the sign system of chemical formulas invented by the Swedish chemist Jacob Berzelius. By tracing the history of this “paper tool,” the author reveals how chemistry quickly lost its orientation to natural history and became a major productive force in industrial society. These formulas were not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Models and metaphors.Max Black - 1962 - Ithaca, N.Y.,: Cornell University Press.
    Author Max Black argues that language should conform to the discovered regularities of experience it is radically mistaken to assume that the conception of language is a mirror of reality.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   261 citations  
  • Models and metaphors.Max Black - 1962 - Ithaca, N.Y.,: Cornell University Press.
    Author Max Black argues that language should conform to the discovered regularities of experience it is radically mistaken to assume that the conception of language is a mirror of reality.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   277 citations  
  • Who is a Modeler?Michael Weisberg - 2007 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (2):207-233.
    Many standard philosophical accounts of scientific practice fail to distinguish between modeling and other types of theory construction. This failure is unfortunate because there are important contrasts among the goals, procedures, and representations employed by modelers and other kinds of theorists. We can see some of these differences intuitively when we reflect on the methods of theorists such as Vito Volterra and Linus Pauling on the one hand, and Charles Darwin and Dimitri Mendeleev on the other. Much of Volterra's and (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • The Scientific Image by Bas C. van Fraassen. [REVIEW]Michael Friedman - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (5):274-283.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   919 citations  
  • A comparison of the meaning and uses of models in mathematics and the empirical sciences.Patrick Suppes - 1960 - Synthese 12 (2-3):287--301.
  • Use-novel predictions and Mendeleev’s periodic table: response to Scerri and Worrall.Samuel Schindler - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 39 (2):265-269.
    In this paper I comment on a recent paper by [Scerri, E., & Worrall, J. . Prediction and the periodic table. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 32, 407–452.] about the role temporally novel and use-novel predictions played in the acceptance of Mendeleev’s periodic table after the proposal of the latter in 1869. Scerri and Worrall allege that whereas temporally novel predictions—despite Brush’s earlier claim to the contrary—did not carry any special epistemic weight, use-novel predictions did indeed contribute to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Rehabilitating theory: refusal of the 'bottom-up' construction of scientific phenomena.Samuel Schindler - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 38 (1):160-184.
    In this paper I inquire into Bogen and Woodward’s data/phenomena distinction, which in a similar way to Cartwright’s construal of the model of superconductivity —although in a different domain—argues for a ‘bottom-up’ construction of phenomena from data without the involvement of theory. I criticise Bogen and Woodward’s account by analysing their melting point of lead example in depth, which is usually cited in the literature to illustrate the data/phenomenon distinction. Yet, the main focus of this paper lies on Matthias Kaiser’s (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Van Fraassen's Critique Of Inference To The Best Explanation.Samir Okasha - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 31 (4):691-710.
  • A material theory of induction.John D. Norton - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (4):647-670.
    Contrary to formal theories of induction, I argue that there are no universal inductive inference schemas. The inductive inferences of science are grounded in matters of fact that hold only in particular domains, so that all inductive inference is local. Some are so localized as to defy familiar characterization. Since inductive inference schemas are underwritten by facts, we can assess and control the inductive risk taken in an induction by investigating the warrant for its underwriting facts. In learning more facts, (...)
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • Saving Unobservable Phenomena.Michela Massimi - 2007 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (2):235-262.
    In this paper I argue-against van Fraassen's constructive empiricism-that the practice of saving phenomena is much broader than usually thought, and includes unobservable phenomena as well as observable ones. My argument turns on the distinction between data and phenomena: I discuss how unobservable phenomena manifest themselves in data models and how theoretical models able to save them are chosen. I present a paradigmatic case study taken from the history of particle physics to illustrate my argument. The first aim of this (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • How models are used to represent reality.Ronald N. Giere - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):742-752.
    Most recent philosophical thought about the scientific representation of the world has focused on dyadic relationships between language-like entities and the world, particularly the semantic relationships of reference and truth. Drawing inspiration from diverse sources, I argue that we should focus on the pragmatic activity of representing, so that the basic representational relationship has the form: Scientists use models to represent aspects of the world for specific purposes. Leaving aside the terms "law" and "theory," I distinguish principles, specific conditions, models, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   301 citations  
  • Superconductivity and structures: revisiting the London account.Steven French & James Ladyman - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 28 (3):363-393.
    Cartwright and her collaborators have elaborated a provocative view of science which emphasises the independence from theory &unknown;in methods and aims&unknown; of phenomenological model building. This thesis has been supported in a recent paper by an analysis of the London and London model of superconductivity. In the present work we begin with a critique of Cartwright's account of the relationship between theoretical and phenomenological models before elaborating an alternative picture within the framework of the partial structures version of the semantic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Selectivity and Discord: Two Problems of Experiment.Allan Franklin - 2002 - University of Pittsburgh Press.
    Specifically, Allan Franklin is concerned with two problems in the use of experimental results in science: selectivity of data or analysis procedures and the resolution of discordant results.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Saving the phenomena.James Bogen & James Woodward - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (3):303-352.
  • Models and Metaphors: Studies in Language and Philosophy.William Sacksteder - 1962 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 23 (2):289-290.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Models And Metaphors.Douglas Odegard - 1964 - Philosophy 39 (150):349-356.
    Like his earlier Language and Philosophy. and Problems of Analysis, Models and Metaphors is a collection of Black's papers unified by the belief that linguistic considerations can play an important part in framing and solving philosophical problems. Broadly speaking, the linguistic approach takes two forms: examining the uses of a word, or of a set of related words, frequently occurring in philosophical inquiries, either for the general purposes of clarification or as a useful aid to the solution, or dissolution, of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The scientific imagination: case studies.Gerald James Holton - 1978 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Using firsthand accounts gleaned from notebooks, interviews, and correspondence of such twentieth-century scientists as Einstein, Fermi, and Millikan, Holton shows how the idea of the scientific imagination has practical implications for the history and philosophy of science and the larger understanding of the place of science in our culture.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • I Wish I'd Made You Angry Earlier: Essays on Science, Scientists, and Humanity.Max F. Perutz & Max Ferdinand Perutz - 2002 - Oxford University Press USA.
    This collection of essays from Nobel Laureate Max Perutz explores a wide range of scientific and personal topics with insight and lucidity. It includes lively anecdotes about key figures in 20th-century science.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The scientific imagination: with a new introduction.Gerald James Holton - 1978 - Cambridge, Ma.: Harvard University Press.
    In this book Gerald Holton takes an opposing view, illuminating the ways in which the imagination of the scientist functions early in the formation of a new ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science.Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison (eds.) - 1999 - Cambridge University Press.
    Models as Mediators discusses the ways in which models function in modern science, particularly in the fields of physics and economics. Models play a variety of roles in the sciences: they are used in the development, exploration and application of theories and in measurement methods. They also provide instruments for using scientific concepts and principles to intervene in the world. The editors provide a framework which covers the construction and function of scientific models, and explore the ways in which they (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   350 citations  
  • Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce: Pragmatism and pragmaticism and Scientific metaphysics.Charles Sanders Peirce - 1960 - Cambridge: Belknap Press.
    Charles Sanders Peirce has been characterized as the greatest American philosophic genius. He is the creator of pragmatism and one of the founders of modern logic. James, Royce, Schroder, and Dewey have acknowledged their great indebtedness to him. A laboratory scientist, he made notable contributions to geodesy, astronomy, psychology, induction, probability, and scientific method. He introduced into modern philosophy the doctrine of scholastic realism, developed the concepts of chance, continuity, and objective law, and showed the philosophical significance of the theory (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   507 citations  
  • The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science.Nancy Cartwright - 1999 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    It is often supposed that the spectacular successes of our modern mathematical sciences support a lofty vision of a world completely ordered by one single elegant theory. In this book Nancy Cartwright argues to the contrary. When we draw our image of the world from the way modern science works - as empiricism teaches us we should - we end up with a world where some features are precisely ordered, others are given to rough regularity and still others behave in (...)
  • Tracing the Development of Models in the Philosophy of Science.Daniela M. Bailer-Jones - 1999 - In L. Magnani, N. J. Nersessian & P. Thagard (eds.), Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery. Kluwer/Plenum. pp. 23--40.
  • Models and stories in Hadron physics.Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison - 1999 - In Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison (eds.), Models as Mediators. pp. 326-346.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Models and the limits of theory: quantum hamiltonians and the BCS model of superconductivity.Nancy Cartwright - 1999 - In Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison (eds.), Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge University Press. pp. 241-281.
  • The role of models in the application of scientific theories: epistemological implications.Mauricio Suárez - 1999 - In Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison (eds.), Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce.Charles Sanders Peirce, Charles Hartshorne & Paul Weiss - 1933 - International Journal of Ethics 43 (2):220-226.
  • Scientific Models.Stephan Hartmann & Roman Frigg - 2005 - In Sarkar Sahotra (ed.), The Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia, Vol. 2. Routledge.
    Models are of central importance in many scientific contexts. The roles the MIT bag model of the nucleon, the billiard ball model of a gas, the Bohr model of the atom, the Gaussian-chain model of a polymer, the Lorenz model of the atmosphere, the Lotka- Volterra model of predator-prey interaction, agent-based and evolutionary models of social interaction, or general equilibrium models of markets play in their respective domains are cases in point.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • .Michela Massimi & Angela Breitenbach - 2017
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science.Nancy Cartwright - 2002 - Noûs 36 (4):699-725.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   265 citations  
  • The tool box of science: Tools for the building of models with a superconductivity example.Nancy Cartwright, Towfic Shomar & Mauricio Suárez - 1995 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 44:137-149.
    We call for a new philosophical conception of models in physics. Some standard conceptions take models to be useful approximations to theorems, that are the chief means to test theories. Hence the heuristics of model building is dictated by the requirements and practice of theory-testing. In this paper we argue that a theory-driven view of models can not account for common procedures used by scientists to model phenomena. We illustrate this thesis with a case study: the construction of one of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • New Pathways in Science.Arthur Eddington - 1935 - Philosophy 10 (40):483-485.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Concepts of Science.Peter Achinstein - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (187):106-108.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • The Scientific Imagination: Case Studies.Gerald Holton - 1980 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (2):193-195.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • A History of Molecular Biology.Michel Morange & Matthew Cobb - 1999 - Journal of the History of Biology 32 (3):568-570.
  • Rosalind Franklin: The Dark Lady of DNA.Brenda Maddox & Victor K. Mcelheny - 2003 - Journal of the History of Biology 36 (3):591-597.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations