Switch to: Citations

References in:

The Factory Model of Disease

The Monist 90 (4):555-584 (2007)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Health as a theoretical concept.Christopher Boorse - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (4):542-573.
    This paper argues that the medical conception of health as absence of disease is a value-free theoretical notion. Its main elements are biological function and statistical normality, in contrast to various other ideas prominent in the literature on health. Apart from universal environmental injuries, diseases are internal states that depress a functional ability below species-typical levels. Health as freedom from disease is then statistical normality of function, i.e., the ability to perform all typical physiological functions with at least typical efficiency. (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   550 citations  
  • Static And Dynamic Dispositions.Neil Edward Williams - 2005 - Synthese 146 (3):303-324.
    When it comes to scientific explanation, our parsimonious tendencies mean that we focus almost exclusively on those dispositions whose manifestations result in some sort of change – changes in properties, locations, velocities and so on. Following this tendency, our notion of causation is one that is inherently dynamic, as if the maintenance of the status quo were merely a given. Contrary to this position, I argue that a complete concept of causation must also account for dispositions whose manifestations involve no (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The myth of mental illness.Thomas S. Szasz - 2004 - In Arthur Caplan, James J. McCartney & Dominic A. Sisti (eds.), Ethics. Georgetown University Press. pp. 43--50.
  • Review of Thomas Szasz: The Myth of Mental Illness: Foundations of a Theory of Personal Conduct[REVIEW]Thomas S. Szasz - 1963 - Ethics 73 (2):145-147.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Health as an objective value.James G. Lennox - 1995 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 20 (5):499-511.
    Variants on two approaches to the concept of health have dominated the philosophy of medicine, here referred to as ‘reductionist’ and ‘relativis’. These two approaches share the basic assumption that the concept of health cannot be both based on an empirical biological foundation and be evaluative, and thus adopt either the view that it is ‘objective’ or evaluative. It is here argued that there are a subset of value concepts that are formed in recognition of certain fundamental facts about living (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • What is disease?Lester S. King - 1954 - Philosophy of Science 21 (3):193-203.
    Biological science does not try to distinguish between health and disease. Biology is concerned with the interaction between living organisms and their environment. What we call health or disease is quite irrelevant.These reactions between the individual and his environment are complex. The individual and his surroundings form an integrated system which we can arbitrarily divide into two parts. There is an “external” component, by which we mean such factors as light, heat, percentage of oxygen in the air, quantity of minerals (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • From an ontological point of view.John Heil - 2003 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    From an Ontological Point of View is a highly original and accessible exploration of fundamental questions about what there is. John Heil discusses such issues as whether the world includes levels of reality; the nature of objects and properties; the demands of realism; what makes things true; qualities, powers, and the relation these bear to one another. He advances an account of the fundamental constituents of the world around us, and applies this account to problems that have plagued recent work (...)
  • Wright on functions.Christopher Boorse - 1976 - Philosophical Review 85 (1):70-86.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   201 citations  
  • The nature of disease.Lawrie Reznek - 1987 - New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Concepts of health and disease: interdisciplinary perspectives.Arthur L. Caplan, Hugo Tristram Engelhardt & James J. McCartney (eds.) - 1981 - Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, Advanced Book Program/World Science Division.
    The concepts of health and disease play pivotal roles in medicine and the health professions This volume brings together the requisite literature for understanding current discussions and debates these concepts. The selections in the volume attempt to present a wide range of views concerning the nature of the concepts of health and issues using both historical and contemporary sources -- Back cover.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Power for realists.Charles B. Martin - 1993 - In Keith Cambell, John Bacon & Lloyd Reinhardt (eds.), Ontology, Causality, and Mind: Essays on the Philosophy of D. M. Armstrong. Cambridge University Press. pp. 175-786.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • From an Ontological Point of View.John Heil - 2003 - Philosophy 79 (309):491-494.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   380 citations  
  • The concept of disease: Structure and change.Paul Thagard - 1996 - Communication and Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Journal 29 (3/4):445-478.
    By contrasting Hippocratic and nineteenth century theories of disease, this paper describes important conceptual changes that have taken place in the history of medicine. Disease concepts are presented as causal networks that represent the relations among the symptoms, causes, and treatment of a disease. The transition to the germ theory of disease produced dramatic conceptual changes as the result of a radically new view of disease causation. An analogy between disease and fermentation was important for two of the main developers (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Do we need a concept of disease?Germund Hesslow - 1993 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 14 (1).
    The terms health, disease and illness are frequently used in clinical medicine. This has misled philosophers into believing that these concepts are important for clinical thinking and decision making. For instance, it is held that decisions about whether or not to treat someone or whether to relieve someone of moral responsibility depend on whether the person has a disease. In this paper it is argued that the crucial role of the disease concept is illusory. The health/disease distinction is irrelevant for (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Do We Need a Concept of Disease?Germund Hesslow - 1993 - Theoretical Medicine: An International Journal for the Philosophy and Methodology of Medical Research and Practice 14 (1):1-14.
    The terms "health", "disease" and "illness" are frequently used in clinical medicine. This has misled philosophers into believing that these concepts are important for clinical thinking and decision making. For instance, it is held that decisions about whether or not to treat someone or whether to relieve someone of moral responsibility depend on whether the person has a disease. In this paper it is argued that the crucial role of the 'disease' concept is illusory. The health/disease distinction is irrelevant for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • The Unnaturalness of Aging: A Sickness unto Death?Arthur L. Caplan - 1981 - In Arthur L. Caplan, H. Tristram Engelhardt & James J. McCartney (eds.), Concepts of Health and Disease: Interdisciplinary Perspectives. Addison-Wesley, Advanced Book Program/World Science Division. pp. 725--737.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations