Results for 'C. McLarty'

970 found
Order:
  1. Exploring Categorical Structuralism.C. Mclarty - 2004 - Philosophia Mathematica 12 (1):37-53.
    Hellman [2003] raises interesting challenges to categorical structuralism. He starts citing Awodey [1996] which, as Hellman sees, is not intended as a foundation for mathematics. It offers a structuralist framework which could denned in any of many different foundations. But Hellman says Awodey's work is 'naturally viewed in the context of Mac Lane's repeated claim that category theory provides an autonomous foundation for mathematics as an alternative to set theory' (p. 129). Most of Hellman's paper 'scrutinizes the formulation of category (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  2. What structuralism achieves.C. McLarty - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford University Press. pp. 354--369.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  3. Categorical Foundations and Mathematical Practice.C. McLarty - 2012 - Philosophia Mathematica 20 (1):111-113.
    Linnebo and Pettigrew's critique in this journal of categorical foundations well emphasizes that the particulars of various categorical foundations matter, and that mathematical practice must be a major consideration. But several categorists named by the authors as proposing categorical foundations do not propose foundations, notably Awodey, and the article's description of current textbook practice seems inaccurate. They say that categorical foundations have justificatory autonomy if and only if mathematics can be justified simply by its practice. Do they seriously believe philosophers (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  40
    Introduction: Hypotheses and Progress.C. McLarty - 2012 - Philosophia Mathematica 20 (2):135-142.
    The unifying theme of this issue is Plato’s dialectical view of mathematical progress and hypotheses. Besides provisional propositions, he calls concepts and goals also hypotheses. He knew mathematicians create new concepts and goals as well as theorems, and abandon many along the way, and erase the creative process from their proofs. So the hypotheses of mathematics necessarily change through use — unless Benson is correct that Plato believed mathematics could reach the unhypothetical goals of dialectic. Landry discusses Plato on mathematical (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Penelope Maddy. Defending the Axioms: On the Philosophical Foundations of Set Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011. ISBN 978-0-19-959618-8 (hbk); 978-0-19-967148-9 (pbk). Pp. x + 150. [REVIEW]C. McLarty - 2013 - Philosophia Mathematica 21 (3):385-392.
  6.  40
    Saunders Mac Lane. Saunders Mac Lane: A mathematical autobiography.Colin McLarty - 2007 - Philosophia Mathematica 15 (3):400-404.
    We are used to seeing foundations linked to the mainstream mathematics of the late nineteenth century: the arithmetization of analysis, non-Euclidean geometry, and the rise of abstract structures in algebra. And a growing number of case studies bring a more philosophy-of-science viewpoint to the latest mathematics, as in [Carter, 2005; Corfield, 2006; Krieger, 2003; Leng, 2002]. Mac Lane's autobiography is a valuable bridge between these, recounting his experience of how the mid- and late-twentieth-century mainstream grew especially through Hilbert's school.An autobiography (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Fermat’s Last Theorem.Colin McLarty - 2024 - In Bharath Sriraman (ed.), Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Cham: Springer. pp. 2011-2033.
    For 300 years, Fermat’s Last Theorem seemed to be pure arithmetic little connected even to other problems in arithmetic. But the last decades of the twentieth century saw the discovery of very special cubic curves, and the rise of the huge theoretical Langlands Program. The Langlands perspective showed those curves are so special they cannot exist, and thus proved Fermat’s Last Theorem. With many great contributors, the proof ended in a deep and widely applicable geometric result relating nice curves in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  12
    Voir-Dire in the Case of Mathematical Progress.Colin McLarty - 2000 - In Emily Grosholz & Herbert Breger (eds.), The growth of mathematical knowledge. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 269--280.
  9.  54
    Book review: John Bell. Introduction to toposes and local set theory. [REVIEW]Colin McLarty - 1989 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 31 (1):150-161.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  18
    J. P. Mayberry, _The Foundations Of Mathematics In The Theory Of Sets. Encyclopedia Of Mathematics And Its Applications Ser._ , Vol. 82. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (2000), xx+429 pp., index, cloth $80.00 (cloth). [REVIEW]Colin McLarty - 2002 - Philosophy of Science 69 (2):404-406.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. What does it take to prove fermat's last theorem? Grothendieck and the logic of number theory.Colin McLarty - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (3):359-377.
    This paper explores the set theoretic assumptions used in the current published proof of Fermat's Last Theorem, how these assumptions figure in the methods Wiles uses, and the currently known prospects for a proof using weaker assumptions.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  12. Numbers can be just what they have to.Colin McLarty - 1993 - Noûs 27 (4):487-498.
  13.  43
    2000-2001 Spring Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic.Michael Detlefsen, Erich Reck, Colin McLarty, Rohit Parikh, Larry Moss, Scott Weinstein, Gabriel Uzquiano, Grigori Mints & Richard Zach - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):413-419.
  14.  17
    Raymond J. Nelson 1917-1997.Chin-Tai Kim & Colin McLarty - 1997 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 71 (2):125 - 126.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. The uses and abuses of the history of topos theory.Colin Mclarty - 1990 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (3):351-375.
    The view that toposes originated as generalized set theory is a figment of set theoretically educated common sense. This false history obstructs understanding of category theory and especially of categorical foundations for mathematics. Problems in geometry, topology, and related algebra led to categories and toposes. Elementary toposes arose when Lawvere's interest in the foundations of physics and Tierney's in the foundations of topology led both to study Grothendieck's foundations for algebraic geometry. I end with remarks on a categorical view of (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  16.  27
    Book Review: Shaughan Lavine. Understanding the Infinite. [REVIEW]Colin McLarty - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (2):314-324.
  17.  20
    Mathematics: Form and Function by Saunders MacLane. [REVIEW]Colin McLarty - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (1):33-37.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Games and the art of agency.C. Thi Nguyen - 2019 - Philosophical Review 128 (4):423-462.
    Games may seem like a waste of time, where we struggle under artificial rules for arbitrary goals. The author suggests that the rules and goals of games are not arbitrary at all. They are a way of specifying particular modes of agency. This is what make games a distinctive art form. Game designers designate goals and abilities for the player; they shape the agential skeleton which the player will inhabit during the game. Game designers work in the medium of agency. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  19.  19
    Elementary Categories, Elementary Toposes.Colin McLarty - 1991 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Now available in paperback, this acclaimed book introduces categories and elementary toposes in a manner requiring little mathematical background. It defines the key concepts and gives complete elementary proofs of theorems, including the fundamental theorem of toposes and the sheafification theorem. It ends with topos theoretic descriptions of sets, of basic differential geometry, and of recursive analysis.
  20. Axiomatizing a category of categories.Colin McLarty - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1243-1260.
    Elementary axioms describe a category of categories. Theorems of category theory follow, including some on adjunctions and triples. A new result is that associativity of composition in categories follows from cartesian closedness of the category of categories. The axioms plus an axiom of infinity are consistent iff the axioms for a well-pointed topos with separation axiom and natural numbers are. The theory is not finitely axiomatizable. Each axiom is independent of the others. Further independence and definability results are proved. Relations (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  21. Autonomy and Aesthetic Engagement.C. Thi Nguyen - 2019 - Mind 129 (516):1127-1156.
    There seems to be a deep tension between two aspects of aesthetic appreciation. On the one hand, we care about getting things right. On the other hand, we demand autonomy. We want appreciators to arrive at their aesthetic judgments through their own cognitive efforts, rather than deferring to experts. These two demands seem to be in tension; after all, if we want to get the right judgments, we should defer to the judgments of experts. The best explanation, I suggest, is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  22. Cognitive islands and runaway echo chambers: problems for epistemic dependence on experts.C. Thi Nguyen - 2020 - Synthese 197 (7):2803-2821.
    I propose to study one problem for epistemic dependence on experts: how to locate experts on what I will call cognitive islands. Cognitive islands are those domains for knowledge in which expertise is required to evaluate other experts. They exist under two conditions: first, that there is no test for expertise available to the inexpert; and second, that the domain is not linked to another domain with such a test. Cognitive islands are the places where we have the fewest resources (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  23.  91
    ‘Mathematical Platonism’ Versus Gathering the Dead: What Socrates teaches Glaucon &dagger.Colin McLarty - 2005 - Philosophia Mathematica 13 (2):115-134.
    Glaucon in Plato's _Republic_ fails to grasp intermediates. He confuses pursuing a goal with achieving it, and so he adopts ‘mathematical platonism’. He says mathematical objects are eternal. Socrates urges a seriously debatable, and seriously defensible, alternative centered on the destruction of hypotheses. He offers his version of geometry and astronomy as refuting the charge that he impiously ‘ponders things up in the sky and investigates things under the earth and makes the weaker argument the stronger’. We relate his account (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  24. The last mathematician from Hilbert's göttingen: Saunders Mac Lane as philosopher of mathematics.Colin McLarty - 2007 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (1):77-112.
    While Saunders Mac Lane studied for his D.Phil in Göttingen, he heard David Hilbert's weekly lectures on philosophy, talked philosophy with Hermann Weyl, and studied it with Moritz Geiger. Their philosophies and Emmy Noether's algebra all influenced his conception of category theory, which has become the working structure theory of mathematics. His practice has constantly affirmed that a proper large-scale organization for mathematics is the most efficient path to valuable specific results—while he sees that the question of which results are (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  25. Learning from questions on categorical foundations.Colin McLarty - 2005 - Philosophia Mathematica 13 (1):44-60.
    We can learn from questions as well as from their answers. This paper urges some things to learn from questions about categorical foundations for mathematics raised by Geoffrey Hellman and from ones he invokes from Solomon Feferman.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  26. Fluid Mechanics for Philosophers, or Which Solutions Do You Want for Navier-Stokes?Colin McLarty - 2023 - In Lydia Patton & Erik Curiel (eds.), Working Toward Solutions in Fluid Dynamics and Astrophysics: What the Equations Don’t Say. Springer Verlag. pp. 31-56.
    Of the seven $1,000,000 Clay Millennium Prize Problems in mathematics, just one would immediately appeal to Leonard Euler. That is “Existence and Smoothness of the Navier-Stokes Equation” (Fefferman 2000). Euler gave the basic equation in the 1750s. The work to this day shows Euler’s intuitive, vividly physical sense of mathematics.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  42
    Animal Rights and the Duty to Harm: When to be a Harm Causing Deontologist.C. E. Abbate - 2020 - Zeitschrift Für Ethik Und Moralphilosophie 3 (1):5-26.
    An adequate theory of rights ought to forbid the harming of animals to promote trivial interests of humans, as is often done in the animal-user industries. But what should the rights view say about situations in which harming some animals is necessary to prevent intolerable injustices to other animals? I develop an account of respectful treatment on which, under certain conditions, it’s justified to intentionally harm some individuals to prevent serious harm to others. This can be compatible with recognizing the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  99
    Poincaré: Mathematics & logic & intuition.Colin Mclarty - 1997 - Philosophia Mathematica 5 (2):97-115.
    often insisted existence in mathematics means logical consistency, and formal logic is the sole guarantor of rigor. The paper joins this to his view of intuition and his own mathematics. It looks at predicativity and the infinite, Poincaré's early endorsement of the axiom of choice, and Cantor's set theory versus Zermelo's axioms. Poincaré discussed constructivism sympathetically only once, a few months before his death, and conspicuously avoided committing himself. We end with Poincaré on Couturat, Russell, and Hilbert.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29. Value Capture.C. Thi Nguyen - forthcoming - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy.
    Value capture occurs when an agent’s values are rich and subtle; they enter a social environment that presents simplified — typically quantified — versions of those values; and those simplified articulations come to dominate their practical reasoning. Examples include becoming motivated by FitBit’s step counts, Twitter Likes and Re-tweets, citation rates, ranked lists of best schools, and Grade Point Averages. We are vulnerable to value capture because of the competitive advantage that such crisp and clear expressions of value have in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Moral outrage porn.C. Thi Nguyen & Bekka Williams - 2020 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 18 (2):147-72.
    We offer an account of the generic use of the term “porn”, as seen in recent usages such as “food porn” and “real estate porn”. We offer a definition adapted from earlier accounts of sexual pornography. On our account, a representation is used as generic porn when it is engaged with primarily for the sake of a gratifying reaction, freed from the usual costs and consequences of engaging with the represented content. We demonstrate the usefulness of the concept of generic (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  31.  69
    Defining sets as sets of points of spaces.Colin McLarty - 1988 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 17 (1):75 - 90.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32.  54
    Anti-foundation and self-reference.Colin McLarty - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (1):19 - 28.
    This note argues against Barwise and Etchemendy's claim that their semantics for self-reference requires use of Aczel's anti-foundational set theory, AFA, semantics for self-reference requires use of Aczel's anti-foundational set theory, AFA, ones irrelevant to the task at hand" (The Liar, p. 35). Switching from ZF to AFA neither adds nor precludes any isomorphism types of sets. So it makes no difference to ordinary mathematics. I argue against the author's claim that a certain kind of 'naturalness' nevertheless makes AFA preferable (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33.  17
    Structuralism in differential equations.Colin McLarty - 2024 - Synthese 203 (3):1-15.
    Structuralism in philosophy of mathematics has largely focused on arithmetic, algebra, and basic analysis. Some have doubted whether distinctively structural working methods have any impact in other fields such as differential equations. We show narrowly construed structuralism as offered by Benacerraf has no practical role in differential equations. But Dedekind’s approach to the continuum already did not fit that narrow sense, and little of mathematics today does. We draw on one calculus textbook, one celebrated analysis textbook, and a monograph on (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  59
    Foundations as truths which organize mathematics.Colin Mclarty - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (1):76-86.
    The article looks briefly at Fefermans own foundations. Among many different senses of foundations, the one that mathematics needs in practice is a recognized body of truths adequate to organize definitions and proofs. Finding concise principles of this kind has been a huge achievement by mathematicians and logicians. We put ZFC and categorical foundations both into this context.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  50
    Failure of cartesian closedness in NF.Colin McLarty - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (2):555-556.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36.  46
    The large structures of grothendieck founded on finite-order arithmetic.Colin Mclarty - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):296-325.
    The large-structure tools of cohomology including toposes and derived categories stay close to arithmetic in practice, yet published foundations for them go beyond ZFC in logical strength. We reduce the gap by founding all the theorems of Grothendieck’s SGA, plus derived categories, at the level of Finite-Order Arithmetic, far below ZFC. This is the weakest possible foundation for the large-structure tools because one elementary topos of sets with infinity is already this strong.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Comparing Lives and Epistemic Limitations: A Critique of Regan's Lifeboat from An Unprivileged Position.C. E. Abbate - 2015 - Ethics and the Environment 20 (1):1-21.
    In The Case for Animal Rights, Tom Regan argues that although all subjects-of-a-life have equal inherent value, there are often differences in the value of lives. According to Regan, lives that have the highest value are lives which have more possible sources of satisfaction. Regan claims that the highest source of satisfaction, which is available to only rational beings, is the satisfaction associated with thinking impartially about moral choices. Since rational beings can bring impartial reasons to bear on decision making, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38. Philosophy of games.C. Thi Nguyen - 2017 - Philosophy Compass 12 (8):e12426.
    What is a game? What are we doing when we play a game? What is the value of playing games? Several different philosophical subdisciplines have attempted to answer these questions using very distinctive frameworks. Some have approached games as something like a text, deploying theoretical frameworks from the study of narrative, fiction, and rhetoric to interrogate games for their representational content. Others have approached games as artworks and asked questions about the authorship of games, about the ontology of the work (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  39.  6
    Принцип субсидіарності: Уроки соціального вчительства католицької церкви.Cергій Присухін - 2018 - Ukrainian Religious Studies 86:42-48.
    Анотація. У статті проаналізовані досягнення Соціального Вчительства Католицької Церкви, репрезентовані працями Лева ХІІІ, Пія ХІ, Пія ХІІ, Івана Павла ІІ, що розкривають змістовні характеристики поняття «принцип субсидіарності», його роль і значення в системі християнських цінностей. Принцип субсидіарності робить можливими такі взаємовідносини в соціальному житті, коли спільнота вищого порядку не втручається у внутрішнє життя спільноти нижчого порядку, перебираючи на себе належні тій функції; заради спільного добра, спільного блага вона надає їй у разі потреби підтримку й допомогу, узгоджуючи у такий спосіб її (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40. Philosophical Relevance of Category Theory.Colin McLarty - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  28
    Elaine Landry.*Plato Was Not a Mathematical Platonist.Colin McLarty - 2023 - Philosophia Mathematica 31 (3):417-424.
    This book goes far beyond its title. Landry indeed surveys current definitions of “mathematical platonism” to show nothing like them applies to Socrates in Plat.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Transparency is Surveillance.C. Thi Nguyen - 2021 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 105 (2):331-361.
    In her BBC Reith Lectures on Trust, Onora O’Neill offers a short, but biting, criticism of transparency. People think that trust and transparency go together but in reality, says O'Neill, they are deeply opposed. Transparency forces people to conceal their actual reasons for action and invent different ones for public consumption. Transparency forces deception. I work out the details of her argument and worsen her conclusion. I focus on public transparency – that is, transparency to the public over expert domains. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  43.  90
    Category theory in real time.Colin Mclarty - 1994 - Philosophia Mathematica 2 (1):36-44.
    The article surveys some past and present debates within mathematics over the meaning of category theory. It argues that such conceptual analyses, applied to a field still under active development, must be in large part either predictions of, or calls for, certain programs of further work.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. Emmy Noether's “set theoretic” topology: From Dedekind to the first functors.Colin McLarty - 2006 - In José Ferreirós Domínguez & Jeremy Gray (eds.), The Architecture of Modern Mathematics: Essays in History and Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 187--208.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  25
    Two Constructivist Aspects of Category Theory.Colin McLarty - 2006 - Philosophia Scientiae:95-114.
    Category theory has two unexpected links to constructivism: First, why is topos logic so close to intuitionistic logic? The paper argues that in part the resemblance is superficial, in part it is due to selective attention, and in part topos theory is objectively tied to the motives for later intuitionistic logic little related to Brouwer’s own stated motives. Second, why is so much of general category theory somehow constructive? The paper aims to synthesize three hypotheses on why it would be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  18
    Two Constructivist Aspects of Category Theory.Colin McLarty - 2006 - Philosophia Scientiae:95-114.
    Category theory has two unexpected links to constructivism: First, why is topos logic so close to intuitionistic logic? The paper argues that in part the resemblance is superficial, in part it is due to selective attention, and in part topos theory is objectively tied to the motives for later intuitionistic logic little related to Brouwer’s own stated motives. Second, why is so much of general category theory somehow constructive? The paper aims to synthesize three hypotheses on why it would be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  75
    Assuming Risk: A Critical Analysis of a Soldier's Duty to Prevent Collateral Casualties.C. E. Abbate - 2014 - Journal of Military Ethics 13 (1):70-93.
    Recent discussions in the just war literature suggest that soldiers have a duty to assume certain risks in order to protect the lives of all innocent civilians. I challenge this principle of risk by arguing that it is justified neither as a principle that guides the conduct of combat soldiers, nor as a principle that guides commanders in the US military. I demonstrate that the principle of risk fails on the first account because it requires soldiers both to violate their (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  12
    Como Grothendieck simplificou a geometria algébrica.Colin McLarty & Norman R. Madarasz - 2016 - Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 61 (2):276-294.
    Alexandre Grothendieck foi um dos maiores matemáticos do século 20 e um dos mais atípicos. Nascido na Alemanha a um pai anarquista de origem russa, sua infância foi marcada pela militância política dos seus pais, assim passando por revoluções, guerras e sobrevivência. Descoberto por sua precocidade matemática por Henri Cartan, Grothendieck fez seu doutorado sob orientação de Laurent Schwartz e Jean Dieudonné. As principais contribuições dele são na área da topologia e na geometria algébrica, assim como na teoria das categorias. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  58
    Elementary axioms for canonical points of toposes.Colin McLarty - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):202-204.
  50.  18
    Emmy Noether’s first great mathematics and the culmination of first-phase logicism, formalism, and intuitionism.Colin McLarty - 2011 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 65 (1):99-117.
    Emmy Noether’s many articles around the time that Felix Klein and David Hilbert were arranging her invitation to Göttingen include a short but brilliant note on invariants of finite groups highlighting her creativity and perspicacity in algebra. Contrary to the idea that Noether abandoned Paul Gordan’s style of mathematics for Hilbert’s, this note shows her combining them in a way she continued throughout her mature abstract algebra.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 970