Switch to: References

Citations of:

Logic and existence

In Jan T. J. Srzednicki, V. F. Rickey & J. Czelakowski (eds.), British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. Distributors for the United States and Canada, Kluwer Boston. pp. 45--58 (1954)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Ontological Burden of Grammatical Categories.Toshiharu Waragai - 1979 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 5 (4):185-205.
  • Existentials and existents.Gerald Vision - 1981 - Theoria 47 (1):1-30.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Plural quantifiers: a modal interpretation.Rafal Urbaniak - 2014 - Synthese 191 (7):1-22.
    One of the standard views on plural quantification is that its use commits one to the existence of abstract objects–sets. On this view claims like ‘some logicians admire only each other’ involve ineliminable quantification over subsets of a salient domain. The main motivation for this view is that plural quantification has to be given some sort of semantics, and among the two main candidates—substitutional and set-theoretic—only the latter can provide the language of plurals with the desired expressive power (given that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Lesniewski and Russell's paradox: Some problems.Rafal Urbaniak - 2008 - History and Philosophy of Logic 29 (2):115-146.
    Sobocinski in his paper on Leśniewski's solution to Russell's paradox (1949b) argued that Leśniewski has succeeded in explaining it away. The general strategy of this alleged explanation is presented. The key element of this attempt is the distinction between the collective (mereological) and the distributive (set-theoretic) understanding of the set. The mereological part of the solution, although correct, is likely to fall short of providing foundations of mathematics. I argue that the remaining part of the solution which suggests a specific (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Subject and predicate.J. L. Shaw - 1976 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 4 (1-2):155-179.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Stanislaw Leśniewski's Logical Systems.John T. Sanders - 1996 - Axiomathes 7 (3):407-415.
    Stanislaw Lesniewski’s interests were, for the most part, more philosophical than mathematical. Prior to taking his doctorate at Jan Kazimierz University in Lvov, Lesniewski had spent time at several continental universities, apparently becoming relatively attached to the philosophy of one of his teachers, Hans Comelius, to the chapters of John Stuart Mill’s System of Logic that dealt specifically with semantics, and, in general, to studies of general grammar and philosophy of language. In these several early interests are already to be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Prior’s concept of possible worlds: Clasp between Wittgenstein and Warsaw´s School.Zuzana Rybaříková - 2015 - Pro-Fil 16 (1):30-43.
    Arthur Prior was one of the logicians who participated in the invention of the possible worlds’ semantics. The ontology, which is connected with his systems of modal logic, is unique. Prior tried to reduce the number of abstract entities as much as possible. Hence he did not elect to introduce possible worlds and possibilia into his ontology. In addition, he held a reductionist view, which is called modal actualism by Fine or modalism by Melia. Prior was inspired by various authors (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The logic of obligation and the obligations of the logician.A. N. Prior - 2012 - Synthese 188 (3):423-448.
  • A leśniewskian re-examination of Goodman's nominalistic rejection of classes.Judith M. Prakel - 1983 - Topoi 2 (1):87-98.
  • Irrational blame.Hanna Pickard - 2013 - Analysis 73 (4):613-626.
    I clarify some ambiguities in blame-talk and argue that blame's potential for irrationality and propensity to sting vitiates accounts of blame that identify it with consciously accessible, personal-level judgements or beliefs. Drawing on the cognitive psychology of emotion and appraisal theory, I develop an account of blame that accommodates these features. I suggest that blame consists in a range of hostile, negative first-order emotions, towards which the blamer has a specific, accompanying second-order attitude, namely, a feeling of entitlement—a feeling that (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The property-theoretical, performative-nominalistic theory of proper names.Francesco Orilia - 2000 - Dialectica 54 (3):155–176.
    This paper embeds a theory of proper names in a general approach to singular reference based on type‐free property theory. It is proposed that a proper name “N” is a sortal common noun whose meaning is essentially tied to the linguistic type “N”. Moreover, “N” can be singularly referring insofar as it is elliptical for a definite description of the form the “N” Following Montague, the meaning of a definite description is taken to be a property of properties. The proposed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Property‐theoretical, Performative‐nominalistic Theory of Proper Names.Francesco Orilia - 2000 - Dialectica 54 (3):155-176.
    This paper embeds a theory of proper names in a general approach to singular reference based on type‐free property theory. It is proposed that a proper name “N” is a sortal common noun whose meaning is essentially tied to the linguistic type “N”. Moreover, “N” can be singularly referring insofar as it is elliptical for a definite description of the form the “N” Following Montague, the meaning of a definite description is taken to be a property of properties. The proposed (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Zilch.Alex Oliver & Timothy Smiley - 2013 - Analysis 73 (4):601-613.
    We all learn about the mistake of treating ‘nothing’ as if it were a term standing for something; but is it a mistake to treat it as an empty term, denoting nothing? We argue not, and we introduce ‘zilch’, defined as ‘the non-self-identical thing’, as a term which is empty as a matter of logical necessity. We contrast its behaviour with that of the quantifier ‘nothing’, and illustrate its uses. We use the same idea to vindicate Locke’s, Descartes’ and Hume’s (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Aristotle's syllogistic and its extensions.Czes?aw Lejewski - 1963 - Synthese 15 (1):125 - 154.
  • A Re-examination of the Russellian Theory of Descriptions.Czeslaw Lejewski - 1960 - Philosophy 35 (132):14-29.
    The theory of descriptions occupies a very prominent place in Russell's system of logic and indeed in his system of philosophy. Since the publication of the now classical paper “On Denoting” in Mind for 1905 the theory had been incorporated into Principia Mathematica , the first volume of which appeared in 1910. In 1918 Russell discussed descriptions in his lectures on the Philosophy of Logical Atomism, which subsequently were published in The Monist for 1919. A very lucid exposition of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The meaning of the quantifiers in the logic of Leśniewski.Guido Küng - 1977 - Studia Logica 36 (4):309-322.
  • Medieval metaphysics and contemporary logical language.Desmond Paul Henry - 1982 - Topoi 1 (1-2):43-51.
  • Denotationless terms and predicates expressive of positive qualities.Rolf A. Eberle - 1969 - Theoria 35 (2):104-123.
  • Quantification and Metaphysical Discourse.Patrick Dieveney - 2013 - Theoria 80 (4):292-318.
    It is common in metaphysical discourse to make claims like “Everything is self-identical” in which “everything” is intended to range over everything. This sort of “unrestricted” generality appears central to metaphysical discourse. But there is debate whether such generality, which appears to involve quantification over an all-inclusive domain, is even meaningful. To address this concern, Shaughan Lavine and Vann McGee supply competing accounts of the generality expressed by this use of “everything.” I argue that, from the perspective of the metaphysician, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Leśniewski's Systems of Logic and Foundations of Mathematics.Rafal Urbaniak - 2013 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    With material on his early philosophical views, his contributions to set theory and his work on nominalism and higher-order quantification, this book offers a uniquely expansive critical commentary on one of analytical philosophy’s great ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Golden Age of Polish Philosophy. Kaziemierz Twardowski’s philosophical legacy.Sandra Lapointe, Jan Wolenski, Mathieu Marion & Wioletta Miskiewicz (eds.) - 2009 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This volume portrays the Polish or Lvov-Warsaw School, one of the most influential schools in analytic philosophy, which, as discussed in the thorough introduction, presented an alternative working picture of the unity of science.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Stanisław leśniewski.Peter Simons - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Free logic.John Nolt - 2021 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations