Results for 'Topological reduction theory'

999 found
Order:
  1.  23
    On a duality between Boolean valued analysis and topological Reduction Theory.Hirokazu Nishimura - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):23-32.
    By creating an unbounded topological reduction theory for complex Hilbert spaces over Stonean spaces, we can give a category-theoretic duality between Boolean valued analysis and topological reduction theory for complex Hilbert spaces. MSC: 03C90, 03E40, 06E15, 46M99.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  12
    Some connections between boolean valued analysis and topological reduction theory for C*‐algebras.Hirokazu Nishimura - 1990 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 36 (5):471-479.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  35
    Some connections between boolean valued analysis and topological reduction theory for C*-algebras.Hirokazu Nishimura - 1990 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 36 (5):471-479.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  11
    On numerical characterizations of the topological reduction of incomplete information systems based on evidence theory.Yanlan Zhang & Changqing Li - 2023 - Journal of Intelligent Systems 32 (1).
    Knowledge reduction of information systems is one of the most important parts of rough set theory in real-world applications. Based on the connections between the rough set theory and the theory of topology, a kind of topological reduction of incomplete information systems is discussed. In this study, the topological reduction of incomplete information systems is characterized by belief and plausibility functions from evidence theory. First, we present that a topological space (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  13
    On the forking topology of a reduct of a simple theory.Ziv Shami - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (3-4):313-324.
    Let T be a simple L-theory and let \ be a reduct of T to a sublanguage \ of L. For variables x, we call an \-invariant set \\) in \ a universal transducer if for every formula \\in L^-\) and every a, $$\begin{aligned} \phi ^-\ L^-\text{-forks } \text{ over }\ \emptyset \ \text{ iff } \Gamma \wedge \phi ^-\ L\text{-forks } \text{ over }\ \emptyset. \end{aligned}$$We show that there is a greatest universal transducer \ and it is type-definable. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  36
    Inverse topological systems and compactness in abstract model theory.Daniele Mundici - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):785-794.
    Given an abstract logic L = L(Q i ) i ∈ I generated by a set of quantifiers Q i , one can construct for each type τ a topological space S τ exactly as one constructs the Stone space for τ in first-order logic. Letting T be an arbitrary directed set of types, the set $S_T = \{(S_\tau, \pi^\tau_\sigma)\mid\sigma, \tau \in T, \sigma \subset \tau\}$ is an inverse topological system whose bonding mappings π τ σ are naturally (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  15
    Topological Models of Rough Sets and Decision Making of COVID-19.Mostafa A. El-Gayar & Abd El Fattah El Atik - 2022 - Complexity 2022:1-10.
    The basic methodology of rough set theory depends on an equivalence relation induced from the generated partition by the classification of objects. However, the requirements of the equivalence relation restrict the field of applications of this philosophy. To begin, we describe two kinds of closure operators that are based on right and left adhesion neighbourhoods by any binary relation. Furthermore, we illustrate that the suggested techniques are an extension of previous methods that are already available in the literature. As (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  20
    Topology and Morphogenesis.Xin Wei Sha - 2012 - Theory, Culture and Society 29 (4-5):220-246.
    One can use mathematics not as an instrument or measure, or a replacement for God, but as a poetic articulation, or perhaps as a stammered experimental approach to cultural dynamics. I choose to start with the simplest symbolic substances that respect the lifeworld’s continuous dynamism, temporality, boundless morphogenesis, superposability, continuity, density and value, and yet are independent of measure, metric, counting, finitude, formal logic, syntax, grammar, digitality and computability – in short, free of the formal structures that would put a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Supervenience, Reduction, and Translation.Neil Dewar - 2019 - Philosophy of Science 86 (5):942-954.
    This article considers the following question: What is the relationship between supervenience and reduction? I investigate this formally: first, by introducing a recent argument by Christian List to the effect that one can have supervenience without reduction; then, by considering how the notion of Nagelian reduction can be related to the formal apparatus of definability and translation theory; then, by showing how, in the context of propositional theories, topological constraints on supervenience serve to enforce reducibility; (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  51
    On the reduction of general relativity to Newtonian gravitation.Samuel C. Fletcher - 2019 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 68:1-15.
    Intertheoretic reduction in physics aspires to be both to be explanatory and perfectly general: it endeavors to explain why an older, simpler theory continues to be as successful as it is in terms of a newer, more sophisticated theory, and it aims to relate or otherwise account for as many features of the two theories as possible. Despite often being introduced as straightforward cases of intertheoretic reduction, candidate accounts of the reduction of general relativity to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  11.  12
    Open core and small groups in dense pairs of topological structures.Elías Baro & Amador Martin-Pizarro - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (1):102858.
    Dense pairs of geometric topological fields have tame open core, that is, every definable open subset in the pair is already definable in the reduct. We fix a minor gap in the published version of van den Dries's seminal work on dense pairs of o-minimal groups, and show that every definable unary function in a dense pair of geometric topological fields agrees with a definable function in the reduct, off a small definable subset, that is, a definable set (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12. Reductive theories of modality.Theodore Sider - 2003 - In Michael J. Loux & Dean W. Zimmerman (eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 180-208.
    Logic begins but does not end with the study of truth and falsity. Within truth there are the modes of truth, ways of being true: necessary truth and contingent truth. When a proposition is true, we may ask whether it could have been false. If so, then it is contingently true. If not, then it is necessarily true; it must be true; it could not have been false. Falsity has modes as well: a false proposition that could not have been (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  13.  15
    A note on the non‐forking‐instances topology.Ziv Shami - 2020 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 66 (3):336-340.
    The non‐forking‐instances topology (NFI topology) is a topology on the Stone space of a theory T that depends on a reduct of T. This topology has been used in [6] to describe the set of universal transducers for (invariants sets that translate forking‐open sets in to forking‐open sets in T). In this paper we show that in contrast to the stable case, the NFI topology need not be invariant over parameters in but a weak version of this holds for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  20
    The undecidability of the lattice of R.E. closed subsets of an effective topological space.Sheryl Silibovsky Brady & Jeffrey B. Remmel - 1987 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 35 (C):193-203.
    The first-order theory of the lattice of recursively enumerable closed subsets of an effective topological space is proved undecidable using the undecidability of the first-order theory of the lattice of recursively enumerable sets. In particular, the first-order theory of the lattice of recursively enumerable closed subsets of Euclidean n -space, for all n , is undecidable. A more direct proof of the undecidability of the lattice of recursively enumerable closed subsets of Euclidean n -space, n ⩾ (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Describing the macroscopic world: Closing the circle within the dynamical reduction program. [REVIEW]G. C. Ghirardi, R. Grassi & F. Benatti - 1995 - Foundations of Physics 25 (1):5-38.
    With reference to recently proposed theoretical models accounting for reduction in terms of a unified dynamics governing all physical processes, we analyze the problem of working out a worldview accommodating our knowledge about natural phenomena. We stress the relevant conceptual differences between the considered models and standard quantum mechanics. In spite of the fact that both theories describe systems within a genuine Hilbert space framework, the peculiar features of the spontaneous reduction models limit drastically the states which are (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  16.  26
    The intensional side of algebraic-topological representation theorems.Sara Negri - 2017 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 5):1121-1143.
    Stone representation theorems are a central ingredient in the metatheory of philosophical logics and are used to establish modal embedding results in a general but indirect and non-constructive way. Their use in logical embeddings will be reviewed and it will be shown how they can be circumvented in favour of direct and constructive arguments through the methods of analytic proof theory, and how the intensional part of the representation results can be recovered from the syntactic proof of those embeddings. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Possible worlds II: Non-reductive theories of possible worlds.Louis DeRosset - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (6):1009-1021.
    It is difficult to wander far in contemporary metaphysics without bumping into talk of possible worlds. And, reference to possible worlds is not confined to metaphysics. It can be found in contemporary epistemology and ethics, and has even made its way into linguistics and decision theory. What are those possible worlds, the entities to which theorists in these disciplines all appeal? Some have hoped that a theory of possible worlds can be used to reduce modality to non-modal terms. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18.  27
    On topological set theory.Thierry Libert & Olivier Esser - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (3):263-273.
    This paper is concerned with topological set theory, and particularly with Skala's and Manakos' systems for which we give a topological characterization of the models. This enables us to answer natural questions about those theories, reviewing previous results and proving new ones. One of these shows that Skala's set theory is in a sense compatible with any ‘normal’ set theory, and another appears on the semantic side as a ‘Cantor theorem’ for the category of Alexandroff (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. Dynamical reduction theories as a natural basis for a realistic worldview.G. C. Ghirardi - 1998 - In Elena Castellani (ed.), Interpreting Bodies. Princeton University Press. pp. 258--96.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  70
    Dynamical Reduction Theories: Changing Quantum Theory so the Statevector Represents Reality.GianCarlo Ghirardi & Philip Pearle - 1990 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:19 - 33.
    The propositions, that what we see around us is real and that reality should be represented by the statevector, conflict with quantum theory. In quantum theory, the statevector can readily become a sum of states of comparable norm, each state representing a different reality. In this paper we present the Continuous Spontaneous Localization (CSL) theory, in which a modified Schrodinger equation, while scarcely affecting the dynamics of a microscopic system, rapidly "reduces" the statevector of a macroscopic system (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Deflationary (Reductive) Theories of Fictional Objects. Review and Analysis.Jacek Gurczynski - 2011 - Filozofia Nauki 19 (1):133.
  22.  25
    Delay-reduction theory: Straddling the functional-mechanism continuum.Edmund Fantino & Nureya Abarca - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):317-318.
  23.  47
    Dual easy uniformization and model-theoretic descriptive set theory.Shaughan Lavine - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1290-1316.
    It is well known that, in the terminology of Moschovakis, Descriptive set theory (1980), every adequate normed pointclass closed under ∀ω has an effective version of the generalized reduction property (GRP) called the easy uniformization property (EUP). We prove a dual result: every adequate normed pointclass closed under ∃ω has the EUP. Moschovakis was concerned with the descriptive set theory of subsets of Polish topological spaces. We set up a general framework for parts of descriptive set (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  17
    Forcing in nonstandard analysis.Masanao Ozawa - 1994 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 68 (3):263-297.
    A nonstandard universe is constructed from a superstructure in a Boolean-valued model of set theory. This provides a new framework of nonstandard analysis with which methods of forcing are incorporated naturally. Various new principles in this framework are provided together with the following applications: An example of an 1-saturated Boolean ultrapower of the real number field which is not Scott complete is constructed. Infinitesimal analysis based on the generic extension of the hyperreal numbers is provided, and the hull completeness (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  25.  52
    Suárez's Non-Reductive Theory of Efficient Causation.Jacob Tuttle - 2016 - Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy 4 (1):125-158.
    This paper examines an important but neglected topic in Suárez’s metaphysics–—namely, his theory of efficient causation. According to Suárez, efficient causation is to be identified with action, one of Aristotle’s ten highest genera or categories. The paper shows how Suárez’s identification of efficient causation with action helps to shed light on his views about the precise nature of efficient causation, and its role in his ontology. More specifically, it shows that Suárez understands efficient causation to be a distinctive or (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  26.  50
    Larc: A State Reduction Theory of Quantum Measurement. [REVIEW]Michael Simpson - 2011 - Foundations of Physics 41 (10):1648-1663.
    This proposes a new theory of Quantum measurement; a state reduction theory in which reduction is to the elements of the number operator basis of a system, triggered by the occurrence of annihilation or creation (or lowering or raising) operators in the time evolution of a system. It is from these operator types that the acronym ‘LARC’ is derived. Reduction does not occur immediately after the trigger event; it occurs at some later time with probability (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27. Towards a reductive theory of visual style.George Kubler - 1979 - In Leonard B. Meyer & Berel Lang (eds.), The Concept of Style. University of Pennsylvania Press. pp. 119--127.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  3
    I. Dynamical Reduction Theories: Changing Quantum Theory so the Statevector Represents Reality.GianCarlo Ghirardi & Philip Pearle - 1990 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (2):19-33.
    We dedicate these papers to the memory of John Bell, whose contributions to, support for, and encouragement of the research program described here has meant more than words can say to those involved in it.In Schrödinger’s “cat paradox” example, a nucleus which has a 50% probability of decaying within an hour is coupled to a cat by a “hellish contraption” which, if it detects the decay, will kill the cat. If we take the point of view that what we see (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  11
    Can the anxiety-reduction theory explain abnormal fixations?Norman R. F. Maier & Paul Ellen - 1951 - Psychological Review 58 (6):435-445.
  30. The Effects of Dynamic Work Environments on Entrepreneurs’ Humble Leader Behaviors: Based on Uncertainty Reduction Theory.Xiao Deng, Bo Gao & Guozheng Li - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31. Knowing What an Experience Is Like and the Reductive Theory of Knowledge‐wh.Kevin Lynch - 2019 - Analytic Philosophy 61 (3):252-275.
    This article discusses a kind of knowledge classifiable as knowledge-wh but which seems to defy analysis in terms of the standard reductive theory of knowledge-wh ascriptions, according to which they are true if and only if one knows that p, where this proposition is an acceptable answer to the wh-question ‘embedded’ in the ascription. Specifically, it is argued that certain cases of knowing what an experience is like resist such treatment. I argue that in some of these cases, one (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32. Inter-theory Relations in Quantum Gravity: Correspondence, Reduction and Emergence.Karen Crowther - 2018 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 63:74-85.
    Relationships between current theories, and relationships between current theories and the sought theory of quantum gravity (QG), play an essential role in motivating the need for QG, aiding the search for QG, and defining what would count as QG. Correspondence is the broad class of inter-theory relationships intended to demonstrate the necessary compatibility of two theories whose domains of validity overlap, in the overlap regions. The variety of roles that correspondence plays in the search for QG are illustrated, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  33. General Theory of Topological Explanations and Explanatory Asymmetry.Daniel Kostic - 2020 - Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 375 (1796):1-8.
    In this paper, I present a general theory of topological explanations, and illustrate its fruitfulness by showing how it accounts for explanatory asymmetry. My argument is developed in three steps. In the first step, I show what it is for some topological property A to explain some physical or dynamical property B. Based on that, I derive three key criteria of successful topological explanations: a criterion concerning the facticity of topological explanations, i.e. what makes it (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  34. A topological theory of fundamental concrete particulars.Daniel Giberman - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (10):2679-2704.
    Fundamental concrete particulars are needed to explain facts about non-fundamental concrete particulars. However, the former can only play this explanatory role if they are properly discernible from the latter. Extant theories of how to discern fundamental concreta primarily concern mereological structure. Those according to which fundamental concreta can bear, but not be, proper parts are motivated by the possibilities that all concreta bear proper parts and that some properties of wholes are not fixed by the properties of their proper parts. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  35.  25
    A Peircean Reduction Thesis: The Foundations of Topological Logic.Robert W. Burch - 1991 - Texas Tech University Press.
  36.  10
    Reductive Nominalism and Trope Theory.Timothy H. Pickavance & Robert C. Koons - 2017 - In The Atlas of Reality. Wiley. pp. 147–170.
    There are a number of different versions of Reductive Nominalism, versions distinguished by the way in which each accounts for facts about having and sharing properties. This chapter discusses three broad varieties of Reductive Nominalism: Predicate Nominalism, Class Nominalism, and Resemblance Nominalism. Class Nominalism identifies properties with classes or sets. Resemblance Nominalists come in two sub‐varieties, depending on whether they take the resemblance relation to hold between particular properties (called 'tropes') or particular things that have properties (ordinary particulars). Trope (...) comes in two varieties depending on whether one plumps for universals. It should not be difficult to see that Extreme Resemblance Nominalism is faced with Class Nominalism's extensionality problems, both the problem of contingent predication and the co‐extensive property problem. Resemblance Nominalists can reply by insisting on a distinction between a priori or conceptual equivalence and metaphysical equivalence. The chapter focuses on the extensionality problems for Class Nominalism. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  36
    Randall Dougherty and Alexander S. Kechris. The complexity of antidifferentiation. Advances in mathematics, vol. 88 , pp. 145–169. - Ferenc Beleznay and Matthew Foreman. The collection of distal flows is not Borel. American journal of mathematics, vol. 117 , pp. 203–239. - Ferenc Beleznay and Matthew Foreman. The complexity of the collection of measure-distal transformations. Ergodic theory and dynamical systems, vol. 16 , pp. 929–962. - Howard Becker. Pointwise limits of subsequences and sets. Fundamenta mathematicae, vol. 128 , pp. 159–170. - Howard Becker, Sylvain Kahane, and Alain Louveau. Some complete sets in harmonic analysis. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 339 , pp. 323–336. - Robert Kaufman. PCA sets and convexity Fundamenta mathematicae, vol. 163 , pp. 267–275). - Howard Becker. Descriptive set theoretic phenomena in analysis and topology. Set theory of the continuum, edited by H. Judah, W. Just, and H. Woodin, Mathematical Sciences Research Institute. [REVIEW]Gabriel Debs - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):385-388.
  38. Similarity, Topology, and Physical Significance in Relativity Theory.Samuel C. Fletcher - 2016 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 67 (2):365-389.
    Stephen Hawking, among others, has proposed that the topological stability of a property of space-time is a necessary condition for it to be physically significant. What counts as stable, however, depends crucially on the choice of topology. Some physicists have thus suggested that one should find a canonical topology, a single ‘right’ topology for every inquiry. While certain such choices might be initially motivated, some little-discussed examples of Robert Geroch and some propositions of my own show that the main (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  39.  24
    Topological representations of post algebras of order ω+ and open theories based on ω+-valued post logic.Helena Rasiowa - 1985 - Studia Logica 44 (4):353 - 368.
    Post algebras of order + as a semantic foundation for +-valued predicate calculi were examined in [5]. In this paper Post spaces of order + being a modification of Post spaces of order n2 (cf. Traczyk [8], Dwinger [1], Rasiowa [6]) are introduced and Post fields of order + are defined. A representation theorem for Post algebras of order + as Post fields of sets is proved. Moreover necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of representations preserving a given set (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40. Set Theory, Topology, and the Possibility of Junky Worlds.Thomas Mormann - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (1): 79 - 90.
    A possible world is a junky world if and only if each thing in it is a proper part. The possibility of junky worlds contradicts the principle of general fusion. Bohn (2009) argues for the possibility of junky worlds, Watson (2010) suggests that Bohn‘s arguments are flawed. This paper shows that the arguments of both authors leave much to be desired. First, relying on the classical results of Cantor, Zermelo, Fraenkel, and von Neumann, this paper proves the possibility of junky (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  58
    Aspects of general topology in constructive set theory.Peter Aczel - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 137 (1-3):3-29.
    Working in constructive set theory we formulate notions of constructive topological space and set-generated locale so as to get a good constructive general version of the classical Galois adjunction between topological spaces and locales. Our notion of constructive topological space allows for the space to have a class of points that need not be a set. Also our notion of locale allows the locale to have a class of elements that need not be a set. Class (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  42.  11
    The Planetary Theory of Ibn al-Shatir: Reduction of the Geometric Models to Numerical Tables.Fuad Abbud - 1962 - Isis 53 (4):492-499.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43.  87
    Theory structure, reduction, and disciplinary integration in biology.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1993 - Biology and Philosophy 8 (3):319-347.
    This paper examines the nature of theory structure in biology and considers the implications of those theoretical structures for theory reduction. An account of biological theories as interlevel prototypes embodying causal sequences, and related to each other by strong analogies, is presented, and examples from the neurosciences are provided to illustrate these middle-range theories. I then go on to discuss several modifications of Nagel''s classical model of theory reduction, and indicate at what stages in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  44.  22
    Textual Theory and Complex Belief Systems: Topological Theory.J. Nescolarde-Selva & J. L. Usó-Doménech - 2016 - Foundations of Science 21 (1):153-175.
    In order to establish patterns of materialization of the beliefs we are going to consider that these have defined mathematical structures. It will allow us to understand better processes of the textual, architectonic, normative, educative, etc., materialization of an ideology. The materialization is the conversion by means of certain mathematical correspondences, of an abstract set whose elements are beliefs or ideas, in an impure set whose elements are material or energetic. Text is a materialization of ideology and it is any (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  62
    Functorial duality for ortholattices and de Morgan lattices.Katalin Bimbó - 2007 - Logica Universalis 1 (2):311-333.
    . Relational semantics for nonclassical logics lead straightforwardly to topological representation theorems of their algebras. Ortholattices and De Morgan lattices are reducts of the algebras of various nonclassical logics. We define three new classes of topological spaces so that the lattice categories and the corresponding categories of topological spaces turn out to be dually isomorphic. A key feature of all these topological spaces is that they are ordered relational or ordered product topologies.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46. Arithmetic, Set Theory, Reduction and Explanation.William D’Alessandro - 2018 - Synthese 195 (11):5059-5089.
    Philosophers of science since Nagel have been interested in the links between intertheoretic reduction and explanation, understanding and other forms of epistemic progress. Although intertheoretic reduction is widely agreed to occur in pure mathematics as well as empirical science, the relationship between reduction and explanation in the mathematical setting has rarely been investigated in a similarly serious way. This paper examines an important particular case: the reduction of arithmetic to set theory. I claim that the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  47.  19
    Quotient topologies in constructive set theory and type theory.Hajime Ishihara & Erik Palmgren - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 141 (1):257-265.
    The standard construction of quotient spaces in topology uses full separation and power sets. We show how to make this construction using only the predicative methods available in constructive type theory and constructive set theory.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  48.  38
    Topological representation of geometric theories.Henrik Forssell - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (6):380-393.
    Using Butz and Moerdijk's topological groupoid representation of a topos with enough points, a ‘syntax-semantics’ duality for geometric theories is constructed. The emphasis is on a logical presentation, starting with a description of the semantic topological groupoid of models and isomorphisms of a theory. It is then shown how to extract a theory from equivariant sheaves on a topological groupoid in such a way that the result is a contravariant adjunction between theories and groupoids, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Theory Reduction by Means of Functional Sub‐types.Michael Esfeld & Christian Sachse - 2007 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21 (1):1 – 17.
    The paper sets out a new strategy for theory reduction by means of functional sub-types. This strategy is intended to get around the multiple realization objection. We use Kim's argument for token identity (ontological reductionism) based on the causal exclusion problem as starting point. We then extend ontological reductionism to epistemological reductionism (theory reduction). We show how one can distinguish within any functional type between functional sub-types. Each of these sub-types is coextensive with one type of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  50.  18
    Topological Structure of Diagonalizable Algebras and Corresponding Logical Properties of Theories.Giovanna D'Agostino - 1994 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 35 (4):563-572.
    This paper studies the topological duality between diagonalizable algebras and bi-topological spaces. In particular, the correspondence between algebraic properties of a diagonalizable algebra and topological properties of its dual space is investigated. Since the main example of a diagonalizable algebra is the Lindenbaum algebra of an r.e. theory extending Peano Arithmetic, endowed with an operator defined by means of the provability predicate of the theory, this duality gives the possibility to study arithmetical properties of theories (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 999