Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Socrates on the definition of Piety.S. Marc Cohen - 1971 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 9 (1):1-13.
    The central argument in the Euthyphro is the one Socrates advances against the definition of piety as "what all the gods love." The argument turns on establishing that a loved thing (philoumenon) is 1) a loved thing because it is loved (phileitai), not 2) loved because it is a loved thing. I suggest that this claim can be understood and found acceptable if we take "because" to be used equivocally in it. Despite the equivocation, Socrates' argument is valid, showing that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Impiety of Socrates.M. F. Burnyeat - 1997 - Ancient Philosophy 17 (1):1-12.
  • Kant’s Solution to the Euthyphro Dilemma.Jochen Bojanowski - 2016 - Philosophia 44 (4):1209-1228.
    Are our actions morally good because we approve of them or are they good independently of our approval? Are we projecting moral values onto the world or do we detect values that are already there? For many these questions don’t state a real alternative but a secular variant of the Euthyphro dilemma: If our actions are good because we approve of them moral goodness appears to be arbitrary. If they are good independently of our approval, it is unclear how we (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Socrates and euthyphro: The argument and its revival.Terence Irwin - 2006 - In Lindsay Judson & Vassilis Karasmanis (eds.), Remembering Socrates: philosophical essays. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Carried Away in the Euthyphro.Lindsay Judson - 2010 - In David Charles (ed.), Definition in Greek philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 31-61.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • 6 The historic decline of virtue ethics.Dorothea Frede - 2013 - In Daniel C. Russell (ed.), The Cambridge companion to virtue ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 124.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Socrates' religious experiences.John Bussanich - 2013 - In John Bussanich & Nicholas D. Smith (eds.), The Bloomsbury companion to Socrates. New York: Continuum.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought.Michael Frede - 2011 - University of California Press.
    Where does the notion of free will come from? How and when did it develop, and what did that development involve? In Michael Frede's radically new account of the history of this idea, the notion of a free will emerged from powerful assumptions about the relation between divine providence, correctness of individual choice, and self-enslavement due to incorrect choice. Anchoring his discussion in Stoicism, Frede begins with Aristotle--who, he argues, had no notion of a free will--and ends with Augustine. Frede (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Wrong Turns in the Euthyphro.Paul Woodruff - 2019 - Apeiron 52 (2):117-136.
    Journal Name: Apeiron Issue: Ahead of print.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • "Euthyphro" 10a2-11b1: A Study in Platonic Metaphysics and its Reception Since 1960.David Wolfsdorf - 2005 - Apeiron 38 (1):1-72.
  • Virtue without Knowledge.Roslyn Weiss - 1994 - Ancient Philosophy 14 (2):263-282.
  • Reasons and causes in the phaedo.Gregory Vlastos - 1969 - Philosophical Review 78 (3):291-325.
    An analysis of phaedo 96c-606c seeks to demonstrate that when forms are cited as either "safe" or "clever" aitiai they are not meant to function as either final or efficient causes, But as logico-Metaphysical essences which have no causal efficacy whatever, But which do have definite (and far-Reaching) implications for the causal order of the physical universe, For it is assumed that a causal statement, Such as "fire causes heat" will be true if, And only if, The asserted physical bond (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Platonic Causes.David Sedley - 1998 - Phronesis 43 (2):114-132.
    This paper examines Plato's ideas on cause-effect relations in the "Phaedo." It maintains that he sees causes as things (not events, states of affairs or the like), with any information as to how that thing brings about the effect relegated to a strictly secondary status. This is argued to make good sense, so long as we recognise that aition means the "thing responsible" and exploit legal analogies in order to understand what this amounts to. Furthermore, provided that we do not (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Das Meisterargument in Platons Euthyphron.Benjamin Schnieder - 2015 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 18 (1):227-254.
    In Plato’s Euthyphro, Euthyphro proposes to analyse the pious as that which is beloved of the gods. In the most widely discussed argument of the dialogue, Socrates tries to show that Euthyphro’s analysis fails. The argument crucially involves an ingenious use of the explanatory connective ‘because’. This paper presents a detailed reconstruction and defence of the argument. It starts with a rigorous analysis of its logical form, explains and justifies its premises, and closes with a defence of the argument against (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Über Relativbegriffe in der Philosophie Platons.Erhard Scheibe - 1967 - Phronesis 12 (1):28-49.
  • Plato's Euthyphro and the Earlier Theory of Forms.K. M. Sayre & R. E. Allen - 1972 - Philosophical Quarterly 22 (87):165.
  • Justice and Pollution in the Euthyphro.Mark L. McPherran - 2002 - Apeiron 35 (2):105 - 129.
  • A Chiastic Contradiction at Euthyphro 9e1-11b5. Kim - 2004 - Phronesis 49 (3):219-224.
    One of Euthyphro's proposed definitions of to hosion says: '[T]he pious is what all the gods love...'. Scholarly analyses of Socrates' refutation of this definition have focused on its validity or even its 'truth'. By contrast, this paper restricts itself to the refutation's logical structure, particularly the way Socrates juxtaposes the agreed-upon premises to derive a double or 'chiastic' contradiction. In this article, I lay out the details of Socrates' ingenious logical construction, without regard to its validity or fallaciousness, and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Plato’s Euthyphro: An Analysis and Commentary.P. T. Geach - 1966 - The Monist 50 (3):369-382.
    The Euthyphro might well be given to undergraduates to read early in their philosophical training. The arguments are apparently simple, but some of them, as I shall show, lead naturally on to thorny problems of modern philosophy. Another benefit that could be gained from reading the Euthyphro is that the reader may learn to be forewarned against some common fallacies and debating tricks in moral disputes.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Plato’s Euthyphro.P. T. Geach - 1966 - The Monist 50 (3):369-382.
    The Euthyphro might well be given to undergraduates to read early in their philosophical training. The arguments are apparently simple, but some of them, as I shall show, lead naturally on to thorny problems of modern philosophy. Another benefit that could be gained from reading the Euthyphro is that the reader may learn to be forewarned against some common fallacies and debating tricks in moral disputes.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Plato’s Forms as Functions and Structures.Dorothea Frede - 2020 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 23 (2):291-316.
    Despite the fact that the theory of Forms is regarded as the hallmark of Plato’s philosophy, it has remained remarkably elusive, because it is more hinted at than explained in his dialogues. Given the uncertainty concerning the nature and extension of the Forms, this article makes no pretense to coming up with solutions to all problems that have occupied scholars since antiquity. It aims to elucidate only two aspects of that theory: the indication in certain dialogues that the Forms are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • God and the Soul.Antony Flew & Peter Geach - 1970 - Philosophical Quarterly 20 (79):189.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • The Priority of Definition and the Socratic Elenchus.Hugh G. Benson - 1990 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 8:19.
  • Reason and religion in Socratic philosophy.Nicholas D. Smith & Paul Woodruff (eds.) - 2000 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This volume brings together mostly previously unpublished studies by prominent historians, classicists, and philosophers on the roles and effects of religion in Socratic philosophy and on the trial of Socrates. Among the contributors are Thomas C. Brickhouse, Asli Gocer, Richard Kraut, Mark L. McPherran, Robert C. T. Parker, C. D. C. Reeve, Nicholas D. Smith, Gregory Vlastos, Stephen A. White, and Paul B. Woodruff.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Confusing Universals and Particulars In Plato’s Early Dialogues.Alexander Nehamas - 1975 - Review of Metaphysics 29 (2):287 - 306.
    It is said that when Socrates is made to ask questions like "What is the pious and what the impious?", "What is courage?", or "What is the beautiful?", he is asking for the definition of a universal. For the "average" Greek of his time, however, this is a radically new question about a radically new sort of object, and Socrates’ interlocutors do not understand it. They usually answer it as if it were a different, if related, question: they tend to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Socrates.Debra Nails - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Griechische Religion der archaischen und klassischen Epoche.Walter Burkert - 1981 - Religious Studies 17 (2):282-284.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy.J. B. Schneewind - 1998 - Philosophy 74 (289):446-448.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Plato's Euthyphro and the Earlier Theory of Forms.R. E. Allen - 1970 - Philosophy 46 (176):170-172.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Socrates' Gods and the Daimonion.Thomas C. Brickhouse & Nicholas D. Smith - 2000 - In Nicholas D. Smith & Paul Woodruff (eds.), Reason and Religion in Socratic Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 74--88.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations