Results for 'Paul A. Roth'

(not author) ( search as author name )
991 found
Order:
  1.  22
    Redrawing the Lines: Analytic Philosophy, Deconstruction, and Literary Theory.Paul A. Roth - 1991 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (2):180-182.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  19
    Reconstructing Quine: The troubles with a tradition.Paul A. Roth - 1983 - Metaphilosophy 14 (3-4):249-266.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  65
    Essentially narrative explanations.Paul A. Roth - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 62 (C):42-50.
  4. The Pasts.Paul A. Roth - 2012 - History and Theory 51 (3):313-339.
    ABSTRACTThis essay offers a reconfiguration of the possibility‐space of positions regarding the metaphysics and epistemology associated with historical knowledge. A tradition within analytic philosophy from Danto to Dummett attempts to answer questions about the reality of the past on the basis of two shared assumptions. The first takes individual statements as the relevant unit of semantic and philosophical analysis. The second presumes that variants of realism and antirealism about the past exhaust the metaphysical options . This essay argues that both (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  5.  29
    New Philosophy of Social Science: Problems of Indeterminacy.Paul A. Roth - 1995 - Metaphilosophy 26 (4):440-448.
    This article defends methodological and theoretical pluralism in the social sciences. While pluralistic, such a philosophy of social science is both pragmatic and normative. Only by facing the problems of such pluralism, including how to resolve the potential conflicts between various methods and theories, is it possible to discover appropriate criteria of adequacy for social scientific explanations and interpretations. So conceived, the social sciences do not give us fixed and universal features of the social world, but rather contribute to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  7
    Logic and Translation.Paul A. Roth - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (3):154-163.
  7.  13
    Who needs paradigms?Paul A. Roth - 1984 - Metaphilosophy 15 (3-4):225-238.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Beyond understanding: the career of the concept of understanding in the human sciences.Paul A. Roth - forthcoming - Philosophy of the Social Sciences.
  9.  62
    Narrative Explanations: The Case of History.Paul A. Roth - 1988 - History and Theory 27 (1):1-13.
    The very idea of narrative explanation invites two objections: a methodological objection, stating that narrative structure is too far from the form of a scientific explanation to count as an explanation, and a metaphysical objection, stating that narrative structure situates historical practice too close to the writing of fiction. Both of these objections, however, are illfounded. The methodological objection and the dispute regarding the status of historical explanation can be disposed of by revealing their motivating presupposition: the plausibility of an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  10.  17
    Three Dogmas of Explanation.Paul A. Roth - 2008 - History and Theory 47 (1):57-68.
    What ought to count as an explanation? Such normative questions—what “ought to be” the case?—typically mark the domain that those with a type of philosophical aspiration call their own. Debates in the philosophy of history have for too long been marred by bad advice from just such aspirants. The recurrent suggestion has been that historians have a particular need for a theory of explanation since they seem to have none of their own. But neither the study of the natural sciences (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  95
    Hayden White in Philosophical Perspective: Review Essay of Herman Paul’s Hayden White: The Historical Imagination. [REVIEW]Paul A. Roth - 2014 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 44 (1):102-111.
    For almost half a century, the person most responsible for fomenting brouhahas regarding degrees of plasticity in the writing of histories has been Hayden White. Yet, despite the voluminous responses provoked by White’s work, almost no effort has been made to treat White’s writings in a systematic yet sympathetic way as a philosophy of history. Herman Paul’s book begins to remedy that lack and does so in a carefully considered and extremely scholarly fashion. In his relatively brief six chapters (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12. Mistakes.Paul A. Roth - 2003 - Synthese 136 (3):389-408.
    A suggestion famously made by Peter Winch and carried through to present discussions holds that what constitutes the social as a kind consists of something shared – rules or practices commonly learned, internalized, or otherwise acquired by all members belonging to a society. This essays argues against the explanatory efficacy of appeals to this shared something as constitutive of a social kind by examining a violation of social norms or rules, viz., mistakes. I argue that an asymmetric relation exists between (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  13. Hearts of darkness: 'perpetrator history' and why there is no why.Paul A. Roth - 2004 - History of the Human Sciences 17 (2-3):211-251.
    Three theories contend as explanations of perpetrator behavior in the Holocaust as well as other cases of genocide: structural, intentional, and situational. Structural explanations emphasize the sense in which no single individual or choice accounts for the course of events. In opposition, intentional/cutltural accounts insist upon the genocides as intended outcomes, for how can one explain situations in which people ‘step up’ and repeatedly kill defenseless others in large numbers over sustained periods of time as anything other than a choice? (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14. Ways of pastmaking.Paul A. Roth - 2002 - History of the Human Sciences 15 (4):125-143.
    Riddles of induction – old or new, Hume’s or Goodman’s – pose unanswered challenges to assumptions that experiences logically legitimate expectations or classifications. The challenges apply both to folk beliefs and to scientific ones. In particular, Goodman’s ‘new riddle’ famously confounds efforts to specify how additional experiences confirm the rightness of currently preferred ways of organizing objects, i.e. our favored theories of what kinds there are.1 His riddle serves to emphasize that neither logic nor experience certifies accepted groupings of objects (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15.  74
    Siegel on naturalized epistemology and natural science.Paul A. Roth - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (3):482-493.
    What is the relation of epistemology, understood as the study of the evaluation of knowledge claims, and empirical psychology, understood as the study of the causal generation of a person's beliefs? Quine maintains that the relation is one of “mutual containment”.Epistemology in its new setting, conversely, is contained in natural science, as a chapter of psychology. … We are studying how the human subject of our study posits bodies and projects his physics from his data, and we appreciate that our (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  16.  38
    Theories of nature and the nature of theories.Paul A. Roth - 1980 - Mind 89 (355):431-438.
  17.  48
    Truth in interpretation: The case of psychoanalysis.Paul A. Roth - 1991 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 21 (2):175-195.
    This article explores and attempts to resolve some issues that arise when psychoanalytic explanations are construed as a type of historical or narrative explanation. The chief problem is this: If one rejects the claim of narratives to verisimilitude, this appears to divorce the notion of explanation from that of truth. The author examines, in particular, Donald Spence's attempt to deal with the relation of narrative explanations and truth. In his critique of Spence's distinction between narrative truth and historical truth, the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18.  47
    Will the real scientists please stand up? dead ends and live issues in the explanation of scientific knowledge.Paul A. Roth - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 27 (1):43-68.
  19.  13
    Beyond Understanding: The Career of the Concept of Understanding in the Human Sciences.Paul A. Roth - 2003 - In Stephen P. Turner & Paul A. Roth (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 311–333.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Real Understanding The Experience Distant — Understanding Hawaiian‐style The Experience Near — Understanding Holocaust Perpetrators Conclusion Notes.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20. Varieties and vagaries of historical explanation.Paul A. Roth - 2008 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 2 (2):214-226.
    For the better part of the 20th century, expositions of issues regarding historical explanation followed a predictable format, one that took as given the nonequivalence of explanations in history and philosophical models of scientific explanation. Ironically, at the present time, the philosophical point of note concerns how the notion of science has itself changed. Debates about explanation in turn need to adapt to this. This prompts the question of whether anything now still makes plausible the thought that history must make (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  63
    Politics and epistemology: Rorty, MacIntyre, and the ends of philosophy.Paul A. Roth - 1989 - History of the Human Sciences 2 (2):171-191.
    In this paper, I examine how a manifest disagreement between Richard Rorty and Alasdair MacIntyre concerning the history of philosophy is but one of a series of deep and interrelated disagreements concerning, in addition, the history of science, the good life for human beings, and, ultimately, the character of and prospects for humankind as well. I shall argue that at the heart of this series of disagreements rests a dispute with regard to the nature of rationality. And this disagreement concerning (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22. The silence of the norms: The missing historiography of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Paul A. Roth - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 44 (4):545-552.
    History has been disparaged since the late 19th century for not conforming to norms of scientific explanation. Nonetheless, as a matter of fact a work of history upends the regnant philosophical conception of science in the second part of the 20th century. Yet despite its impact, Kuhn’s Structure has failed to motivate philosophers to ponder why works of history should be capable of exerting rational influence on an understanding of philosophy of science. But all this constitutes a great irony and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23. The object of understanding.Paul A. Roth - 2000 - In K. R. Stueber & H. H. Kogaler (eds.), Empathy and Agency: The Problem of Understanding in the Human Sciences. Boulder: Westview Press. pp. 243--269.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. The epistemology of science after Quine.Paul A. Roth - 2008 - In Stathis Psillos & Martin Curd (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science. Routledge. pp. 3.
  25.  50
    Paul A. Roth on The Fiction of Narrative: Essays on History, Literature, and Theory 1957–2007. By Hayden White. Edited with an introduction by Robert Doran. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2010. Pp. 382. [REVIEW]Paul A. Roth - 2013 - History and Theory 52 (1):130-143.
    To claim that Hayden White has yet to be read seriously as a philosopher of history might seem false on the face of it. But do tropes and the rest provide any epistemic rationale for differing representations of historical events found in histories? As an explanation of White’s influence on philosophy of history, such a proffered emphasis only generates a puzzle with regard to taking White seriously, and not an answer to the question of why his efforts should be worthy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  13
    Searleworld.Paul A. Roth - 2012 - History and Theory 51 (1):123-142.
    ABSTRACTJohn Searle's most recent effort to account for human social institutions claims to provide a synthesis of the explanatory and the normative while simultaneously dismissing as confused and wrongheaded theorists who held otherwise. Searle, although doubtless alert to the usual considerations for separating the normative and the explanatory projects, announces at the outset that he conceives of matters quite differently. Searle's reason for reconceiving the field rests on his claim that both ends can be achieved by a single “underlying principle (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  80
    Paradox and indeterminacy.Paul A. Roth - 1978 - Journal of Philosophy 75 (7):347-367.
  28.  11
    Made or Found? On Genesis and Genealogy.Paul A. Roth - 2024 - Analysis 84 (2):345-357.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  32
    History and the manifest image: Hayden white as a philosopher of history1.Paul A. Roth - 2013 - History and Theory 52 (1):130-143.
  30. Hayden White and the Aesthetics of Historiography.Paul A. Roth - 1992 - History of the Human Sciences 5 (1):17-35.
  31. Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for Our Time.Paul A. Roth - 2002 - Common Knowledge 8 (2):418-419.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  61
    Kitcher's two cultures.Paul A. Roth - 2003 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 33 (3):386-405.
  33.  91
    The bureaucratic turn: Weber contra Hempel in Fuller's social epistemology.Paul A. Roth - 1991 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 34 (3-4):365 – 376.
    Like the positivists, Fuller is concerned to demarcate and systematically evaluate scientific claims and practices. Fuller corrects and reforms the positivist enterprise in light of his sociological naturalism. What Fuller's analysis brings to the fore is how the naturalization of epistemology makes the power?knowledge relation into an epistemological issue. Yet, in his writings. Fuller is radically divided with respect to how to react to this fact. Specifically, Fuller vacillates between, on the one hand, a concern for democratizing norms and, on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  94
    On missing Neurath's boat: Some reflections on recent Quine literature.Paul A. Roth - 1984 - Synthese 61 (2):205-231.
  35.  32
    Review Symposium: S. Fuller, Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History for Our Times.Paul A. Roth - 2001 - History of the Human Sciences 14 (2):87-97.
  36.  39
    Logic and translation: A reply to Alan Berger.Paul A. Roth - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (3):154-163.
    The article argues, "contra" berger, that quine's advocacy alleged of classical logic is not based on any alleged "fit" between classical logic and some empirical account of language learning. roth begins by examining berger's claim that quine has changed his position on the acceptability of alternative logics. in berger's account, quine now accepts alternative logics because he could not defend his commitment to classical logic alone based on empirical evidence (e.g., verdict tables). roth argues that berger is mistaken (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  48
    Three grades of normative involvement: Risjord, Stueber, and Henderson on norms and explanation.Paul A. Roth - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (3):339-352.
    What makes for a good explanation of a person’s actions? Their reasons, or soa natural reply goes. But how do reasons function as part of explanations, that is, within an account of the causes of action? Here philosophers divide concerning the logical relation in which reasons stand to actions. For, tradition holds, reasons evaluatively characterized must be causally inert, inasmuch as the normative features cannot be found in any account of the empirical/descriptive. To countenance reasons as causes thus seems to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Personhood, property rights, and the permissibility of abortion.Paul A. Roth - 1983 - Law and Philosophy 2 (2):163 - 191.
    The purpose of this paper is to argue that the tactic of granting a fetus the legal status of a person will not, contrary to the expectations of opponents of abortion, provide grounds for a general prohibition on abortions. I begin by examining two arguments, one moral (J. J. Thomson's A Defense of Abortion) and the other legal (D. Regan's Rewriting Roe v. Wade), which grant the assumption that a fetus is a person and yet argue to the conclusion that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  69
    4. three dogmas (more or less) of explanation.Paul A. Roth - 2008 - History and Theory 47 (1):57–68.
    What ought to count as an explanation? Such normative questions—what “ought to be” the case?—typically mark the domain that those with a type of philosophical aspiration call their own. Debates in the philosophy of history have for too long been marred by bad advice from just such aspirants. The recurrent suggestion has been that historians have a particular need for a theory of explanation since they seem to have none of their own. But neither the study of the natural sciences (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  14
    Erratum: Theories of nature and the nature of theories.Paul A. Roth - 1981 - Mind 90 (358):320 -.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Michael Krausz, ed., Relativism: Interpretation and Confrontation Reviewed by.Paul A. Roth - 1990 - Philosophy in Review 10 (2):66-70.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  54
    Naturalizing Goldman.Paul A. Roth - 1999 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1):89-111.
  43.  35
    Pseudo-problems in social science.Paul A. Roth - 1986 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 16 (1):59-82.
  44.  77
    Quo Vadis? Quine’s Web, Kuhn’s Revolutions, and Baert’s “Way Forward”: Patrick Baert, Philosophy of the Social Sciences: Towards Pragmatism. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2005.Paul A. Roth - 2009 - Human Studies 32 (3):357-363.
  45. St. Louis Roundtable on Philosophy of the Social Science.Paul A. Roth, Alyson Wylie & James Bohman - 2002 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (1):3-91.
  46. What Does the Sociology of Scientific Knowlegde Explain.Paul A. Roth - 1998 - In Irving Velody & Robin Williams (eds.), The Politics of Constructionism. Sage Publications. pp. 69--82.
  47.  73
    A Rationalist Methodology for the Social Sciences.Paul A. Roth - 1989 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 19 (1):104-108.
  48.  65
    Chaos, Clio, and Scientistic Illusions of Understanding.Paul A. Roth & Thomas A. Ryckman - 1995 - History and Theory 34 (1):30-44.
    A number of authors have recently argued that the mathematical insights of "chaos theory" offer a promising formal model or significant analogy for understanding at least some historical events. We examine a representative claim of each kind regarding the application of chaos theory to problems of historical explanation. We identify two lines of argument. One we term the Causal Thesis, which states that chaos theory may be used to plausibly model, and so explain, historical events. The other we term the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49. The End of Histories? Review Essay of Alexander Rosenberg’s How History Gets Things Wrong: the Neuroscience of Our Addiction to Stories.Mariana Imaz-Sheinbaum & Paul A. Roth - forthcoming - Journal of the Philosophy of History:1-9.
    Alex Rosenberg’s latest book purports to establish that narrative history cannot have any epistemic value. Rosenberg argues not for the replacement of narrative history by something more science-like, but rather the end of histories understood as an account of human doings under a certain description. This review critiques three of his main arguments: 1) narrative history must root its explanations in folk psychology, 2) there are no beliefs nor desires guiding human action, and 3) historical narratives are morally and ethically (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. What does the sociology of scientific knowledge explain?: or, when epistemological chickens come home to roost.Paul A. Roth - 1994 - History of the Human Sciences 7 (1):95-108.
1 — 50 / 991