Results for ' “discharges against medical advice”'

997 found
Order:
  1.  25
    Discharge against medical advice: Ethico-legal implications from an African perspective.Joseph Olusesan Fadare & Abiodun Christopher Jemilohun - 2012 - South African Journal of Bioethics and Law 5 (2).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  33
    What Do We Owe to Patients Who Leave Against Medical Advice? The Ethics of AMA Discharges.Leenoy Hendizadeh, Paula Goodman-Crews, Jeannette Martin & Eli Weber - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (2):139-145.
    Discharges against medical advice (AMA) make up a significant number of hospital discharges in the United States, and often involve vulnerable patients who struggle to obtain adequate medical care. Unfortunately, much of the AMA discharge process focuses on absolving the medical center of liability for what happens to these patients once they leave the acute setting. Comparatively little attention is paid to the ethical obligations of the medical team once an informed decision to leave the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  27
    Beyond the Waiver: An Ethical Approach to Discharge Against Medical Advice.Jeremy Chin & Rosalind Mcdougall - 2018 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 27 (2):348-352.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  7
    A Different Type of “Against Medical Advice”: When Patients Refuse Discharge.Leah Eisenberg - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (7):81-82.
    Patients are often eager to get out of the hospital; so eager that some decide to leave before their treatment team feels it is medically appropriate for them to do so. This is known as an AMA disc...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  10
    Review of David Alfandre, ed., Against-Medical-Advice Discharges From the Hospital: Optimizing Prevention and Management to Promote High Quality, Patient-Centered Care. [REVIEW]Haavi Morreim - 2019 - American Journal of Bioethics 19 (1):W1-W4.
    Patients who leave the hospital prior to their medically recommended endpoint (i.e., a discharge against medical advice, or “AMA”) typically prompt considerable consternation among physicians and o...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  41
    Applying the welfare model to at-own-risk discharges.Lalit Kumar Radha Krishna, Sumytra Menon & Ravindran Kanesvaran - 2017 - Nursing Ethics 24 (5):525-537.
    “At-own-risk discharges” or “self-discharges” evidences an irretrievable breakdown in the patient–clinician relationship when patients leave care facilities before completion of medical treatment and against medical advice. Dissolution of the therapeutic relationship terminates the physician’s duty of care and professional liability with respect to care of the patient. Acquiescence of an at-own-risk discharge by the clinician is seen as respecting patient autonomy. The validity of such requests pivot on the assumptions that the patient is fully informed and competent (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  12
    Applying the welfare model to at-own-risk discharges.Lalit Kumar Radha Krishna, Sumytra Menon & Ravindran Kanesvaran - 2017 - Nursing Ethics 24 (5):525-537.
    “At-own-risk discharges” or “self-discharges” evidences an irretrievable breakdown in the patient–clinician relationship when patients leave care facilities before completion of medical treatment and against medical advice. Dissolution of the therapeutic relationship terminates the physician’s duty of care and professional liability with respect to care of the patient. Acquiescence of an at-own-risk discharge by the clinician is seen as respecting patient autonomy. The validity of such requests pivot on the assumptions that the patient is fully informed and competent (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  8
    Essentials of nursing law and ethics.Susan J. Westrick - 2014 - Burlington, Massachusetts: Jones & Bartlett Learning.
    The legal environment -- Regulation of nursing practice -- Nurses in legal actions -- Standards of care -- Defenses to negligence or malpractice -- Prevention of malpractice -- Nurses as witnesses -- Professional liability insurance -- Accepting or refusing an assignment/patient abandonment -- Delegation to unlicensed assistive personnel -- Patients' rights and responsibilities -- Confidential communication -- Competency and guardianship -- Informed consent -- Refusal of treatment -- Pain control -- Patient teaching and health counseling -- Medication administration -- Clients (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  9
    When Is Enough, Enough?Megan Homsy - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (1):3-4.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:When Is Enough, Enough?Megan HomsyThis was a case that stuck with many members of our transplant team for a long time. The patient was a 44-year-old Caucasian male evaluated for a liver transplant with a diagnosis of hepatitis C virus (HCV), originally diagnosed 11 years before the transplant evaluation. The patient met the criteria for the following substance use diagnoses: alcohol use disorder moderate in sustained remission, in a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  52
    Perceived Quality of Informed Refusal Process: A Cross‐Sectional Study from Iranian Patients' Perspectives.Mehrdad Farzandipour, Abbas Sheikhtaheri & Monireh Sadeqi Jabali - 2014 - Developing World Bioethics 15 (3):172-178.
    Patients have the right to refuse their treatment; however, this refusal should be informed. We evaluated the quality of the informed refusal process in Iranian hospitals from patients' viewpoints. To this end, we developed a questionnaire that covered four key aspects of the informed refusal process including; information disclosure, voluntariness, comprehension, and provider-patient relationship. A total of 284 patients who refused their treatment from 12 teaching hospitals in the Isfahan Province, Iran, were recruited and surveyed to produce a convenience sample. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  9
    Working with Patience: An Insight into Dealing with Difficult Emotions.David Vilanova - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (1):10-12.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Working with Patience:An Insight into Dealing with Difficult EmotionsDavid VilanovaAs the most trusted professionals in the nation, nurses are expected to care for their patients with empathy and freedom from bias. The reality is that nurses are human, and some form of implicit bias is inevitable. In my own experience, this issue has reared its head on several occasions. My nursing background is prominently in cardiac and intensive care. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  7
    Silent Screams; Lily's Story.Eva V. Regel - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (1):19-22.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Silent Screams; Lily's StoryEva V. Regel"Trauma is personal. It does not disappear if it is not validated. When it is ignored or invalidated, the silent screams continue internally heard only by the one held captive. When someone enters the pain and hears the scream, healing can begin."—Danielle Bernock, "Emerging Wings; A true story of Lies, Pain and the Love that Heals."Some patients stay with you long after they leave. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  51
    Changing policy to reflect a concern for patients who sign out against medical advice.Alissa Hurwitz Swota - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (3):32 – 34.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  20
    “For Your Own Good”? Is It Ethical to Use Chemical Restraints on Patients Who Lack Capacity but Wish to Leave the Hospital against Medical Advice?Leah R. Eisenberg - 2022 - American Journal of Bioethics 22 (7):93-94.
    The work of a clinical ethicist often focuses on identifying what goals an autonomous patient has for themselves, or on helping identify a surrogate when a patient lacks autonomy for a specific dec...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  13
    Decisional Capacity After Dark: Is Autonomy Delayed Truly Autonomy Denied?Jacob M. Appel - 2024 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 33 (2):260-266.
    The model for capacity assessment in the United States and much of the Western world relies upon the demonstration of four skills including the ability to communicate a clear, consistent choice. Yet such assessments often occur at only one moment in time, which may result in the patient expressing a choice to the evaluator that is highly inconsistent with the patient’s underlying values and goals, especially if a short-term factor (such as frustration with the hospital staff) distorts the patient’s preferences (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  19
    The Tincture of the Doctor's Time.Holland Kaplan - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (1):12-14.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Tincture of the Doctor's TimeHolland KaplanI first thought of Mr. H as a "difficult patient" while reading the written hand-off I received on him as I was preparing to take over an inpatient general medicine service—"He leaves all the time to smoke." I don't think the statement was meant to imply anything about the patient; if anything, it may have been included for context to prepare me for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  28
    Cardiopulmonary resuscitation in the elderly: patients' and relatives' views.G. E. Mead & C. J. Turnbull - 1995 - Journal of Medical Ethics 21 (1):39-44.
    One hundred inpatients on an acute hospital elderly care unit and 43 of their relatives were interviewed shortly before hospital discharge. Eighty per cent of elderly patients and their relatives were aware of cardiopulmonary resuscitation (CPR). Television drama was their main source of information. Patients and relatives overestimated the effectiveness of CPR. Eighty-six per cent of patients were willing to be routinely consulted by doctors about their own CPR status, but relatives were less enthusiastic about routine consultation. Patients' and relatives' (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18.  14
    Should older people ever be discharged from hospital at night?Brent Hyslop - 2022 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 19 (3):445-450.
    The discharge of older people from hospital at night is a topical and emotive issue that has recently gained media attention in New Zealand and the United Kingdom, including calls to prevent it occurring. With growing pressures on hospital capacity and ageing populations, normative aspects of hospital discharge are increasingly relevant. This paper therefore addresses the question: Should older people (say, over eighty years old) ever be discharged home from hospital during the night? Or given safety concerns, should regulation (...) the night-time discharge of older people be put in place? Employing a principlist lens to bioethics, this paper considers key principles or values involved, including discharge safety concerns, personal preference and consent, the risk of remaining in hospital, and broader considerations around discharge policy. These points act as a possible framework for further research and discussion of normative aspects of hospital discharge. Overall, this paper argues that while discharge safety concerns must be properly acknowledged and addressed, it can still sometimes be appropriate for an older person to leave hospital at night. The option of night-time discharge should therefore remain open to people of all ages. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  26
    Advice on good practice from the Standards Committee.J. S. Happel - 1985 - Journal of Medical Ethics 11 (1):39-41.
    The role of the General Medical Council has changed over the last few years and this paper shows how the GMC now gives advice on good practice, as well as a warning against bad practice.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Against causal decision theory.Huw Price - 1986 - Synthese 67 (2):195 - 212.
    Proponents of causal decision theories argue that classical Bayesian decision theory (BDT) gives the wrong advice in certain types of cases, of which the clearest and commonest are the medical Newcomb problems. I defend BDT, invoking a familiar principle of statistical inference to show that in such cases a free agent cannot take the contemplated action to be probabilistically relevant to its causes (so that BDT gives the right answer). I argue that my defence does better than those of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  21. Medical diagnostic reasoning: Epistemological modeling as a strategy for design of computer-based consultation programs.Giovanni Barosi, Lorenzo Magnani & Mario Stefanelli - 1993 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 14 (1).
    The complexity of cognitive emulation of human diagnostic reasoning is the major challenge in the implementation of computer-based programs for diagnostic advice in medicine. We here present an epistemological model of diagnosis with the ultimate goal of defining a high-level language for cognitive and computational primitives. The diagnostic task proceeds through three different phases: hypotheses generation, hypotheses testing and hypotheses closure. Hypotheses generation has the inferential form of abduction (from findings to hypotheses) constrained under the criterion of plausibility. Hypotheses testing (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  29
    The actuality and the historical background of covert Euthanasia in Albania.Gëzim Boçari, Elmaz Shaqiri & Gentian Vyshka - 2010 - Journal of Medical Ethics 36 (12):842-844.
    Euthanasia is not legal in Albania, yet there is strong evidence that euthanising a terminally ill patient is not an unknown concept for the Albanians. The first mentioned case of euthanasia is found in 7th century AD mythology and during the communist regime (1944–1989), allegations of euthanising political prisoners and possible rivals in the struggle for power have widely been formulated. There is a trend among relatives and laymen taking care of terminally ill patients to apply tranquilisers in an abusive (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  31
    When Negative Rights Become Positive Entitlements: Complicity, Conscience, and Caregiving.A. G. Shuman, A. A. Khan, J. S. Moyer, M. E. Prince & J. J. Fins - 2012 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 23 (4):308-315.
    Clinicians have an obligation to ensure that patients with adequate capacity can make autonomous decisions. Thus, patients who choose to forego treatment and leave hospitals “against medical advice” are typically allowed to do so. But what happens when they require clinicians’ assistance to physically leave? Is it incumbent upon clinicians to not only respect and fulfill patients’ requests with which they disagree, but to physically assist in their fulfillment? We attempt to develop an ethical framework wherein clinicians can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  17
    Disputes about the Withdrawal of Treatment: The Role of the Courts.Loane Skene - 2004 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 32 (4):701-707.
    It is commonly said that patients have no right to demand that treatment must be continued when medical carers believe it is “futile” to continue it. There are certainly many judicial statements to this effect, some of which are quoted in this paper. However, there are various ways that courts can intervene, even if they do not order directly that treatment must be provided or continued. First, patients or their representatives may argue the process of decision making was unfair (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  18
    Caring for Patients with Substance Use Disorders: Addressing a Missed Opportunity in the Hospital.Rachel Elizabeth Simon & Matthew Tobey - 2018 - Hastings Center Report 48 (4):12-14.
    As physicians, we have seen patients with substance use disorders leave the hospital against medical advice, slipping through the cracks of our health care system. In fact, despite a high burden of life‐threatening illnesses, patients with SUDs are at a nearly threefold increased risk of leaving the hospital against medical advice. Leaving against medical advice is associated with an increased thirty‐day mortality rate as well as an increased rate of hospital readmission. When a patient (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  8
    Disputes about the Withdrawal of Treatment: The Role of the Courts.Loane Skene - 2004 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 32 (4):701-707.
    It is commonly said that patients have no right to demand that treatment must be continued when medical carers believe it is “futile” to continue it. There are certainly many judicial statements to this effect, some of which are quoted in this paper. However, there are various ways that courts can intervene, even if they do not order directly that treatment must be provided or continued. First, patients or their representatives may argue the process of decision making was unfair (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  17
    How to insure against utilitarian overconfidence.Nicholas Agar - 2014 - Monash Bioethics Review 32 (3-4):162-171.
    This paper addresses two examples of overconfident presentations of utilitarian moral conclusions. First, there is Peter Singer’s widely discussed claim that if the consequences of a medical experiment are sufficiently good to justify the use of animals, then we should be prepared to perform the experiment on human beings with equivalent mental capacities. Second, I consider defences of infanticide or after-birth abortion. I do not challenge the soundness of these arguments. Rather, I accuse those who seek to translate these (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  68
    The discrepancy between the legal definition of capacity and the British Medical Association's guidelines.J. O. A. Tan - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (5):427-429.
    Differences in guidance from various organisations is preventing uniform standards of practiceThe emphasis in medical law and ethics on protecting the patient’s right to choose is at an all time high. Apart from circumscribed situations, for instance where the Mental Health Act 19831 is applicable, the only justification for medically treating an adult patient against his or her wishes is on the basis of common law, using the principle of best interests, and only when he or she lacks (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  22
    The paediatrician and the rabbi.A. Shuper - 2000 - Journal of Medical Ethics 26 (6):441-443.
    Objectives—During recent decades, rabbis in Israel have been playing an increasing role in the consultation of patients or their families on medical issues. The study was performed to determine the attitude of physicians to rabbinical consultation by parents of sick children for purposes of basic medical decision making.Design and setting–A questionnaire was prepared which contained questions regarding physicians' reactions to specific medical situations as well as their demographic data. The study participants included all the available physicians who (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  18
    Being an abortion provider as a conflict of interest.Michal Pruski - 2022 - Catholic Medical Quarterly 72 (4):23.
    Dear Editor, -/- One of the recent changes in the UK cabinet, after Liz Truss became the Prime Minister, was that Dr Therese Coffey become the new Health Secretary. Some news outlets were quick to point out her anti-abortion stance (see e.g. (1–3)) and that this, according to them, might be a problem. While pro-lifers might not completely rejoice over this situation as Coffey stated that ‘she wouldn’t “seek to undo” abortion laws’(3), I do not wish to focus here on (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Externalist Argument Against Medical Assistance in Dying for Psychiatric Illness.Hane Htut Maung - 2023 - Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (8):553-557.
    Medical assistance in dying, which includes voluntary euthanasia and assisted suicide, is legally permissible in a number of jurisdictions, including the Netherlands, Belgium, Switzerland and Canada. Although medical assistance in dying is most commonly provided for suffering associated with terminal somatic illness, some jurisdictions have also offered it for severe and irremediable psychiatric illness. Meanwhile, recent work in the philosophy of psychiatry has led to a renewed understanding of psychiatric illness that emphasises the role of the relation between (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  40
    Against medical ethics: a response to Cassell.D. Seedhouse - 1998 - Journal of Medical Ethics 24 (1):13-17.
    This paper responds to Dr Cassell's request for a fuller explanation of my argument in the paper, Against medical ethics: a philosopher's view. A distinction is made between two accounts of ethics in general, and the philosophical basis of health work ethics is briefly stated. The implications of applying this understanding of ethics to medical education are discussed.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  33.  98
    Against medical ethics: opening the can of worms.J. Cassell - 1998 - Journal of Medical Ethics 24 (1):8-17.
    In a controversial paper, David Seedhouse argues that medical ethics is not and cannot be a distinct discipline with it own field of study. He derives this claim from a characterization of ethics, which he states but does not defend. He claims further that the project of medical ethics as it exists and of moral philosophy do not overlap. I show that Seedhouse's views on ethics have wide implications which he does not declare, and in the light of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  55
    ADHD drugs: Values that drive the debates and decisions. [REVIEW]Susan Hawthorne - 2007 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 10 (2):129-140.
    Use of medication for treatment of ADHD (or its historical precursors) has been debated for more than forty years. Reasons for the ongoing differences of opinion are analyzed by exploring some of the arguments for and against considering ADHD a mental disorder. Relative to two important DSM criteria — that a mental disorder causes some sort of harm to the individual and that a mental disorder is the manifestation of a dysfunction in the individual — ADHD’s classification as a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35.  33
    Enemies of patients.Ruth Macklin - 1993 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    A young man, terminally ill and in extreme suffering, asks to be removed from life support, requesting morphine first so he'll be asleep when the machine stops. His physician agrees, but the hospital's chief administrator intervenes, arguing that the morphine might itself cause death, leaving the physician open to criminal indictment for murder. To placate the administrator, the doctor and patient reach a grim compromise: life support will be disconnected first, and only after manifest signs of suffering appear will the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  7
    Stories of Families with Chronically Ill Pediatric Patients during the War in Ukraine.Vita Voloshchuk - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (3):5-7.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Stories of Families with Chronically Ill Pediatric Patients during the War in UkraineVita VoloshchukFebruary 24th was a day that has left a mark in the memory and on the lives of every Ukrainian person. My husband and I work together [End Page E5] in a hospital. He had gone into work early to conduct a kidney transplant that had been scheduled for that day. Suddenly, whilst on my way (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  39
    A consequentialist argument for considering age in triage decisions during the coronavirus pandemic.Matthew C. Altman - 2021 - Bioethics 35 (4):356-365.
    Most ethics guidelines for distributing scarce medical resources during the coronavirus pandemic seek to save the most lives and the most life‐years. A patient’s prognosis is determined using a SOFA or MSOFA score to measure likelihood of survival to discharge, as well as a consideration of relevant comorbidities and their effects on likelihood of survival up to one or five years. Although some guidelines use age as a tiebreaker when two patients’ prognoses are identical, others refuse to consider age (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  16
    Older patients’ perspectives on illness and healthcare during the early phase of the COVID-19 pandemic.Nina Jøranson, Anne Kari Tolo Heggestad, Hilde Lausund, Grete Breievne, Vigdis Bruun-Olsen, Kristi Elisabeth Heiberg, Marius Myrstad & Anette Hylen Ranhoff - 2022 - Nursing Ethics 29 (4):872-884.
    Background Equal access to healthcare is a core principle in Norway’s public healthcare system. The COVID-19 pandemic challenged healthcare systems in the early phase – in particular, related to testing and hospital capacity. There is little knowledge on how older people experienced being infected with an unfamiliar and severe disease, and how they experienced the need for healthcare early in the pandemic Aim To explore the experiences of older people infected by COVID-19 and their need for testing and hospitalisation. Research (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  34
    Moral expertise revisited.John-Stewart Gordon - 2023 - Bioethics 37 (6):533-542.
    In recent years, there has been a lively (bio-)ethical debate on the nature of moral expertise and the concept of moral experts. However, there is currently no common ground concerning most issues. Against this background, this paper has two main goals. First, in more general terms, it examines some of the problems concerning moral expertise and experts, with a special focus on moral advice and testimony. Second, it applies the results in the context of medical ethics, especially in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  22
    Singapore Modifies the U.K. Montgomery Test and Changes the Standard of Care Doctors Owe to Patients on Medical Advice.Sumytra Menon & Voo Teck Chuan - 2018 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 15 (2):181-183.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  9
    The Case Against Medical Licensing.Edwin A. Locke, Arthur S. Mode & Harry Binswanger - 1980 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 8 (5):13-15.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  23
    Resisting Victim Status: Art Against Medical Nemesis.Frank Green - 1998 - Journal of Medical Humanities 19 (2/3):127-131.
  43.  17
    The Case Against Medical Licensing.Edwin A. Locke, Arthur S. Mode & Harry Binswanger - 1980 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 8 (5):13-15.
  44.  13
    Rights to, in and Against Medical Treatment: Increasing Conflict Of Personal, Professional and Societal Interests.Margaret A. Somerville - 1986 - Monash Bioethics Review 5 (3):5-17.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. Rights to, in and against medical treatment.Margaret Somerville - 1986 - Bioethics News 5 (3):5-17.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  37
    Coercion in the fight against medical brain drain.Nir Eyal & Samia Hurst - unknown
    Several contributions in this book tell of doctors' increasing emigration from developing countries where they are in critical shortage, especially from the underserved rural and public sectors of countries in sub-Saharan Africa (SSA) and South Asia. They point out the severe harm from that migration to some of the world's poorest and sickest populations who have no other doctors to turn to, and gain little from their emigration. Since significant harm to the badly off is bad, decline in that migration (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. The right to choose: A comparative analysis of patient autonomy and body integrity dysphoria among Czech healthcare professionals.Leandro Loriga - 2024 - Ethics and Bioethics (in Central Europe) 14 (1-2):41-60.
    The bioethical principle of autonomy is of paramount importance within medical practice. The extent to which a patient’s autonomy overlaps or conflicts with the physician’s duty of beneficence and non-maleficence, however, is not so clear cut, especially for those cases in which the patient’s request for medical intervention goes against the physician’s advice, either because of personal belief or because there is uncertainty regarding the therapeutic approach. Body integrity dysphoria (BID) is a condition that has been included (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  38
    Organizational ethics and health care: Expanding bioethics to the institutional arena.Laura Jane Bishop, M. Nichelle Cherry & Martina Darragh - 1999 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 9 (2):189-208.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Organizational Ethics and Health Care: Expanding Bioethics to the Institutional Arena **Laura Jane Bishop (bio), M. Nichelle Cherry (bio), and Martina Darragh* (bio)In 1995, the Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations (JCAHO) expanded its patient rights standards to include requirements for assuring that hospital business practices would be ethical. Renamed “Patient Rights and Organization Ethics,” these standards are based on the realization that a hospital’s obligation to its (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  49.  10
    Meaningful futility: requests for resuscitation against medical recommendation.Lucas Vivas & Travis Carpenter - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (10):654-656.
    ‘Futility’ is a contentious term that has eluded clear definition, with proposed descriptions either too strict or too vague to encompass the many facets of medical care. Requests for futile care are often surrogates for requests of a more existential character, covering the whole range of personal, emotional, cultural and spiritual needs. Physicians and other practitioners can use requests for futile care as a valuable opportunity to connect with their patients at a deeper level than the mere biomedical diagnosis. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  11
    Discharging to the Street: When Patients Refuse Medically Safer Options.Denise M. Dudzinski, Jamie L. Shirley, Patsy D. Treece, James N. Kirkpatrick & Georgina D. Campelia - 2022 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 33 (2):92-100.
    The ethical obligation to provide a reasonably safe discharge option from the inpatient setting is often confounded by the context of homelessness. Living without the security of stable housing is a known determinant of poor health, often complicating the safety of discharge and causing unnecessary readmission. But clinicians do not have significant control over unjust distributions of resources or inadequate societal investment in social services. While physicians may stretch inpatient stays beyond acute care need in the interest of their patients (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 997