Results for 'Jonathan E. Adler'

(not author) ( search as author name )
989 found
Order:
  1.  82
    Testimony, Trust, Knowing.Jonathan E. Adler - 1994 - Journal of Philosophy 91 (5):264-275.
  2. Epistemological problems of testimony.Jonathan E. Adler - 2006 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  3. Lying, deceiving, or falsely implicating.Jonathan E. Adler - 1997 - Journal of Philosophy 94 (9):435-452.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  4.  36
    More on race and crime: Levin's reply.Jonathan E. Adler - 1994 - Journal of Social Philosophy 25 (2):105-114.
  5. Akratic believing?Jonathan E. Adler - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 110 (1):1 - 27.
    Davidson's account of weakness of will dependsupon a parallel that he draws between practicaland theoretical reasoning. I argue that theparallel generates a misleading picture oftheoretical reasoning. Once the misleadingpicture is corrected, I conclude that theattempt to model akratic belief on Davidson'saccount of akratic action cannot work. Thearguments that deny the possibility of akraticbelief also undermine, more generally, variousattempts to assimilate theoretical to practicalreasoning.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  6.  19
    The Rationality of Science.Jonathan E. Adler - 1983 - Philosophical Quarterly 33 (130):90-92.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  7.  9
    Knowing, Betting and Cohering.Jonathan E. Adler - 1986 - Philosophical Topics 14 (1):243-257.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  9
    The Logic of Scientific Inference: An Introduction.Jonathan E. Adler - 1982 - Philosophical Quarterly 32 (128):291-291.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  15
    Conversation is the Folks’ Epistemology.Jonathan E. Adler - 2008 - Philosophical Forum 39 (3):337-348.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Moore's paradox and the transparency of belief.Jonathan E. Adler & Bradley Armour-Garb - 2007 - In Mitchell S. Green & John N. Williams (eds.), Moore's Paradox: New Essays on Belief, Rationality, and the First Person. Oxford University Press.
  11. Transmitting knowledge.Jonathan E. Adler - 1996 - Noûs 30 (1):99-111.
  12.  13
    Surprise.Jonathan E. Adler - 2008 - Educational Theory 58 (2):149-173.
    Surprise is of great value for learning, especially in cases where deep‐seated preconceptions and assumptions are upset by vivid demonstrations. In this essay, Jonathan Adler explores the ways in which surprise positively affects us and serves as a valuable tool for motivating learning. Adler considers how students’ attention is aroused and focused self‐critically when their subject matter–related expectations are not borne out. These “surprises” point students toward discoveries about gaps or weaknesses or false assumptions within their subject (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  15
    Conundrums of Belief Self-Control.Jonathan E. Adler - 2002 - The Monist 85 (3):456-467.
    A much disputed conceptual argument aims to show the impossibility of direct believing at will. Regardless of the success of this argument, it has been held to be impotent against indirect forms of belief-control, such as by developing oneself to be more careful or fair-minded in evaluating evidence. However, the shift to indirect forms inherits difficulties connected to the conceptual argument.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  11
    Hume’s “Of Miracles” (Part One).Jonathan E. Adler - 1994 - Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 14 (2):1-10.
  15.  12
    Relevant Alternatives, Presuppositions, and Skepticism.Jonathan E. Adler - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (11):653-654.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  15
    Resisting the Force of Argument.Jonathan E. Adler - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy 106 (6):339-364.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  19
    William James and What Cannot be Believed.Jonathan E. Adler - 2005 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 13 (1):65-79.
    My critical comments focus mainly on premises,, and. However, in treating these I will address other of James’s assumptions—particularly, the presupposition of his argument that it is possible to will to believe. Later I will try to accommodate existential aspects of James’s argument that retain value, even if my objections to his argument stand.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Reliabilist justification (or knowledge) as a good truth-ratio.Jonathan E. Adler - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (4):445–458.
    Fair lotteries offer familiar ways to pose a number of epistemological problems, prominently those of closure and of scepticism. Although these problems apply to many epistemological positions, in this paper I develop a variant of a lottery case to raise a difficulty with the reliabilist's fundamental claim that justification or knowledge is to be analyzed as a high truth-ratio (of the relevant belief-forming processes). In developing the difficulty broader issues are joined including fallibility and the relation of reliability to understanding.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  19.  30
    Abstraction is uncooperative.Jonathan E. Adler - 1984 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 14 (2):165–181.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  20.  36
    Fallacies and alternative interpretations.Jonathan E. Adler - 1994 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72 (3):271 – 282.
  21.  32
    Charity, Interpretation, Fallacy.Jonathan E. Adler - 1996 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 29 (4):329 - 343.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22. Another argument for the knowledge Norm.Jonathan E. Adler - 2009 - Analysis 69 (3):407-411.
    The knowledge norm of assertion is mainly in competition with a high probability or rational credibility norm. The argument for the knowledge norm that I offer turns on cases in which a hearer responds to a speaker's assertion by asserting another sentence that would lower the probability of the speaker's assertion, were its probability less than one. In cases like this, though with qualifications, is the hearer's contribution a challenge to the speaker's assertion or complementary to it? My answer is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  23.  78
    Review of Mark Johnson: Moral imagination: implications of cognitive science for ethics[REVIEW]Jonathan E. Adler - 1995 - Ethics 105 (2):401-404.
  24. The ethics of belief: Off the wrong track.Jonathan E. Adler - 1999 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23 (1):267–285.
  25. Presupposition, attention, and why questions.Jonathan E. Adler - 2008 - In Jonathan Eric Adler & Lance J. Rips (eds.), Reasoning: Studies of Human Inference and its Foundations. Cambridge University Press. pp. 748--764.
  26. Contextualism and fallibility: pragmatic encroachment, possibility, and strength of epistemic position.Jonathan E. Adler - 2012 - Synthese 188 (2):247-272.
    A critique of conversational epistemic contextualism focusing initially on why pragmatic encroachment for knowledge is to be avoided. The data for pragmatic encroachment by way of greater costs of error and the complementary means to raise standards of introducing counter-possibilities are argued to be accountable for by prudence, fallibility and pragmatics. This theme is sharpened by a contrast in recommendations: holding a number of factors constant, when allegedly higher standards for knowing hold, invariantists still recommend assertion (action), while contextualists do (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  27. Withdrawal and contextualism.Jonathan E. Adler - 2006 - Analysis 66 (4):280–285.
  28.  21
    Fallacies Not Fallacious: Not!Jonathan E. Adler - 1997 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 30 (4):333 - 350.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29.  88
    Stove on Hume's inductive scepticism.Jonathan E. Adler - 1975 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 53 (2):167 – 170.
  30.  99
    Conservatism and tacit confirmation.Jonathan E. Adler - 1990 - Mind 99 (396):559-570.
  31. Knowledge and Its Place in Nature.Hilary Kornblith & Jonathan E. Adler - 2004 - Philosophical Quarterly 54 (216):479-482.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  32.  8
    Confidence in Argument.Jonathan E. Adler - 2006 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (2):225-257.
    When someone presents an argument on a charged topic and it is (credibly) alleged that the arguer has a strong personal interest and investment in the conclusion, the allegation, directed to the reception or evaluation of the argument, typically gives rise to two seemingly conflicting reactions:I. The allegation is an unwarranted diversion (a species ofargumentum ad hominemorgenetie fallacy).The prejudices or biases of the arguer are irrelevant to thecogencyof the argument. ('Cogency’ is used broadly to refer both to correct support relations, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33. Skepticism and universalizability.Jonathan E. Adler - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (3):143-156.
  34.  78
    Constrained belief and the reactive attitudes.Jonathan E. Adler - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4):891-905.
    Evidentialism implies that, for epistemic purposes, belief should be responsive only to evidence. Focusing on our reactive attitude such as resentment or indignation, I construct an argument that the beliefs or judgments accompanying those attitudes are constrained in advance by circumstances to be full, rather than being open to the whole range of partial beliefs. These judgments or beliefs imply strong claims to justification. But the circumstances in which those attitudes are formed allow only very limited evidence. Nevertheless, we cannot (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  14
    Knowledge, Truth, and Learning.Jonathan E. Adler - 2003 - In Randall Curren (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Education. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 285–304.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Epistemological Background Educational Applications On Not Addressing Epistemological Controversies.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36. Luckless desert is different desert.Jonathan E. Adler - 1987 - Mind 96 (382):247-249.
  37.  24
    Indirect learning and the aims-curricula fallacy.Jonathan E. Adler - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 27 (2):223–232.
    ABSTRACT I have two main theses. The first is that the inference from accepting an educational aim, especially an ideal aim such as self-realization or critical thinking, to a conclusion as to the content or structure of a curriculum is fallacious. The first thesis should not be controversial. But even if so, the aims-curricula fallacy is readily committed, and that calls for explanation. My second thesis is that the aims–curricula fallacy is often committed because the possibilities for realizing educational aims (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  11
    Indirect Learning and the Aims-Curricula Fallacy.Jonathan E. Adler - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 27 (2):223-232.
    I have two main theses. The first is that the inference from accepting an educational aim, especially an ideal aim such as self-realization or critical thinking, to a conclusion as to the content or structure of a curriculum is fallacious. The first thesis should not be controversial. But even if so, the aims-curricula fallacy is readily committed, and that calls for explanation. My second thesis is that the aims–curricula fallacy is often committed because the possibilities for realizing educational aims through (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  16
    Constrained Belief and the Reactive Attitudes.Jonathan E. Adler - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4):891-905.
    Evidentialism implies that, for epistemic purposes, belief should be responsive only to evidence. Focusing on our reactive attitude such as resentment or indignation, I construct an argument that the beliefs or judgments accompanying those attitudes are constrained in advance by circumstances to be full, rather than being open to the whole range of partial beliefs. These judgments or beliefs imply strong claims to justification. But the circumstances in which those attitudes are formed allow only very limited evidence. Nevertheless, we cannot (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  37
    Crime rates by race and causal relevance: A reply to Levin.Jonathan E. Adler - 1993 - Journal of Social Philosophy 24 (1):176-184.
  41.  48
    Knowing, Betting and Cohering.Jonathan E. Adler - 1986 - Philosophical Topics 14 (1):243-257.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  24
    In Defense of Radical Empiricism: Essays and Lectures.Jonathan E. Adler, Roderick Firth & John Troyer - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (3):453.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43.  43
    Particullary, Gilligan, and the two-levels view: A reply.Jonathan E. Adler - 1989 - Ethics 100 (1):149-156.
  44.  61
    Why Be Charitable?Jonathan E. Adler - 1981 - Informal Logic 4 (2).
  45.  12
    Reply by Repetition and Reminder.Jonathan E. Adler - 1997 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 30 (4):367 - 375.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  5
    Commentary on Cohen.Jonathan E. Adler - unknown
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  8
    Comments on "Developing Philosophies of Childhood".Jonathan E. Adler - 1981 - Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children 2 (3-4):10-10.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  10
    Commentary on Kauffeld & Fields.Jonathan E. Adler - unknown
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  14
    Distortion and Excluded Middles.Jonathan E. Adler - unknown
    Why is there so much distortion in ordinary, political, social, and ethical argument? Since we have a pervasive interest in reasoning well and corresponding abilities, the extent of distortion invites explanation. The leading candidates are the need to economize, widespread, fallacious heuristics or assumptions, and self-defensive biases. I argue that these are not sufficient. An additional force is the intellectual pressure generated by acceptance of norms of conversation and argument, which exclude ‘middles’ of, prominently, neither accept nor reject. I conjecture (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  74
    Epistemic Dependence, Diversity of Ideas, and a Value of Intellectual Vices.Jonathan E. Adler - 1999 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 3:117-129.
    The present argument assumes that teaching through modeling attempts to teach the intellectual virtues not primarily as an independent goal of education as, for example, a way to build good character, but for its value to inquiry. I argue that intellectual vices (such as being gullible, dogmatic, pigheaded, or prejudiced)—while harmful to inquiry in certain ways—are essential to its well functioning. Furthermore, to the extent that teaching models critical inquiry, there are educational lessons for which some students ought to take (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 989