Results for 'Criminal intent. '

989 found
Order:
  1.  3
    Corporate criminal intent.William A. Simpson - unknown
  2.  17
    If Criminal Intentions Are Nonvoluntary, Mandatory Neurointerventions Might Be Permissible.Andrea Lavazza - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 9 (3):154-156.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  69
    Racial Conflation: Agency, Black Action, and Criminal Intent.Alisa Bierria - 2020 - Journal of Social Philosophy (4):575-594.
  4.  20
    S. Azuelos-Atias, A Pragmatic Analysis of Legal Proofs of Criminal Intent [REVIEW].Bernard S. Jackson - 2009 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 22 (3):365-372.
  5.  32
    Delimiting Legal Interpretation: The Problem of Moral Bias and Political Distortion—the Case of Criminal Intention.Izabela Skoczeń & Francesca Poggi - 2022 - Ratio Juris 35 (2):191-222.
  6.  44
    On the logical syntax or linguistic deep structure of certain crime descriptions: Prolegomena to the doctrine of criminal intent.Lennart Åqvist - 1985 - Synthese 65 (2):291 - 306.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Intention and Culpability Concerning Certain Doubts About the Role of Intention in the Criminal Law.J. A. Laing - 1996
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  89
    The Relevance of Intention to Criminal Wrongdoing.Dana Kay Nelkin & Samuel C. Rickless - 2016 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (4):745-762.
    In this paper, we defend the general thesis that intentions are relevant not only to moral permissibility and impermissibility, but also to criminal wrongdoing, as well as a specific version of the Doctrine of Double Effect that we believe can help solve some challenging puzzles in the criminal law. We begin by answering some recent arguments that marginalize or eliminate the role of intentions as components of criminal wrongdoing [e.g., Alexander and Ferzan, Chiao, Walen ]. We then (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  31
    Intention in Criminal Law: The Challenge from Non‐Observational Knowledge.Bebhinn Donnelly-Lazarov - 2017 - Ratio Juris 30 (4):451-470.
    Intention is at the heart of criminal law. If it is not the mens rea requirement found most often in offences, it is still the standard against which other grades of fault tend relatively to be judged. It has generated much controversy, as the crucial question, “Did the defendant intend X?” is resistant to clear answers. This paper argues that intention-questions are difficult because intention is not the thing law takes it to be: Importantly, contrary to law's assumptions, it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  22
    Review of Azuelos-Atias (2007): A Pragmatic Analysis of Legal Proofs of Criminal Intent. [REVIEW]Tal Havkin - 2008 - Pragmatics and Cognition 16 (1):203-213.
  11.  19
    Criminal Legislation against Illegal Income and Corruption: Between Good Intentions and Legitimacy.Oleg Fedosiuk - 2012 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 19 (3):1215-1233.
    Recently (2010–2011) new criminal legislation to combat illegal income and corruption was passed and publicly discussed in Lithuania. Within the list of the new legal measures, special attention should be paid to criminalisation of illicit enrichment, establishment of a model of extended property confiscation, reinforcement of responsibility for corruption-related offenses, a provision that not only property but also personal benefits may constitute a bribe. It can be seen from the explanatory letters attached to the draft laws and the political (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  55
    The Intention Debate in German Criminal Law.Greg Taylor - 2004 - Ratio Juris 17 (3):346-380.
    This article considers the various suggestions that have been put forward by German scholars to replace the traditional concept of intention, which the author has criticized elsewhere (Taylor 2004). The debate on this topic has become a minor academic industry in Germany, and should be better known as the English-speaking world struggles with its own concepts of intention. Despite the great amount of effort and ingenuity devoted to this topic in Germany, however, the author concludes that only one theory of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  46
    Intention, Agency and Criminal Liability: Philosophy of Action and the Criminal Law.Anthony Kenny & R. A. Duff - 1991 - Philosophical Quarterly 41 (164):378.
  14.  34
    Concepts of Intention in German Criminal Law.G. Taylor - 2004 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 24 (1):99-127.
    In German criminal law, intention is the label used not only for cases of knowledge and desire; it also includes cases of what the common law would call recklessness. German criminal law calls its approximation of recklessness dolus eventualis. It is on that concept that the article concentrates. After a brief review of the historical development of the German concept of intention, the author shows that dolus eventualis consists of two components: the cognitive element, which (as in the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  25
    Intention, Agency, and Criminal Liability.Michael Corrado - 1992 - Law and Philosophy 11 (3):265-281.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  16. Criminal liability in a medical context: The treatment of good intentions.Andrew Ashworth - 1996 - In A. P. Simester & A. T. H. Smith (eds.), Harm and culpability. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 173--93.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  79
    The Costs to Criminal Theory of Supposing that Intentions are Irrelevant to Permissibility.Douglas Husak - 2009 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (1):51-70.
    I attempt to describe the several costs that criminal theory would be forced to pay by adopting the view (currently fashionable among moral philosophers) that the intentions of the agent are irrelevant to determinations of whether his actions are permissible (or criminal).
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  18.  19
    Intention, Agency and Criminal Liability: Philosophy of Action and the Criminal Law.Robert W. Hoag - 1992 - Philosophical Books 33 (2):114-116.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  38
    Intention and foresight in criminal law.Hans Oberdiek - 1972 - Mind 81 (323):389-400.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  16
    Intention and Criminal Responsibility.Burleigh T. Wilkins - 1985 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 2 (2):271-278.
  21.  22
    A Matter of Intent: A Social Obligation to Improve Criminal Procedures for Individuals with Dementia.Jalayne J. Arias & Lauren S. Flicker - 2020 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 48 (2):318-327.
    The relationship between dementia and criminal behavior perplexes legal and health care systems. Dementia is a progressive clinical syndrome defined by impairment in at least two cognitive domains that interferes with one's activities of daily. Dementia symptoms have been associated with behaviors that violate social norms and constitute criminal actions. A failure to address a gap in policies that support appropriate management of individuals with dementia reflects a failure in our social obligation to care for those who are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Criminally Ignorant: Why the Law Pretends We Know What We Don't.Alexander Sarch - 2019 - New York, NY, USA: Oup Usa.
    The willful ignorance doctrine says defendants should sometimes be treated as if they know what they don't. This book provides a careful defense of this method of imputing mental states. Though the doctrine is only partly justified and requires reform, it also demonstrates that the criminal law needs more legal fictions of this kind. The resulting theory of when and why the criminal law can pretend we know what we don't has far-reaching implications for legal practice and reveals (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  50
    Criminalizing Health-Related Behaviors Dangerous to Others? Disease Transmission, Transmission-Facilitation, and the Importance of Trust.Leslie Pickering Francis & John G. Francis - 2012 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (1):47-63.
    Statutes criminalizing behavior that risks transmission of HIV/AIDS exemplify use of the criminal law against individuals who are victims of infectious disease. These statutes, despite their frequency, are misguided in terms of the goals of the criminal law and the public health aim of reducing overall burdens of disease, for at least three important reasons. First, they identify individual offenders for punishment, a paradigm that is misplaced in the most typical contexts of transmission of infectious disease and even (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  98
    The philosophy of criminal law: selected essays.Douglas N. Husak - 2010 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Does criminal liability require an act? -- Motive and criminal liability -- The costs to criminal theory of supposing that intentions are irrelevant to permissibility -- Transferred intent -- The nature and justifiability of nonconsummate offenses -- Strict liability, justice, and proportionality -- The sequential principle of relative culpability -- Willful ignorance, knowledge, and the equal culpability thesis : a study of the significance of the principle of legality -- Rapes without rapists : consent and reasonable mistake (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  25.  39
    Strict Criminal Liability in the Grading of Offenses: Forfeiture, Change of Normative Position, or Moral Luck?Kenneth Simons - 2012 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 32 (3):445-466.
    Notwithstanding the demands of retributive desert, strict criminal liability is sometimes defensible when the strict liability pertains, not to whether conduct is to be criminalized at all, but to the seriousness of the actor’s crime. Suppose an actor commits an intentional assault or rape, and accidentally brings about a death. Punishing the actor more seriously because the death resulted is sometimes justifiable, even absent proof of his independent culpability as to the death. But what punishment is proportionate for such (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  37
    Recklessness and Circumstances in Criminal Attempts.Di Yang - 2023 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 17 (2):359-380.
    Criminal attempts require intent to commit an offence. But what constitutes such intent? Some cases are fairly straightforward. I act with intent to convert stolen goods if I intend that the goods I purchase be stolen. A man acts with intent to commit rape if he intends that the sexual intercourse be non-consensual. Other cases leave room for reasonable disagreement. Did a man intend to convert criminal property when he purchased goods which he suspected might be stolen? And (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Intention and Culpability.Jacqueline A. Laing - 1997 - Dissertation, Oxford
    A thesis that aims to demonstrate that intention is an ineradicable feature of the criminal law, both structuring the special part while remaining essential to the general. We cannot without interfering with the natural logic of the criminal law eliminate the concept of intention.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Punishment for criminal attempts: A legal perspective on the problem of moral luck.Thomas Bittner - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (1):pp. 51-83.
    In the criminal law, the law of attempts is of comparatively recent vintage. It is part of an important contemporary legal trend towards early intervention in the criminal process. There are now a substantial number of crimes on the books that, like the crime of attempt, only require that the perpetrator start down the road to carrying out his criminal intentions and do not require him actually to have harmed his victim. Besides the law of attempts, these (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  14
    Punishment for Criminal Attempts.Thomas Bittner - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (1):51-83.
    In the criminal law, the law of attempts is of comparatively recent vintage. It is part of an important contemporary legal trend towards early intervention in the criminal process. There are now a substantial number of crimes on the books that, like the crime of attempt, only require that the perpetrator start down the road to carrying out his criminal intentions and do not require him actually to have harmed his victim. Besides the law of attempts, these (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Punishing Intentions and Neurointerventions.David Birks & Alena Buyx - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 9 (3):133-143.
    How should we punish criminal offenders? One prima facie attractive punishment is administering a mandatory neurointervention—interventions that exert a physical, chemical or biological effect on the brain in order to diminish the likelihood of some forms of criminal offending. While testosterone-lowering drugs have long been used in European and US jurisdictions on sex offenders, it has been suggested that advances in neuroscience raise the possibility of treating a broader range of offenders in the future. Neurointerventions could be a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  31.  20
    Criminal Liability for Negligent Accountancy.Justinas Sigitas Pečkaitis - 2013 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 20 (1):343-357.
    This article presents the conception of negligent account management, analyses the rules of the criminal act that govern criminal liability for negligent account management, by focussing on the form of guilt and the problem of its content. The plenary session’s conclusion that the two offences – failure to administer bookkeeping and failure to protect the bookkeeping documents – can be committed both intentionally and negligently is disputed in this article. The adoption of the new Criminal Code in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  86
    Double Effect and the Criminal Law.Alexander Sarch - 2017 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 11 (3):453-479.
    American criminal law is committed to some version of the doctrine of double effect. In this paper, I defend a new variant of the agent-centered rationale for a version of DDE that is of particular relevance to the criminal law. In particular, I argue for a non-absolute version of DDE that concerns the relative culpability of intending a bad or wrongful state of affairs as opposed to bringing it about merely knowingly. My aim is to identify a particular (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33.  35
    Book Review:Intention, Agency and Criminal Liability. R. A. Duff. [REVIEW]David Dolinko - 1991 - Ethics 102 (1):172-.
  34.  87
    Intention and Attempt.Vincent Chiao - 2010 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 4 (1):37-55.
    Anglo-American criminal law traditionally demands a criminal purpose for an attempt conviction, even when the crime attempted requires only foresight or recklessness. Some legal philosophers have defended this rule by appeal to an alleged difference in the moral character or intentional structure of intended versus non-intended harms. I argue that there are reasons to be skeptical of any such differences; and that even if conceded, it is only on the basis of an unworkable view of criminal responsibility (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  32
    The Jury and Criminal Responsibility in Anglo-American History.Thomas A. Green - 2015 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (3):423-442.
    Anglo-American theories of criminal responsibility require scholars to grapple with, inter alia, the relationship between the formal rule of law and the powers of the lay jury as well as two inherent ideas of freedom: freedom of the will and political liberty. Here, by way of canvassing my past work and prefiguring future work, I sketch some elements of the history of the Anglo-American jury and offer some glimpses of commentary on the interplay between the jury—particularly its application of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  9
    Public health officials and MECs for health should be held criminally liable for causing the death of cancer patients through their intentional or negligent conduct that results in oncology equipment not working in hospitals.D. J. McQuoid-Mason - 2017 - South African Journal of Bioethics and Law 10 (2):83.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  9
    Race, Criminal Law and Ethical Life.Ekow N. Yankah - 2019 - In Larry Alexander & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan (eds.), The Palgrave Handbook of Applied Ethics and the Criminal Law. Springer Verlag. pp. 625-648.
    Race is central to the construction and application of American criminal law and, in turn, criminal law significant to the American racial experience. Yet, there remains controversy about the very nature of the question of “race in criminal law.” This chapter takes up different possible views of race and racism in criminal law, scanning questions surrounding hate crimes and racist intent, before focusing on structural racism in legislation, policing, prosecution, sentencing, mass incarceration and collateral sanctioning as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  40
    Comments on Doug Husak: The Low Cost of Recognizing (and of Ignoring) the Limited Relevance of Intentions to Permissibility.Alec Walen - 2009 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (1):71-78.
    Doug Husak frames a worry that makes sense in the abstract, but in reality, there is not much to worry about. The thesis that intentions are irrelevant to permissibility (IIP) is a straw man. There are reasons to think that the moral significance of intentions is not properly registered in criminal law. But the moral basis for criticism is not nearly as extreme as the IIP, and the fixes are not that hard to make. Lastly, if they are not (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  34
    Is Strict Criminal Liability in the Grading of Offences Consistent with Retributive Desert?Kenneth W. Simons - 2012 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 32 (3):445-466.
    Notwithstanding the demands of retributive desert, strict criminal liability is sometimes defensible when the strict liability pertains, not to whether conduct is to be criminalized at all, but to the seriousness of the actor’s crime. Suppose an actor commits an intentional assault or rape, and accidentally brings about a death. Punishing the actor more seriously because the death resulted is sometimes justifiable, even absent proof of his independent culpability as to the death. But what punishment is proportionate for such (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  90
    Crime and Culpability: A Theory of Criminal Law.Larry Alexander, Kimberly Kessler Ferzan & Stephen J. Morse - 2009 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Kimberly Kessler Ferzan & Stephen J. Morse.
    This book presents a comprehensive overview of what the criminal law would look like if organised around the principle that those who deserve punishment should receive punishment commensurate with, but no greater than, that which they deserve. Larry Alexander and Kimberly Kessler Ferzan argue that desert is a function of the actor's culpability, and that culpability is a function of the risks of harm to protected interests that the actor believes he is imposing and his reasons for acting in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  41. The Abolition of Punishment: Is a Non-Punitive Criminal Justice System Ethically Justified?Przemysław Zawadzki - 2024 - Diametros 21 (79):1-9.
    Punishment involves the intentional infliction of harm and suffering. Both of the most prominent families of justifications of punishment – retributivism and consequentialism – face several moral concerns that are hard to overcome. Moreover, the effectiveness of current criminal punishment methods in ensuring society’s safety is seriously undermined by empirical research. Thus, it appears to be a moral imperative for a modern and humane society to seek alternative means of administering justice. The special issue of Diametros “The Abolition of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  17
    The Legal Fiction in Criminal Proceedings – Is it Historical Anachronism or Objectively Conditional Necessity?Artūras Panomariovas - 2011 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 18 (2):725-738.
    Quite often, for one or the other purpose, the fact (or phenomenon) that does not exist is presented to the society or individuals as the real, really existing although it (the fact or phenomenon) simply does not exist in the real life. And often the term “fiction” is used to describe such phenomena. Although fiction is considered an inseparable companion of a social life, the question arises what the actual (true) fiction is and whether the use of it in (...) proceeding does not mean an intentional law maker’s (or the person’s applying the law) fraud, deceit directed towards the addressee of the applicable law. Fiction and its impact on criminal proceedings is analyzed in this article. Features, characterizing fiction are discussed here as well. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  11
    Moral and Criminal Responsibilities for Free Choice between Good and Evil in the Philosophy of Chŏng Yakyong, with Reference to Matteo Ricci.Jongwoo Yi - 2023 - Comparative and Continental Philosophy 15 (3):195-207.
    Humans must take moral and criminal responsibility for making a free choice between good and evil, according to Chŏng Yakyong, and this view was influenced by Matteo Ricci. Choosing to commit an evil action means committing a willful crime, so one must take responsibility for this action in the form of punishment. However, unintentional wrongdoings can be forgiven. For example, a man stealing to survive or killing a robber in order to live should not be punished, because these individuals (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  59
    The Significance of Transferred Intent.Peter Westen - 2013 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (2):321-350.
    The doctrine of transferred intent (or transferred “malice” in England) generally provides that if A attempts to harm B but, because of bad aim, misses and accidentally causes the same harm to befall C, A’s harmful intent vis-à-vis B is transferred to C, thus rendering A guilty of intentionally harming C. Commentators acknowledge the doctrine to be a legal fiction, but they differ regarding whether the fiction produces just results, some believing it does, others believing that A is guilty at (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  18
    Forensic Epidemiology: Law at the Intersection of Public Health and Criminal Investigations.Richard A. Goodman, Judith W. Munson, Kim Dammers, Zita Lazzarini & John P. Barkley - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (4):684-700.
    Since at least the mid-1970s, public health and law enforcement officials have conducted joint or parallel investigations of both health problems possibly associated with criminal intent and crimes having particular health dimensions. However, the anthrax and other terrorist attacks of fall 2001 have dramatically underscored the needs that public health and law enforcement officials have for a clear understanding of the goals and methods each discipline uses in investigating such problems, including and especially the potential use of biologic agents (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  28
    Review of R. A. Duff: Intention, Agency and Criminal Liability.[REVIEW]David Dolinko - 1991 - Ethics 102 (1):172-173.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  47.  9
    Intention in Law.Gideon Yaffe - 2010 - In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 338–344.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Further reading.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  11
    A Philosophy of Criminal Attempts.Bebhinn Donnelly-Lazarov - 2015 - Cambridge University Press.
    An investigation of criminal attempts unearths some of the most fundamental, intriguing and perplexing questions about criminal law and its place in human action. When does attempting begin? What is the relationship between attempting and intending? Do we always attempt the possible and, if so, possible to whom? Does attempting involve action and does action involve attempting? Is my attempt fixed by me or can another perspective reveal what it is? How 'much' action is needed for an attempt, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  28
    Intentional collaboration, predictable complicity, and proactive prevention: U.S. schools’ ethical responsibilities in slowing the school-to-deportation pipeline.Tatiana Geron & Meira Levinson - 2018 - Journal of Global Ethics 14 (1):23-33.
    ABSTRACTIn the United States, constitutional and statutory law reinforce the right of all children to receive an education, regardless of their citizenship or immigration status. In a time of heightened anti-immigrant sentiment and law enforcement, however, partnerships among school districts, local law enforcement, and the U.S. Departments of Justice and Homeland Security subject undocumented and unaccompanied minor students to indefensible levels of risk for detention and deportation. We identify three stances that U.S. schools may take in the face of a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  34
    Two Models of Criminal Fault.R. A. Duff - 2019 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 13 (4):643-665.
    I discuss two problems for the standard Anglo-American account of recklessness, and the distinctions between intention, recklessness, and negligence. One problem concerns the over-breadth of recklessness as thus defined—that it covers agents whose actions display different kinds of culpability. The other problem concerns the importance attached to awareness of risk in distinguishing recklessness from negligence—that one who is unaware of the risk that he takes or creates sometimes displays just the same kind of fault as an advertent risk-taker. We can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 989