Results for 'Andreas Kamlah'

(not author) ( search as author name )
999 found
Order:
  1. Anschauliches und symbolisches Denken.Andreas Kamlah - 1997 - In Alex Burri (ed.), Sprache und Denken =. New York: W. de Gruyter.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  30
    An improved definition of 'theoretical in a given theory'.Andreas Kamlah - 1976 - Erkenntnis 10 (3):349 - 359.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  3.  3
    Der Aufstieg der wissenschaftlichen Philosophie.Hans Reichenbach, Andreas Kamlah & Wesley C. Salmon - 1968 - Braunschweig,: Vieweg.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  4.  33
    Invarianzgesetze und zeitmetrik.Andreas Kamlah - 1973 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 4 (2):224-260.
    Modern Philosophy of Science has not yet recognized the significance of physical invariance principles for science and daily life. In this paper we investigate as a simple example, how time independence or time translational invariance of natural laws determines the time scale. We start with informal definitions of the invariance of concepts and laws. We then ask if time independence is an essential feature of natural laws or if time dependent laws are plausible without loss of predictive relevance. In section (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  5.  28
    Wie arbeitet die analytische wissenschaftstheorie?Andreas Kamlah - 1980 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 11 (1):23-44.
    Summary In the last decade analytical philosophy of science has been considered by many people as a descriptive activity. In part I of this paper we show that philosophy of science has been designed as normative logical analysis by Reichenbach and Carnap before world war II. Thus the identification analytical = descriptive is historically unjustified. In part II we discuss three tasks of analytical philosophy of science, the logical reconstruction of concepts, theories, and methods. While the first is mainly descriptive, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  6.  61
    Kants Antwort auf Hume und eine linguistische Analyse seiner Modalbegriffe.Andreas Kamlah - 2009 - Kant Studien 100 (1):28-52.
    The concept of necessity plays a central role in Kant's philosophy, but seems to lead to severe paradoxes. On the one hand he states: ‘Notwendigkeit und strenge Allgemeinheit sind sichere Kennzeichen einer Erkenntnis a priori’. On the other hand he talks also about ‘notwendig (d. i. nach einer Regel)’, which means ‘necessary according to the empirical natural laws’. However, he never states explicitly the distinction between these two different concepts of necessity. Either Kant's philosophy is inconsistent or we have to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7.  12
    Invarianzgesetze und Zeitmetrik.Andreas Kamlah - 1973 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 4 (2):224-260.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8.  46
    On reduction of theories.Andreas Kamlah - 1985 - Erkenntnis 22 (1-3):119 - 142.
  9.  66
    Probability as a quasi-theoretical concept — J.V. Kries' sophisticated account after a century.Andreas Kamlah - 1983 - Erkenntnis 19 (1-3):239 - 251.
    These arguments are fairly well known today. It is interesting to note that v. Kries already knew them, and that they have been ignored by Reichenbach and v. Mises in their original account of probability.2This observation leads to the interesting question why the frequency theory of probability has been adopted by many people in our century in spite of severe counterarguments. One may think of a change in scientific attitude, of a scientific revolution put forward by Feyerabendarian propaganda- and who (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  11
    Wie arbeitet die analytische Wissenschaftstheorie?Andreas Kamlah - 1980 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 11 (1):23-44.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  26
    Everybody Has the Right to Do What He Wants: Hans Reichenbach's Volitionism and Its Historical Roots.Andreas Kamlah - 2013 - In Nikolay Milkov & Volker Peckhaus (eds.), The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism. Springer. pp. 151--175.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  90
    Hans Reichenbach's relativity of geometry.Andreas Kamlah - 1977 - Synthese 34 (3):249 - 263.
    Hans Reichenbach's 1928 thesis of the relativity of geometry has been misunderstood as the statement that the geometrical structure of space can be described in different languages. In this interpretation the thesis becomes an instance of trivial semantical conventionalism, as Grünbaum calls it. To understand Reichenbach correctly, we have to interpret it in the light of the linguistic turn, the transition from thought oriented philosophy to language oriented philosophy, which mainly took place in the first decades of our century. Reichenbach (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  28
    Methode oder dogma?Andreas Kamlah - 1981 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (1):138-162.
    Summary Some leading ideas of the constructivist protophysics are discussed on the basis of P. Janich's Protophysik der Zeit. After having reviewed the contents of the second edition Janich's claim that analytical philosophy of science is purely affirmative and not critical towards science in its historical appearence is refuted. In the next section the principles of constructivist methodology of physics are criticised, and the claim is refuted that prescriptions for measurement cannot without circularity be shown to be invalid by experimental (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  12
    Methode oder Dogma?Andreas Kamlah - 1981 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (1):138-162.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  44
    The causal relation as the most fundamental fact of the world. Comments on Hans Reichenbach's paper: The space problem in the new quantum mechanics.Andreas Kamlah - 1991 - Erkenntnis 35 (1-3):49 - 60.
  16.  10
    Methode oder Dogma?: Eine Auseinandersetzung mit der zweiten Auflage von P. Janichs Protophysik der Zeit.Andreas Kamlah - 1981 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (1):138-162.
    Some leading ideas of the constructivist protophysics are discussed on the basis of P. Janich's Protophysik der Zeit. After having reviewed the contents of the second edition Janich's claim that analytical philosophy of science is purely affirmative and not critical towards science in its historical appearence is refuted. In the next section the principles of constructivist methodology of physics are criticised, and the claim is refuted that prescriptions for measurement cannot without circularity be shown to be invalid by experimental results. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  47
    The connexion between Reichenbach's three-valued and V. Neumann's lattice-theoretical quantum logic.Andreas Kamlah - 1981 - Erkenntnis 16 (3):315 - 325.
  18.  10
    Die exakte Beschreibung von Naturvorgängen. Das Problem der exakten Beschreibung.Andreas Kamlah - 1977 - In Manfred Riedel & Jürgen Mittelstraß (eds.), Vernünftiges Denken: Studien Zur Praktischen Philosophie Und Wissenschaftstheorie. New York: De Gruyter. pp. 194-216.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Der Griff der Sprache nach der Natur.Andreas Kamlah - 2006 - Erkenntnis 65 (3):433-440.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  45
    Die logische struktur der operationalen definitionen.Andreas Kamlah - 2006 - Philosophia Naturalis 43 (2):195-213.
    Operational definitions were once considered the backbone of semantics of natural science. Still in 1955 A. W. Burks published an explication of the general scheme of these definitions. In the fifties of the last century however they became outmoded, while high school teachers for presumably good reasons were still in favour of them. I consider the banishment of this kind of definitions premature, and try to improve the explication of Burks in a way which qualifies them for a rehabilitation. In (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  2
    Hans Reichenbachs Beziehung zum Wiener Kreis.Andreas Kamlah - 1985 - In Hans J. Dahms (ed.), Philosophie, Wissenschaft, Aufklärung: Beiträge zur Geschichte und Wirkung des Wiener Kreises. De Gruyter. pp. 221-236.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Hans Reichenbach: Grundzüge der symbolischen Logik.Andreas Kamlah & Maria Reichenbach (eds.) - 1999 - Vieweg.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  17
    Metagesetze und theorieunabhängige bedeutung physikalischer begriffe.Andreas Kamlah - 1978 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 9 (1):41-62.
    The determination of the meaning of theoretical terms by the axioms of theories as meaning postulates and the merely fictitious character of a basic observational language leads to Feyerabends problem of the incommensurability of physical theories. Different theories are actually compared by physicists as well. They might have a common sub-language as the language of macroscopic physics in atomic physics. Furthermore shared metalaws define an equivalence relation which identifies terms of different theories and enables physicists to talk about them in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  10
    Metagesetze und theorieunabhängige Bedeutung physikalischer Begriffe.Andreas Kamlah - 1978 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 9 (1):41-62.
    The determination of the meaning of theoretical terms by the axioms of theories as meaning postulates and the merely fictitious character of a basic observational language leads to Feyerabends problem of the incommensurability of physical theories. Different theories are actually compared by physicists as well. They might have a common sublanguage as the language of macroscopic physics in atomic physics. Furthermore shared metalaws (e. g. invariance principles) define an equivalence relation which identifies terms of different theories and enables physicists to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  8
    Reflexionen über die struktur der physikalischen sprache.Andreas Kamlah - 2001 - Erkenntnis 54 (1):39-53.
    The aim of this paper is to discuss how far physics differs frommathematics, and if a philosophy of science which uses mathematics or logicsas a model for physics would be unable to be aware of many importantfeatures of that natural science.Many functions in physics differ from those of mathematics in beingfunctional dependecies and in having a lawlike character.Physical quantities have the character of "`determinables"'', sets ofspecial entities which are presupposed by physical theories.One may suspect that physics also could not be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  39
    Some remarks on a paper by P. Suppes.Andreas Kamlah - 1981 - Erkenntnis 16 (3):327 - 333.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  38
    What can methodologists learn from the history of probability.Andreas Kamlah - 1987 - Erkenntnis 26 (3):305 - 325.
  28.  2
    Zur diskussion um die protophysik.Andreas Kamlah - 1978 - In Kuno Lorenz (ed.), Konstruktionen Versus Positionen: Beiträge Zur Diskussion Um Die Konstruktive Wissenschaftstheorie. Bd 1: Spezielle Wissenschaftstheorie. Bd 2: Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie. Paul Lorenzen Zum 60. Geburtstag. New York: De Gruyter. pp. 311-339.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Philosophische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik Und Wahrscheinlichkeit.Hans Reichenbach & Andreas Kamlah - 1989
  30.  16
    Review. [REVIEW]Andreas Kamlah - 1986 - Erkenntnis 24 (2):235-252.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  19
    Eine anmerkung zu Andreas kamlahs darstellung der 'normativ-analytischen' wissenschaftstheorie.Ulrich Charpa - 1981 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (1):135-137.
    In an illuminating article A. Kamlah considers philosophy of science as an activity leading step by step from neutral descriptions to rational prescriptions. What his remarks do not offer us is a way of dealing with the troublesome ambiguities we find in the analyses provided by those philosophers of science who refuse to say whether they legislate how scientists should behave or describe how they do. In this context I want to draw attention to a helpful distinction H. A. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  1
    Eine Anmerkung zu Andreas Kamlahs Darstellung der ‘normativ-analytischen’ Wissenschaftstheorie.Ulrich Charpa - 1981 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (1):135-137.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  7
    Philosophy of science: an introduction for future knowledge workers.Andreas Beck Holm - 2013 - Frederiksberg C: Samfundslitteratur.
    A student's future as a knowledge worker (one who "thinks for a living" with the task of problem solving) is the starting point of this book. With this in mind, the book combines a review of philosophical positions and problems with practical examples and perspectives gained from everyday challenges faced by knowledge workers in their businesses and organizations. Through the use of summative chapters, highlighted key concepts, questions for reflection, and illustrative examples on how to work with the theories presented, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  3
    Alfabeto delle proprietà: filosofia in metafore e storie.Andrea Tagliapietra - 2016 - Bergamo: Moretti&Vitali.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  9
    Pregnancy loss care should not be biased in favour of human gestation.Andrea Bidoli - 2024 - Journal of Medical Ethics 50 (5):312-313.
    In their paper, Romanis and Adkins delve into the potential impact of artificial amnion and placenta technology (AAPT) on cases of pregnancy loss1 that do not involve procreative loss. First, they call for more recognition of the negative feelings a person might have due to the premature end of their pregnant state. They claim that, should AAPT minimise concerns about prematurity as anticipated, individuals might feel pressured to opt for partial ectogestation to preserve their or their fetus’ well-being; moreover, they (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  97
    The responsibility gap: Ascribing responsibility for the actions of learning automata.Andreas Matthias - 2004 - Ethics and Information Technology 6 (3):175-183.
    Traditionally, the manufacturer/operator of a machine is held (morally and legally) responsible for the consequences of its operation. Autonomous, learning machines, based on neural networks, genetic algorithms and agent architectures, create a new situation, where the manufacturer/operator of the machine is in principle not capable of predicting the future machine behaviour any more, and thus cannot be held morally responsible or liable for it. The society must decide between not using this kind of machine any more (which is not a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  37.  44
    Mapping the Dimensions of Agency.Andreas Schönau, Ishan Dasgupta, Timothy Brown, Erika Versalovic, Eran Klein & Sara Goering - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 12 (2):172-186.
    Neural devices have the capacity to enable users to regain abilities lost due to disease or injury – for instance, a deep brain stimulator (DBS) that allows a person with Parkinson’s disease to regain the ability to fluently perform movements or a Brain Computer Interface (BCI) that enables a person with spinal cord injury to control a robotic arm. While users recognize and appreciate the technologies’ capacity to maintain or restore their capabilities, the neuroethics literature is replete with examples of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  38. Wittgenstein and Heidegger against a Science of Aesthetics.Andreas Vrahimis - 2020 - Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 57 (1):64-85.
    Wittgenstein’s and Heidegger’s objections against the possibility of a science of aesthetics were influential on different sides of the analytic/continental divide. Heidegger’s anti-scientism leads him to an alētheic view of artworks which precedes and exceeds any possible aesthetic reduction. Wittgenstein also rejects the relevance of causal explanations, psychological or physiological, to aesthetic questions. The main aim of this paper is to compare Heidegger with Wittgenstein, showing that: there are significant parallels to be drawn between Wittgenstein’s and Heidegger’s anti-scientism about aesthetics, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  48
    Scienza e società della conoscenza.Andrea Cerroni - 2006 - Torino: UTET università.
    Anche se siamo comunemente abituati a pensare alla scienza come a un qualcosa di assolutamente atemporale e indipendente da tutto, in realtà essa è profondamente influenzata dalla cultura e dalla società del tempo in cui vive. Infatti né la scienza è isolabile dalla società, né la società è isolabile dalla scienza, tanto meno come si sta configurando oggi. Per approfondire questi aspetti, esistono però due visioni antagoniste che bisogna superare: secondo la visione scolastica, retaggio del positivismo ottocentesco ancora molto diffuso (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  9
    L'incubo degli ultimi uomini: etica e politica in Max Weber.Dimitri D'Andrea - 2005 - Roma: Carocci.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. A Radical Relationist Solution to the Problem of Intentional Inexistence.Andrea Marchesi - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):7509-7534.
    The problem of intentional inexistence arises because the following (alleged) intuitions are mutually conflicting: it seems that sometimes we think about things that do not exist; it seems that intentionality is a relation between a thinker and what such a thinker thinks about; it seems that relations entail the existence of what they relate. In this paper, I argue for what I call a radical relationist solution. First, I contend that the extant arguments for the view that relations entail the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42. The Concept and Necessity of an End in Ethics.Andreas Trampota - 2013 - In Andreas Trampota, Oliver Sensen & Jens Timmermann (eds.), Kant’s “Tugendlehre”. A Comprehensive Commentary. Boston: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 139-158.
  43. A Systematic Reconstruction of Brentano’s Theory of Consciousness.Andrea Marchesi - 2022 - Topoi 41 (1):123-132.
    In recent years, Brentano’s theory of consciousness has been systematically reassessed. The reconstruction that has received the most attention is the so-called identity reconstruction. It says that secondary consciousness and the mental phenomenon it is about are one and the same. Crucially, it has been claimed that this thesis is the only one which can make Brentano’s theory immune to what he considers the main threat to it, namely, the duplication of the primary object. In this paper, I argue that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  11
    Arguments against Ronald Dworkin’s liberal egalitarianism.Andrea Luisa Bucchile Faggion - 2017 - Filosofia Unisinos 18 (3):146-154.
    In A Matter of Principle, Ronald Dworkin discusses the role a political morality should play in decisions about when the law should be obeyed and enforced, and even what law is. Noticing that liberalism was once a quasi-consensus theory in Great Britain and the United States – and, therefore, a natural candidate to that role in those countries – Dworkin argues that the loss of that status is due to an alleged failure of liberal political theorists to identify a kind (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  5
    Metaethical assumptions of philosophical anarchism.Andrea Luisa Bucchile Faggion - 2020 - Ethic@: An International Journal for Moral Philosophy 19 (1):33–48.
    As a positive thesis, philosophical anarchism claims that political authority is always at odds with practical rationality insomuch as authoritative directives are best analysed as content-independent reasons. The aim of this paper is to clarify the metaethical assumptions behind such a claim. Since philosophical anarchists reject as irrational the possibility that an agent can follow content-independent reasons issued by another agent, emphasising agents’ responsibility to assess the content of every directive before acting in conformity with it, it is safe to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. On transcendental semantics beyond critique of pure reason, p. 165-170.Andrea Luisa Bucchile Faggion - 2007 - Kant E-Prints 2:165-170.
    It is safe to say that the main line of criticism against the reading of Critical Philosophy as Transcendental Semantics is that Kant would be concerned about semantic problems only on Critique of Pure Reason so that such reading would not make sense beyond that work. In this paper, I describe Transcendental Semantics in short words and analyze at length Kant’s theory of concepts on Transcendental Analytic of Critique of Pure Reason in order to make a suggestion: every concept has (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  27
    Geometry by ropes and rods.W. Balzer & A. Kamlah - 1980 - Erkenntnis 15 (2):245 - 267.
  48. Naïve Truth and the Evidential Conditional.Iacona Andrea & Lorenzo Rossi - 2024 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 1:1-26.
    This paper develops the idea that valid arguments are equivalent to true conditionals by combining Kripke’s theory of truth with the evidential account of conditionals offered by Crupi and Iacona. As will be shown, in a first-order language that contains a naïve truth predicate and a suitable conditional, one can define a validity predicate in accordance with the thesis that the inference from a conjunction of premises to a conclusion is valid when the corresponding conditional is true. The validity predicate (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The Value of the One Value: Exactly True Logic revisited.Andreas Kapsner & Umberto Rivieccio - 2023 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 52 (5):1417-1444.
    In this paper we re-assess the philosophical foundation of Exactly True Logic ($$\mathcal {ET\!L}$$ ET L ), a competing variant of First Degree Entailment ($$\mathcal {FDE}$$ FDE ). In order to do this, we first rebut an argument against it. As the argument appears in an interview with Nuel Belnap himself, one of the fathers of $$\mathcal {FDE}$$ FDE, we believe its provenance to be such that it needs to be taken seriously. We submit, however, that the argument ultimately fails, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. The Vienna Circle’s reception of Nietzsche.Andreas Vrahimis - 2020 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 8 (9):1-29.
    Friedrich Nietzsche was among the figures from the history of nineteenth century philosophy that, perhaps surprisingly, some of the Vienna Circle’s members had presented as one of their predecessors. While, primarily for political reasons, most Anglophone figures in the history of analytic philosophy had taken a dim view of Nietzsche, the Vienna Circle’s leader Moritz Schlick admired and praised Nietzsche, rejecting what he saw as a misinterpretation of Nietzsche as a militarist or proto-fascist. Schlick, Frank, Neurath, and Carnap were in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 999