Results for 'quantification of the predicate'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  25
    The politics of modern reason: Politics, anti-politics and norms on continental philosophy, James Bohman.Quantification Parts & Aristotelian Predication - 1999 - The Monist 82 (2).
  2. Quantification of the predicate and many-sorted logic.William Tuthill Parry - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 26 (3):342-360.
  3.  46
    XI.—Hamilton's Quantification of the Predicate.W. Bednarowski - 1956 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56 (1):217-240.
    This paper consists roughly of three parts. In the first part, an attempt has been made to find some tenable interpretation of Hamilton's logic. This results in accepting that Hamilton's logic can be "saved" if it is understood as being an everday language version of Euler's relations, i.e., extensional relations between terms. In the second part, the propositions of Euler and the propositions of Aristotle are compared and found to be interdefinable: every proposition of Aristotle can be defined by a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  24
    Hamilton's quantification of the predicate.Robert J. Fogelin - 1976 - Philosophical Quarterly 26 (104):217-228.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  42
    Euler-type Diagrams and the Quantification of the Predicate.Jens Lemanski - 2020 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 49 (2):401-416.
    Logicians have often suggested that the use of Euler-type diagrams has influenced the idea of the quantification of the predicate. This is mainly due to the fact that Euler-type diagrams display more information than is required in traditional syllogistics. The paper supports this argument and extends it by a further step: Euler-type diagrams not only illustrate the quantification of the predicate, but also solve problems of traditional proof theory, which prevented an overall quantification of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  6.  75
    Aristotle’s Logic and the Quest for the Quantification of the Predicate.Bert Mosselmans - 2008 - Foundations of Science 13 (3-4):195-198.
    This paper examines the quest for the quantification of the predicate, as discussed by W.S. Jevons, and relates it to the discussion about universals and particulars between Plato and Aristotle. We conclude that the quest for the quantification of the predicate can only be achieved by stripping the syllogism from its metaphysical heritage.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  22
    Aristotle’s Logic and the Quest for the Quantification of the Predicate.Michael Burke, Mark Janse & Bert Mosselmans - 2008 - Foundations of Science 13 (3-4):195-198.
    This paper examines the quest for the quantification of the predicate, as discussed by W.S. Jevons, and relates it to the discussion about universals and particulars between Plato and Aristotle. We conclude that the quest for the quantification of the predicate can only be achieved by stripping the syllogism from its metaphysical heritage.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  23
    Timothy Smiley. Syllogism and quantification. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 27 no. 1 , pp. 58–72. - William Tuthill Parry. Quantification of the predicate and many-sorted logic. Philosophy and phenomenological research, vol. 26 no. 3 , pp. 342–360. [REVIEW]John Bacon - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (4):606-607.
  9.  9
    Review of The Logical Copula and Quantification of the Predicate[REVIEW]John Grier Hibben - 1897 - Psychological Review 4 (5):535-535.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Basic Laws of the Predicate Calculus.John-Michael Kuczynski - 2018
    The most basic laws and principles of the Predicate Calculus, also known as Quantification Theory, are stated, as clearly and concisely as possible.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Quantification and the Nature of Crosslinguistic Variation.Lisa Matthewson - 2001 - Natural Language Semantics 9 (2):145-189.
    The standard analysis of quantification says that determiner quantifiers (such as every) take an NP predicate and create a generalized quantifier. The goal of this paper is to subject these beliefs to crosslinguistic scrutiny. I begin by showing that in St'á'imcets (Lillooet Salish), quantifiers always require sisters of argumental type, and the creation of a generalized quantifier from an NP predicate always proceeds in two steps rather than one. I then explicitly adopt the strong null hypothesis that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  12. Predicate abstraction, the limits of quantification, and the modality of existence.Philip Percival - 2011 - Philosophical Studies 156 (3):389-416.
    For various reasons several authors have enriched classical first order syntax by adding a predicate abstraction operator. “Conservatives” have done so without disturbing the syntax of the formal quantifiers but “revisionists” have argued that predicate abstraction motivates the universal quantifier’s re-classification from an expression that combines with a variable to yield a sentence from a sentence, to an expression that combines with a one-place predicate to yield a sentence. My main aim is to advance the cause of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Unrestricted Quantification and the Structure of Type Theory.Salvatore Florio & Nicholas K. Jones - 2021 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 102 (1):44-64.
    Semantic theories based on a hierarchy of types have prominently been used to defend the possibility of unrestricted quantification. However, they also pose a prima facie problem for it: each quantifier ranges over at most one level of the hierarchy and is therefore not unrestricted. It is difficult to evaluate this problem without a principled account of what it is for a quantifier to be unrestricted. Drawing on an insight of Russell’s about the relationship between quantification and the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  14.  29
    Abstract Forms of Quantification in the Quantified Argument Calculus.Edi Pavlović & Norbert Gratzl - 2023 - Review of Symbolic Logic 16 (2):449-479.
    The Quantified argument calculus (Quarc) has received a lot of attention recently as an interesting system of quantified logic which eschews the use of variables and unrestricted quantification, but nonetheless achieves results similar to the Predicate calculus (PC) by employing quantifiers applied directly to predicates instead. Despite this noted similarity, the issue of the relationship between Quarc and PC has so far not been definitively resolved. We address this question in the present paper, and then expand upon that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15. Rigid and flexible quantification in plural predicate logic.Lucas Champollion, Justin Bledin & Haoze Li - forthcoming - Semantics and Linguistic Theory 27.
    Noun phrases with overt determiners, such as <i>some apples</i> or <i>a quantity of milk</i>, differ from bare noun phrases like <i>apples</i> or <i>milk</i> in their contribution to aspectual composition. While this has been attributed to syntactic or algebraic properties of these noun phrases, such accounts have explanatory shortcomings. We suggest instead that the relevant property that distinguishes between the two classes of noun phrases derives from two modes of existential quantification, one of which holds the values of a variable (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  50
    Parts, Quantification and Aristotelian Predication.Mario Mignucci - 2000 - The Monist 83 (1):3-21.
    Reading through the Corpus Aristotelicum we come across a group of expressions meant to indicate predicative relations, which lead us to think that Aristotle connected predication to a part-whole relation. He frequently calls the ‘εἴδη’, “species”, ‘μέρη’, “parts”, of their genera. More generally, the universal is said to contain that of which it is true. In a parallel way, what is contained by something is also what is under something else. Again, it is quite common for him to consider the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  17.  51
    Double quantification and the meaning of shenme 'what' in chinese bare conditionals.Jo-Wang Lin - 1999 - Linguistics and Philosophy 22 (6):573-593.
    This paper shows that the semantics of shenme ‘what’ in Chinese bare conditionals may exhibit a phenomenon of double quantification. I argue that such double quantification can be nicely accounted for if one adopts Carlson's (1977a, b) semantics of bare plurals and verb meanings as well as the following two assumptions: (i) shenme ‘what’ can be a proform of bare NPs and hence has the same kind of denotation as bare NPs, and (ii) Chinese bare NPs are names (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  19
    Double Quantification and the Meaning of Shenme ‘What’ in Chinese Bare Conditionals.L. Jo-Wang - 1999 - Linguistics and Philosophy 22 (6):573-593.
    This paper shows that the semantics of shenme ‘what’ in Chinese bare conditionals may exhibit a phenomenon of double quantification. I argue that such double quantification can be nicely accounted for if one adopts Carlson's (1977a, b) semantics of bare plurals and verb meanings as well as the following two assumptions: (i) shenme ‘what’ can be a proform of bare NPs and hence has the same kind of denotation as bare NPs, and (ii) Chinese bare NPs are names (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. On the Semantics of Existence Predicates.Friederike Moltmann - 2010 - In Ingo Reich (ed.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 15, Saarbruecken. pp. 31-54.
    The most common philosophical view about the notion of existence is that it is a second-order property or existential quantification. A less common view is that existence is a (first-order) property of 'existent' as opposed to 'nonexistent' (past or merely intentional) objects. An even less common view is that existence divides into different 'modes of being' for different sorts of entities. In this paper I will take a closer look at the semantic behavior of existence predicates in natural language, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20. Deflationism: A Use-Theoretic Analysis of the Truth-Predicate.Arvid Båve - 2006 - Dissertation, Stockholm University
    I here develop a specific version of the deflationary theory of truth. I adopt a terminology on which deflationism holds that an exhaustive account of truth is given by the equivalence between truth-ascriptions and de-nominalised (or disquoted) sentences. An adequate truth-theory, it is argued, must be finite, non-circular, and give a unified account of all occurrences of “true”. I also argue that it must descriptively capture the ordinary meaning of “true”, which is plausibly taken to be unambiguous. Ch. 2 is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  21.  46
    P. C. Gilmore. A program for the production from axioms, of proofs for theorems derivable within the first order predicate calculus. English, with English, French, German, Russian, and Spanish summaries. Information processing, Proceedings of the International Conference on Information Processing, Unesco, Paris 15–20 June 1959, Unesco, Paris, R. Oldenbourg, Munich, Butterworths, London, 1960, pp. 265–273. - J. Porte, P. C. Gilmore, Dag H. Prawitz, Håkon Prawitz, and Neri Voghera. Discussion. Information processing, Proceedings of the International Conference on Information Processing, Unesco, Paris 15–20 June 1959, Unesco, Paris, R. Oldenbourg, Munich, Butterworths, London, 1960, p. 273. - P. C. Gilmore. A proof method for quantification theory: Its justification and realization. IBM journal of research and development, vol. 4 , pp. 28–35. [REVIEW]J. A. Robinson - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):124-125.
  22.  37
    Ploucquet’s “Refutation” of the Traditional Square of Opposition.Wolfgang Lenzen - 2008 - Logica Universalis 2 (1):43-58.
    . In the 18th century, Gottfried Ploucquet developed a new syllogistic logic where the categorical forms are interpreted as set-theoretical identities, or diversities, between the full extension, or a non-empty part of the extension, of the subject and the predicate. With the help of two operators ‘O’ (for “Omne”) and ‘Q’ (for “Quoddam”), the UA and PA are represented as ‘O(S) – Q(P)’ and ‘Q(S) – Q(P)’, respectively, while UN and PN take the form ‘O(S) > O(P)’ and ‘Q(S) (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  17
    Neuromimetic Semantics: Coordination, Quantification, and Collective Predicates.Harry Howard - 2004 - Elsevier.
    This book attempts to marry truth-conditional semantics with cognitive linguistics in the church of computational neuroscience. To this end, it examines the truth-conditional meanings of coordinators, quantifiers, and collective predicates as neurophysiological phenomena that are amenable to a neurocomputational analysis. Drawing inspiration from work on visual processing, and especially the simple/complex cell distinction in early vision (V1), we claim that a similar two-layer architecture is sufficient to learn the truth-conditional meanings of the logical coordinators and logical quantifiers. As a prerequisite, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  32
    Satisfying Predicates: Kleene's Proof of the Hilbert–Bernays Theorem.Gary Ebbs - 2015 - History and Philosophy of Logic 36 (4):346-366.
    The Hilbert–Bernays Theorem establishes that for any satisfiable first-order quantificational schema S, one can write out linguistic expressions that are guaranteed to yield a true sentence of elementary arithmetic when they are substituted for the predicate letters in S. The theorem implies that if L is a consistent, fully interpreted language rich enough to express elementary arithmetic, then a schema S is valid if and only if every sentence of L that can be obtained by substituting predicates of L (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  14
    On Zardini’s Rules for Multiplicative Quantification as the Source of Contra(di)Ctions.Uwe Petersen - 2023 - Review of Symbolic Logic 16 (4):1110-1119.
    Certain instances of contraction are provable in Zardini’s system $\mathbf {IK}^\omega $ which causes triviality once a truth predicate and suitable fixed points are available.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Reading the Book of the World.Thomas Donaldson - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (4):1051-1077.
    In Writing the Book of the World, Ted Sider argues that David Lewis’s distinction between those predicates which are ‘perfectly natural’ and those which are not can be extended so that it applies to words of all semantic types. Just as there are perfectly natural predicates, there may be perfectly natural connectives, operators, singular terms and so on. According to Sider, one of our goals as metaphysicians should be to identify the perfectly natural words. Sider claims that there is a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  27.  41
    Non-traditional squares of predication and quantification.Mireille Staschok - 2008 - Logica Universalis 2 (1):77-85.
    . Three logical squares of predication or quantification, which one can even extend to logical hexagons, will be presented and analyzed. All three squares are based on ideas of the non-traditional theory of predication developed by Sinowjew and Wessel. The authors also designed a non-traditional theory of quantification. It will be shown that this theory is superfluous, since it is based on an obscure difference between two kinds of quantification and one pays a high price for differentiating (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  71
    Standard quantification theory in the analysis of English.Stephen Donaho - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (6):499-526.
    Standard first-order logic plus quantifiers of all finite orders ("SFOLω") faces four well-known difficulties when used to characterize the behavior of certain English quantifier phrases. All four difficulties seem to stem from the typed structure of SFOLω models. The typed structure of SFOLω models is in turn a product of an asymmetry between the meaning of names and the meaning of predicates, the element-set asymmetry. In this paper we examine a class of models in which this asymmetry of meaning is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  46
    Extensionality in natural language quantification: the case of many and few.Kristen A. Greer - 2014 - Linguistics and Philosophy 37 (4):315-351.
    This paper presents an extensional account of manyand few that explains data that have previously motivated intensional analyses of these quantifiers :599–620, 2000). The key insight is that their semantic arguments are themselves set intersections: the restrictor is the intersection of the predicates denoted by the N’ or the V’ and the restricted universe, U, and the scope is the intersection of the N’ and V’. Following Cohen, I assume that the universe consists of the union of alternatives to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  31
    The Completeness of Carnap's Predicate Logic.Max Cresswell - 2014 - Australasian Journal of Logic 11 (1).
    The paper first proves the completeness of the first-order predicate logic presented in Carnap’s 1946 article ‘Modalities and quantification’. By contrast the modal logic defined by the semantics Carnap produces is unaxiomatisable. One can though adapt Carnap’s semantics so that a standard completeness proof for a Carnapian version of predicate S5 turns out to be available. //.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  40
    Leibniz’s Logic and the “Cube of Opposition”.Wolfgang Lenzen - 2016 - Logica Universalis 10 (2-3):171-189.
    After giving a short summary of the traditional theory of the syllogism, it is shown how the square of opposition reappears in the much more powerful concept logic of Leibniz. Within Leibniz’s algebra of concepts, the categorical forms are formalized straightforwardly by means of the relation of concept-containment plus the operator of concept-negation as ‘S contains P’ and ‘S contains Not-P’, ‘S doesn’t contain P’ and ‘S doesn’t contain Not-P’, respectively. Next we consider Leibniz’s version of the so-called Quantification (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32. The Problem of Cross-world Predication.Alexander W. Kocurek - 2016 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 45 (6):697-742.
    While standard first-order modal logic is quite powerful, it cannot express even very simple sentences like “I could have been taller than I actually am” or “Everyone could have been smarter than they actually are”. These are examples of cross-world predication, whereby objects in one world are related to objects in another world. Extending first-order modal logic to allow for cross-world predication in a motivated way has proven to be notoriously difficult. In this paper, I argue that the standard accounts (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  33.  24
    A. N. Prior. The parallel between modal logic and quantification theory. Worlds, times and selves, by A. N. Prior and Kit Fine, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, and Duckworth, London, 1977, pp. 9–27. - A. N. Prior. Egocentric logic. Worlds, times and selves, by A. N. Prior and Kit Fine, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, and Duckworth, London, 1977, pp. 28–45. , pp. 191–207.) - A. N. Prior. Supplement to ‘Egocentric logic’. Worlds, times and selves, by A. N. Prior and Kit Fine, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, and Duckworth, London, 1977, pp. 46–50. - A. N. Prior. Worlds, limes and selves. Worlds, times and selves, by A. N. Prior and Kit Fine, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, and Duckworth, London, 1977, pp. 51–66. , pp. 179–191.) - A. N. Prior. Tensed propositions as predicates. Worlds, times and selves, by A. N. Prior and Kit Fine, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, and Duckworth, London, 1977, pp. 67–83. , pp. 290–297.) - A. N. Prio. [REVIEW]R. A. Bull - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (4):654-656.
  34.  28
    The decision problem: solvable classes of quantificational formulas.Burton Dreben - 1979 - Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, Advanced Book Program. Edited by Warren D. Goldfarb.
  35. In defense of the simplest quantified modal logic.Bernard Linsky & Edward N. Zalta - 1994 - Philosophical Perspectives 8:431-458.
    The simplest quantified modal logic combines classical quantification theory with the propositional modal logic K. The models of simple QML relativize predication to possible worlds and treat the quantifier as ranging over a single fixed domain of objects. But this simple QML has features that are objectionable to actualists. By contrast, Kripke-models, with their varying domains and restricted quantifiers, seem to eliminate these features. But in fact, Kripke-models also have features to which actualists object. Though these philosophers have introduced (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   163 citations  
  36.  63
    Being Something: Properties and Predicative Quantification.Michael Rieppel - 2016 - Mind 125 (499):643-689.
    If I say that Alice is everything Oscar hopes to be, I seem to be quantifying over properties. That suggestion faces an immediate difficulty, however: though Alice may be wise, she surely is not the property of being wise. This problem can be framed in terms of a substitution failure: if a predicate like ‘happy’ denoted a property, we would expect pairs like ‘Oscar is happy’ and ‘Oscar is the property of being happy’ to be equivalent, which they clearly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37.  35
    The Alethic Platitudes, Deflationism, and Adverbial Quantification.Bradley Armour-Garb & James A. Woodbridge - 2023 - Philosophical Quarterly 73 (2):323-345.
    Alethic pluralists often claim that accommodating certain alethic platitudes motivates rejecting deflationism in favour of a pluralist inflationism about truth. Deflationists claim that the logical role of the truth predicate, viz providing something equivalent to variables for sentence-in-use positions and quantifiers governing them, is sufficient to account for the appeal to truth in the alethic platitudes. Surprisingly, however, most deflationists face an insufficiently acknowledged problem with respect to explaining how this mode of generalizing works. The standard substitutional or higher-order (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Chapter 3: The Semantics of Special Quantifiers in Predicate Position.Friederike Moltmann - 2013 - In Abstract Objects and the Semantics of Natural Language. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter argues that special quantifiers such as 'something' when occurring in argument position are not ordinary or substitutional quantifiers; rather they have a reifying force introducing a domain of tropes or kinds of tropes to quantify over.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  39.  75
    Plural Predication and the Strongest Meaning Hypothesis.Yoad Winter - 2001 - Journal of Semantics 18 (4):333-365.
    The Strongest Meaning Hypothesis of Dalrymple et al (1994,1998), which was originally proposed as a principle for the interpretation of reciprocals, is extended in this paper into a general principle of plural predication. This principle applies to complex predicates that are composed of lexical predicates that hold of atomic entities, and determines the pluralities in the extension of the predicate. The meaning of such a complex predicate is claimed to be the truth-conditionally strongest meaning that does not contradict (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  40. Polarity in Natural Language: Predication, Quantification and Negation in Particular and Characterizing Sentences.Sebastian Löbner - 2000 - Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (3):213-308.
    The present paper is an attempt at the investigation of the nature of polarity contrast in natural languages. Truth conditions for natural language sentences are incomplete unless they include a proper definition of the conditions under which they are false. It is argued that the tertium non datur principle of classical bivalent logical systems is empirically invalid for natural languages: falsity cannot be equated with non-truth. Lacking a direct intuition about the conditions under which a sentence is false, we need (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  41. On the Geachian Theory of the Trinity And Incarnation.James Cain - 2016 - Faith and Philosophy 33 (4):474-486.
    Contemporary accounts of the Trinity and Incarnation sometimes employ aspects of Peter Geach's theory of relative identity. Geach's theory provides an account not merely of identity predicates, but also proper names and restricted quantification. In a previous work I developed an account of the doctrines of the Trinity and Incarnation incorporating these three aspects of Geach's theory and tried to show how each might contribute to our understanding of the doctrines. Joseph Jedwab has recently argued that my account—or any (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  60
    The grammar of the essential indexical.T. Martin & W. Hinzen - unknown
    Like proper names, demonstratives, and definite descriptions, pronouns have referential uses. These can be 'essentially indexical' in the sense that they cannot be replaced by non-pronominal forms of reference. Here we show that the grammar of pronouns in such occurrences is systematically different from that of other referential expressions, in a way that illuminates the differences in reference in question. We specifically illustrate, in the domain of Romance clitics and pronouns, a hierarchy of referentiality, as related to the topology of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  43. Quantification and Epistemic Modality.Dilip Ninan - 2018 - Philosophical Review 127 (4):433-485.
    This essay introduces a puzzle about the interaction between quantifiers and epistemic modals. The puzzle motivates the idea that whether an object satisfies an epistemically modalized predicate depends on the mode of presentation of the domain of quantification. I compare two ways of implementing this idea, one using counterpart theory, the other using Aloni's 'conceptual covers' theory, and then provides some evidence in favor of the former.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  44. Predicate reference.Fraser MacBride - 2006 - In Barry C. Smith (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language. Oxford University Press. pp. 422--475.
    Whether a predicate is a referential expression depends upon what reference is conceived to be. Even if it is granted that reference is a relation between words and worldly items, the referents of expressions being the items to which they are so related, this still leaves considerable scope for disagreement about whether predicates refer. One of Frege's great contributions to the philosophy of language was to introduce an especially liberal conception of reference relative to which it is unproblematic to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  45.  72
    Domain restriction and the arguments of quantificational determiners.Anastasia Giannakidou - manuscript
    Classical generalized quantifier (GQ) theory posits that quantificational determiners (Q-dets) combine with a nominal argument of type et, a first order predicate, to form a GQ. In a recent paper, Matthewson (2001) challenges this position by arguing that the domain of a Q-det is not of type et, but e, an entity. In this paper, I defend the classical GQ view, and argue that the data that motivated Matthewson’s revision actually suggest that the domain set can, and indeed in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46. Semantics, meta-semantics, and ontology: A critique of the method of truth in metaphysics.Brian A. Ball, Dorothy Edgington & John Hawthorne - unknown
    In this thesis, Semantics, Meta-Semantics, and Ontology, I provide a critique of the method of truth in metaphysics. Davidson has suggested that we can determine the metaphysical nature and structure of reality through semantic investigations. By contrast, I argue that it is not semantics, but meta-semantics, which reveals the metaphysically necessary and sufficient truth conditions of our claims. As a consequence I reject the Quinean criterion of ontological commitment. In Part I, chapter 1, I argue that the metaphysically primary truth (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  39
    Towards quantification of the role of materials innovation in overall technological development.Christopher L. Magee - 2013 - Complexity 18 (1):10-25.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48. Truth and Proof without Models: A Development and Justification of the Truth-valuational Approach (2nd edition).Hanoch Ben-Yami - manuscript
    I explain why model theory is unsatisfactory as a semantic theory and has drawbacks as a tool for proofs on logic systems. I then motivate and develop an alternative, the truth-valuational substitutional approach (TVS), and prove with it the soundness and completeness of the first order Predicate Calculus with identity and of Modal Propositional Calculus. Modal logic is developed without recourse to possible worlds. Along the way I answer a variety of difficulties that have been raised against TVS and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Semantical remarks on the progressive reading of the imperfective.Andrea Bonomi - unknown
    Since there are independent reasons for associating the habitual reading of the imperfective, in Italian, to a logical form based on universal or generic quantification, the purpose of Part I is to see how this kind of semantical structure accounts for another important interpretation of the imperfective: the progressive reading. And since in some particular cases the imperfective can also have a marginal interpretation which can be assimilated to a perfective effect (it is the so-called “narrative” reading), a further (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  34
    Quantification Theory in *9 of Principia Mathematica.Gregory Landini - 2000 - History and Philosophy of Logic 21 (1):57-77.
    This paper examines the quantification theory of *9 of Principia Mathematica. The focus of the discussion is not the philosophical role that section *9 plays in Principia's full ramified type-theory. Rather, the paper assesses the system of *9 as a quantificational theory for the ordinary predicate calculus. The quantifier-free part of the system of *9 is examined and some misunderstandings of it are corrected. A flaw in the system of *9 is discovered, but it is shown that with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000