Results for ' inalienable rights'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Inalienable rights: A litmus test for liberal theories of justice.David Ellerman - 2010 - Law and Philosophy 29 (5):571-599.
    Liberal-contractarian philosophies of justice see the unjust systems of slavery and autocracy in the past as being based on coercion—whereas the social order in modern democratic market societies is based on consent and contract. However, the ‘best’ case for slavery and autocracy in the past were consent-based contractarian arguments. Hence, our first task is to recover those ‘forgotten’ apologia for slavery and autocracy. To counter those consent-based arguments, the historical anti-slavery and democratic movements developed a theory of inalienable (...). Our second task is to recover that theory and to consider several other applications of the theory. Finally, the liberal theories of justice expounded by John Rawls and by Robert Nozick are briefly examined from this perspective. (shrink)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  2.  58
    Inalienable Rights: The Limits of Consent in Medicine and the Law.Scott Kim - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (2):275-278.
    The aims of this book are to “explain the concept of an inalienable right,” “show why it is morally justifiable to ascribe inalienability to some legal rights,” and “examine in more detail some selected rights”. Inalienability of rights is said to be particularly pertinent in bioethics since, for example, if the right to life is inalienable, it would seem that euthanasia and assisted suicide would be impermissible. I will limit my comments to McConnell’s discussions of (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  3.  28
    The Inalienable Right to Withdraw from Research.Terrance McConnell - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (4):840-846.
    Most codes of research ethics and the practice of Institutional Review Boards (IRBs) allow human subjects to withdraw from research at any time. Consent forms invariably make a statement to this effect. So understood, a subject's right to withdraw from research is inalienable; she cannot, through her consent, surrender this right. Recently critics have argued that in selected circumstances the right to withdraw from research is alienable; subjects have the moral authority, through their consent, to obligate themselves not to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  4.  54
    Inalienable Rights: The Limits of Consent in Medicine and Law.Terrance C. McConnell - 2000 - Oup Usa.
    McConnell presents the unusual and distinctive argument that inalienable rights differ from other types of rights in that, rather than restraining the behaviour of others, inalienable rights seem to put limits on the possessors themselves, because even the possessor's consent does not justify others in encroaching on them. He offers a full account of what it means for a right to be inalienable, distinguishing them from other kinds of rights in the contexts of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  38
    Inalienable rights: Recent criticism and old doctrine.B. A. Richards - 1969 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 29 (3):391-404.
    Recent criticism of inalienable-Rights doctrine is shown to be based upon the erroneous assumption that, In calling certain rights inalienable, Eighteenth-Century constitution-Writers implied that they are unconditional. S.M. Brown, Jr., D.G. Ritchie, And e.F. Carritt all reject the doctrine because the exercise or enjoyment of these rights can sometimes be justifiably denied. Provisions of bills of rights and other writings are cited to establish that their authors did not consider these rights unlimited. What (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  26
    Against the inalienable right to withdraw from research.Eric Chwang - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (7):370-378.
    In this paper I argue, against the current consensus, that the right to withdraw from research is sometimes alienable. In other words, research subjects are sometimes morally permitted to waive their right to withdraw. The argument proceeds in three major steps. In the first step, I argue that rights typically should be presumed alienable, both because that is not illegitimately coercive and because the general paternalistic motivation for keeping them inalienable is untenable. In the second step of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7. Inalienable rights and Locke's treatises.A. John Simmons - 1983 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (3):175-204.
  8. Inalienable Rights.Terrance Mcconnell - 2001 - Law and Philosophy 20 (5):541-551.
    This book explains what inalienable rights are and how they restrict the behavior of their possessors. McConnell develops compelling arguments to support the inalienability of the right to life, the right of conscience, and a competent person's right not to have medical treatment administered without consent. Yet, surprisingly, he argues that the inalienability of the right to life does not entail that voluntary euthanasia or assisted suicide are wrong. This distinctive defense of inalienable rights will appeal (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  18
    The Inalienable Right to Withdraw from Research.Terrance McConnell - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (4):840-846.
    Consent forms given to potential subjects in research protocols typically contain a sentence like this: “You have a right to withdraw from this study at any time without penalty.” If you have ever served on an institutional review board or a research ethics committee, you have no doubt read such a sentence often. Moreover, codes of ethics governing medical research endorse such a right. For example, paragraph 24 of the Declaration of Helsinki says, “The subject should be informed of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10.  68
    Inalienable Rights: A Defense.Diana T. Meyers - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (2):304-306.
  11. Directed Duties and Inalienable Rights.Hillel Steiner - 2013 - Ethics 123 (2):230-244.
    This essay advances and defends two claims: (a) that rights cannot be inalienable and (b) that even if they could be, this would not be morally justifiable.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  12.  38
    Inalienable rights.Stuart M. Brown - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (2):192-211.
  13.  44
    The Inalienable Right of Conscience.Terrance McConnell - 1996 - Social Theory and Practice 22 (3):397-416.
  14.  27
    Inalienable Rights.Frank J. Leavitt - 1992 - Philosophy 67 (259):115 - 118.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Voluntary euthanasia and the inalienable right to life.Joel Feinberg - 1978 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 7 (2):93-123.
  16.  20
    Inalienable Rights: A Defense.D. R. Knowles - 1986 - Philosophical Books 27 (4):246-247.
  17.  43
    The inalienable right to life and the durable power of attorney.Carl Wellman - 1995 - Law and Philosophy 14 (2):245 - 269.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  46
    Privacy, Interests, and Inalienable Rights.Adam D. Moore - 2018 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 5 (2):327-355.
    Some rights are so important for human autonomy and well-being that many scholars insist they should not be waived, traded, or abandoned. Privacy is a recent addition to this list. At the other end of the spectrum is the belief that privacy is a mere unimportant interest or preference. This paper defends a middle path between viewing privacy as an inalienable, non-waivable, non-transferrable right and the view of privacy as a mere subjective interest. First, an account of privacy (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19. Contract Remedies and Inalienable Rights*: RANDY E. BARNETT.Randy E. Barnett - 1986 - Social Philosophy and Policy 4 (1):179-202.
    I. Introduction Two kinds of remedies have traditionally been employed for breach of contract: legal relief and equitable relief. Legal relief normally takes the form of money damages. Equitable relief normally consists either of specific performance or an injunction – that is, the party in breach may be ordered to perform an act or to refrain from performing an act. In this article I will use a “consent theory of contract” to assess the choice between money damages and specific performance. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  20.  42
    Are There Inalienable Rights?John O. Nelson - 1989 - Philosophy 64 (250):519-524.
    In the United Nations' Universal Declaration of Human Rights a quite large number of things are said to be ‘human rights’ and though in that Declaration the term ‘inalienable’ is not used to describe the rights in question it has been so used by commentators—at least with respect to some of the rights enumerated. I shall forgo asking the prior question as to whether any such thing as a human right exists and ask simply whether (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  12
    The Declaration of Independence: Inalienable Rights, the Creator, and the Political Order.Christopher Kaczor - 2023 - Nova et Vetera 21 (1):249-274.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Declaration of Independence:Inalienable Rights, the Creator, and the Political OrderChristopher KaczorPierre Manent puts his finger on numerous problems that arise from an emphasis on human rights that is detached from any consideration of human nature, the Creator, or the traditions that inform human practice. In his book Natural Law and Human Rights: Towards a Recovery of Practical Wisdom, Manent writes: "Let us dwell a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  52
    Are there any inalienable rights?Marvin Schiller - 1969 - Ethics 79 (4):309-315.
    The central purpose of the paper is to elucidate the inalienable rights thesis, I.E. That there is at least one inalienable right. Various senses of 'natural right' and 'inalienable' are analyzed so as to further clarify what is or could be the meaning and the truth of that thesis. A widespread confusion between the meaning of the terms 'inalienable natural right' and 'indefeasible natural right' is dispelled. It is concluded that present thinking about inalienable (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  51
    Are There Inalienable Rights?John O. Nelson - 1989 - Philosophy 64 (250):519 - 524.
    In the United Nations' Universal Declaration of Human Rights a quite large number of things are said to be ‘human rights’ and though in that Declaration the term ‘inalienable’ is not used to describe the rights in question it has been so used by commentators—at least with respect to some of the rights enumerated. I shall forgo asking the prior question as to whether any such thing as a human right exists and ask simply whether (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  28
    The utilitarian logic of inalienable rights.Arthur Kuflik - 1986 - Ethics 97 (1):75-87.
  25.  79
    Natural and inalienable rights.William K. Frankena - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (2):212-232.
  26.  5
    Inalienable Rights: A Defense. [REVIEW]Tom Regan - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (2):304-306.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Locke on Slavery and Inalienable Rights.Jennifer Welchman - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (1):67 - 81.
    Some have argued that Locke's failure to condemn contemporary slavery is best viewed as a personal moral lapse which does not reflect on his political theory. I argue to the contrary.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  28.  17
    Abortion and inalienable rights in classical liberalism.Gary D. Gd Glenn - 1975 - American Journal of Jurisprudence 20 (1):62.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29. Who deserves inalienable rights? : the subjectivity of violent state officials and the implications for human rights protection.Rachel Wahl - 2020 - In Danielle Celermajer & Alexandre Lefebvre (eds.), The subject of human rights. Stanford, California: Stanford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  31
    Terrance McConnell, inalienable rights.Alan Wertheimer - 2001 - Law and Philosophy 20 (5):541-551.
  31.  26
    The Rationale for Inalienable Rights in Moral Systems.Diana T. Meyers - 1981 - Social Theory and Practice 7 (2):127-143.
  32.  52
    Infinite Regress and Hohfeld: A Comment on Hillel Steiner’s “Directed Duties and Inalienable Rights”.Pierfrancesco Biasetti - 2015 - Ethics 126 (1):139-152.
    In his article “Directed Duties and Inalienable Rights,” Hillel Steiner advances an argument to show that there cannot be inalienable rights. This “impossibility theorem,” as well as providing an interesting result by itself, could break the theoretical deadlock in the debate between proponents of interest theory, on the one hand, and proponents of will theory, on the other. In this article, I comment on Steiner’s argument, and I try to show why it does not work. I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. The nature and basis of inalienable rights.Terrance McConnell - 1984 - Law and Philosophy 3 (1):25 - 59.
    This paper has two purposes. One is primarily (but not exclusively) conceptual and the other is normative. The first aim is to say what inalienable rights are. To explain this, inalienable rights are contrasted with the notions of forfeitable rights and absolute rights. A recent novel analysis of inalienable rights by Feinberg is explained and criticized. The first task is concluded by discussing what duties inalienable rights imply. The second aim (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  34. Some Difficulties Concerning the Notion of Inalienable Rights.Ralph Nelson - 1985 - Maritain Studies/Etudes Maritainiennes 1:27-58.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. [Book review] mortal peril, our inalienable right to health care? [REVIEW]Epstein Richard Allen - 1999 - Hastings Center Report 29 (1).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  7
    “Three Rights Traditions Walk into a Bar in Jakarta”: Inalienable Human Rights from the Perspective of Different Civilizations.Timothy Samuel Shah & C. Holland Taylor - 2023 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 2023 (203):78-98.
    ExcerptMany people assume that the Universal Declaration of Human Rights of 1948 was an exclusively or primarily Western project, imposed on the rest of the world by the European and American powers that emerged victorious from World War II. Harvard Law professor Mary Ann Glendon’s 2001 book, A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, suggests otherwise. It was not the great powers but small powers that pushed hardest for a declaration of (...). And it was often great powers—and one must acknowledge, great powers dominated by people of European ancestry—that did not like the idea of being pushed around by politically and economically weaker inhabitants of the Global South, who were just beginning to emerge from centuries of Western colonialism and other forms of oppression.1. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Critique of the doctrine of inalienable, natural rights.Jeremy Bentham - unknown
    The Declaration of Rights -- I mean the paper published under that name by the French National Assembly in 1791 -- assumes for its subject-matter a field of disquisition as unbounded in point of extent as it is important in its nature. But the more ample the extent given to any proposition or string of propositions, the more difficult it is to keep the import of it confined without deviation, within the bounds of truth and reason. If in the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  17
    Universales, absolutos e inalienables: los derechos indestructibles.Íñigo Álvarez Gálvez - 2015 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 4:63-80.
    There is a particular moral theory in which human rights are conceived as indestructible rights. Using Dworkin’s words we could say this is a good way of taking rights seriously. However, we may also ask whether there is another way of taking rights as seriously as Dworkin says without being a supporter of that theory. From this point of view, perhaps human rights cannot be considered neither as absolute ; nor universally valid ; and not (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  7
    The right to have rights.Alastair Hunt - 2018 - Brooklyn, NY: Verso.
    Five leading thinkers on the concept of 'rights' in an era of rightlessness Sixty years ago, the political theorist Hannah Arendt, deprived of her German citizenship as a Jew and in exile from her country, observed that before people can enjoy any of the 'inalienable' Rights of Man--before there can be any specific rights to education, work, voting, and so on--there must first be such a thing as 'the right to have rights.' The concept received (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  13
    Evolution, Animal 'rights' & the Environment.James B. Reichmann - 2000 - Catholic University of Amer Press.
    Among the more significant developments of the twentieth century, the widespread attention given to 'rights issues' must surely justify ranking it somewhere near the top. Never before has the issue of rights attracted such a wide audience or stirred so much controversy. Until very recently 'rights' were traditionally recognized as attributable only to humans. Today, we increasingly are hearing a call to extend 'rights' to the nonhuman animal and, on occasion, to the environment. In this book, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  41.  6
    Human Rights Practice and Natural Law.Aaron Rhodes - 2023 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 2023 (203):47-58.
    ExcerptThe University of Notre Dame Kellogg Institute’s 2021 conference on “Inalienable Rights and the Traditions of Constitutionalism” was, for me, a breath of oxygen because it brought together many who understand that human rights are more than simply reflections of particular political preferences of some societies at particular times, and that to understand human rights that way reduces them to the level of arbitrary positive law. Human rights are based in human nature, and in nature (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Natural Rights to Welfare.Siegfried Van Duffel - 2011 - European Journal of Philosophy 21 (4):641-664.
    : Many people have lamented the proliferation of human rights claims. The cure for this problem, it may be thought, would be to develop a theory that can distinguish ‘real’ from ‘supposed’ human rights. I argue, however, that the proliferation of human rights mirrors a deep problem in human rights theory itself. Contemporary theories of natural rights to welfare are historical descendants from a theory of rights to subsistence which was developed in twelfth-century Europe. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  37
    Hobbesian Sovereignty and the Rights of Subjects.Eleanor Curran - 2019 - Hobbes Studies 32 (2):209-230.
    Hobbes, in his political writing, is generally understood to be arguing for absolutism. I argue that despite apparently supporting absolutism, Hobbes, in Leviathan, also undermines that absolutism in at least two and possibly three ways. First, he makes sovereignty conditional upon the sovereign’s ability to ensure the safety of the people. Second and crucially, he argues that subjects have inalienable rights, rights that are held even against the sovereign. When the subjects’ preservation is threatened they are no (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  81
    The Right to Life, Voluntary Euthanasia, and Termination of Life on Request.Elias Moser - 2017 - Philosophy Study 7 (8):445-454.
    In this article, the logical implications of a right to life are examined. It is first argued that the prohibition of Termination of life on request confers an inalienable right to life. A right is inalienable if it cannot legitimately be waived or transferred. Since voluntary euthanasia entails waiver of the right to life, the inalienability yields that it cannot be justified. Therefore, any ethical position that is in favor of voluntary euthanasia has to argue that the right (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  14
    Rethinking Rights, Preserving Community: How My Mind Has Changed.Arthur J. Dyck - 1997 - Journal of Religious Ethics 25 (1):3 - 14.
    Just below the surface of public life in the United States, a biblically based theory of rights vies with a theory that first appeared in the work of Bentham and Mill, and the latter is gaining increasing dominance. The resolution of this conflict has implications for a host of legal matters and public policy decisions, including life and death issues like physician-assisted suicide. Though the ascendancy of the Millian tradition reflects widespread skepticism concerning the possibility of developing a basis (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. The right to trial by jury.Thom Brooks - 2004 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 21 (2):197–212.
    This article offers a justification for the continued use of jury trials. I shall critically examine the ability of juries to render just verdicts, judicial impartiality, and judicial transparency. My contention is that the judicial system that best satisfies these values is most preferable. Of course, these three values are not the only factors relevant for consideration. Empirical evidence demonstrates that juries foster both democratic participation and public legitimation of legal decisions regarding the most serious cases. Nevertheless, juries are costly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47.  24
    Natural Rights in the Thirteenth Century: A Quaestio of Henry of Ghent.Brian Tierney - 1992 - Speculum 67 (1):58-68.
    According to one recent account, in the “preliberal epoch” before the seventeenth century people did not think of individuals “as possessing inalienable rights to anything — much less life, liberty, property, or even the pursuit of happiness.” The statement is not true, but it is excusable. Compared with the flood of writing on the classical rights theories of the early modern period, there has been only a thin trickle of work on medieval ideas concerning individual natural (...), or human rights as we say nowadays, rights inhering in the human person as such. Some modern authors see the seventeenth-century rights theories as a radical departure from ancient and medieval ways of thought; they are content to explain the ideas of Hobbes and Locke and Pufendorf by reference to some aspect of the intellectual, political, or economic life of the seventeenth century itself. C. B. MacPherson, for instance, emphasizing economic factors, inaugurated a minor academic industry when he interpreted Locke's teaching that everyone had a property right in his own person as a reflection of the possessive individualism of early-modern capitalism. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  53
    Rights, Human and Otherwise.Henry David Aiken - 1968 - The Monist 52 (4):502-520.
    1. In this essay I want to try out some ideas: about the notion of a right—how it works and the terms of its meaningful application; about a distinction between institutional and noninstitutional rights; in regard to noninstitutional rights, about specific, nonspecific, general, and so-called universal rights; in relation to ‘universal’ institutional rights, about the notions of ‘natural’ and ‘human’ rights; about certain classes of noninstitutional rights which are variously regarded as basic, fundamental, (...), etc.; and about certain problems concerning what is sometimes referred to as the metaphysics of rights: problems about their reality or existence, their eternality or historicity. Throughout I shall feel quite free to move back and forth between so-called analytical questions about rights and questions of a more substantive nature. I shall be aiming both at a clarification of my thinking about rights and at a determination of those noninstitutional rights which, in my book, are to be taken most seriously. This essay is thus written, in the first instance, for my own edification. To others I offer it as an invitation to colloquy and to further reflection. But such colloquies and reflections will not serve their purpose unless they are funded back into the practical deliberations and decisions of ordinary life. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49. Transitional Justice and the Right of Return of the Palestinian Refugees.Nadim N. Rouhana & Yoav Peled - 2004 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 5 (2):317-332.
    All efforts undertaken so far to establish peace between Israel and the Palestinians have failed to seriously address the right of return of the Palestinian refugees. This failure stemmed from a conviction that the question of historical justice in general had to be avoided. Since justice is a subjective construct, it was argued, allowing it to become a subject of negotiation would only perpetuate the conflict. However, the experience of these peace efforts has shown that without solving the problem of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  49
    Freedom and Human Rights.Mary-Rose Barral - 2007 - The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 3:125-130.
    Human beings are endowed by the Source of their existence on earth with those inalienable rights which all members of humanity ought to respect. Freedom, in all its basic forms, is the root of these rights, but sadly, it is not the patrimony of all the people of the world. Political, societal, even domestic situations often deprive persons of this personal endowment. Basically, a philosophy of life, construed on a set of false premises, rejects some persons and/or (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000