Results for 'Mathematical Rigor'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  71
    Mathematical rigor and proof.Yacin Hamami - 2022 - Review of Symbolic Logic 15 (2):409-449.
    Mathematical proof is the primary form of justification for mathematical knowledge, but in order to count as a proper justification for a piece of mathematical knowl- edge, a mathematical proof must be rigorous. What does it mean then for a mathematical proof to be rigorous? According to what I shall call the standard view, a mathematical proof is rigorous if and only if it can be routinely translated into a formal proof. The standard view (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  2.  69
    Mathematical rigor, proof gap and the validity of mathematical inference.Yacin Hamami - 2014 - Philosophia Scientiae 18 (1):7-26.
    Mathematical rigor is commonly formulated by mathematicians and philosophers using the notion of proof gap: a mathematical proof is rig­orous when there is no gaps in the mathematical reasoning of the proof. Any philosophical approach to mathematical rigor along this line requires then an account of what a proof gap is. However, the notion of proof gap makes sense only relatively to a given conception of valid mathematical reasoning, i.e., to a given conception (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. What is Mathematical Rigor?John Burgess & Silvia De Toffoli - 2022 - Aphex 25:1-17.
    Rigorous proof is supposed to guarantee that the premises invoked imply the conclusion reached, and the problem of rigor may be described as that of bringing together the perspectives of formal logic and mathematical practice on how this is to be achieved. This problem has recently raised a lot of discussion among philosophers of mathematics. We survey some possible solutions and argue that failure to understand its terms properly has led to misunderstandings in the literature.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. Mathematical rigor in physics.Mark Steiner - 1992 - In Michael Detlefsen (ed.), Proof and Knowledge in Mathematics. New York: Routledge. pp. 158.
  5.  19
    Is mathematical rigor necessary in physics?Kevin Davey - 2003 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (3):439-463.
    Many arguments found in the physics literature involve concepts that are not well-defined by the usual standards of mathematics. I argue that physicists are entitled to employ such concepts without rigorously defining them so long as they restrict the sorts of mathematical arguments in which these concepts are involved. Restrictions of this sort allow the physicist to ignore calculations involving these concepts that might lead to contradictory results. I argue that such restrictions need not be ad hoc, but can (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  6.  11
    Mathematical rigor--who needs it?Philip Kitcher - 1981 - Noûs 15 (4):469-493.
  7.  11
    Mathematical Rigor in Physics: Putting Exact Results in Their Place.Axel Gelfert - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):723-738.
    The present paper examines the role of exact results in the theory of many‐body physics, and specifically the example of the Mermin‐Wagner theorem, a rigorous result concerning the absence of phase transitions in low‐dimensional systems. While the theorem has been shown to hold for a wide range of many‐body models, it is frequently ‘violated’ by results derived from the same models using numerical techniques. This raises the question of how scientists regulate their theoretical commitments in such cases, given that the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  10
    Mathematical Rigor and the Origin of the Exhaustion Method.Theokritos Kouremenos - 1997 - Centaurus 39 (3):230-252.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Edmund Husserl: from the mathematical rigor to the philosophical questioning.Vanessa Donado - 2014 - Eidos: Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad Del Norte 21:127-146.
    Nobody can deny that the figure of Edmund Husserl represents the key to the philosophical horizon of our time in both version, as continental as analytical one. But, how can the same approach give ground and support to the development of such diverse topics? Although much work has been done to explain the renewed sense that science and philosophy acquire inside their proposal, the way Husserl reached that conclusion is not sufficiently clear yet. That is why in this article we (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  11
    Some Aspects of the problem of Mathematical Rigor.Haskell B. Curry - 1941 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 6 (3):100-102.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  9
    Rigorous proof and the history of mathematics: Comments on Crowe.Douglas Jesseph - 1990 - Synthese 83 (3):449 - 453.
    Duhem's portrayal of the history of mathematics as manifesting calm and regular development is traced to his conception of mathematical rigor as an essentially static concept. This account is undermined by citing controversies over rigorous demonstration from the eighteenth and twentieth centuries.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  21
    Curry Haskell B.. Some aspects of the problem of mathematical rigor. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 47 , pp. 221–241. [REVIEW]S. C. Kleene - 1941 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 6 (3):100-102.
  13.  28
    Rigor and Clarity: Foundations of Mathematics in France and England, 1800–1840.Joan L. Richards - 1991 - Science in Context 4 (2):297-319.
    The ArgumentIt has long been apparent that in the nineteenth century, mathematics in France and England developed along different lines. The differences, which might well be labelled stylistic, are most easy to see on the foundational level. At first this may seem surprising because it is such a fundamental area, but, upon reflection, it is to be expected. Ultimately discussions about the foundations of mathematics turn on views about what mathematics is, and this is a question which is answered by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  39
    Rigor and Structure.John P. Burgess - 2015 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK.
    While we are commonly told that the distinctive method of mathematics is rigorous proof, and that the special topic of mathematics is abstract structure, there has been no agreement among mathematicians, logicians, or philosophers as to just what either of these assertions means. John P. Burgess clarifies the nature of mathematical rigor and of mathematical structure, and above all of the relation between the two, taking into account some of the latest developments in mathematics, including the rise (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  15.  29
    Arithmetization and Rigor as Beliefs in the Development of Mathematics.Lorena Segura & Juan Matías Sepulcre - 2016 - Foundations of Science 21 (1):207-214.
    With the arrival of the nineteenth century, a process of change guided the treatment of three basic elements in the development of mathematics: rigour, the arithmetization and the clarification of the concept of function, categorised as the most important tool in the development of the mathematical analysis. In this paper we will show how several prominent mathematicians contributed greatly to the development of these basic elements that allowed the solid underpinning of mathematics and the consideration of mathematics as an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Proofs for a price: Tomorrow’s ultra-rigorous mathematical culture.Silvia De Toffoli - 2024 - Bulletin (New Series) of the American Mathematical Society 61 (3):395–410.
    Computational tools might tempt us to renounce complete cer- tainty. By forgoing of rigorous proof, we could get (very) probable results for a fraction of the cost. But is it really true that proofs (as we know and love them) can lead us to certainty? Maybe not. Proofs do not wear their correct- ness on their sleeve, and we are not infallible in checking them. This suggests that we need help to check our results. When our fellow mathematicians will be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Rigorous results, cross-model justification, and the transfer of empirical warrant: the case of many-body models in physics.Axel Gelfert - 2009 - Synthese 169 (3):497-519.
    This paper argues that a successful philosophical analysis of models and simulations must accommodate an account of mathematically rigorous results. Such rigorous results may be thought of as genuinely model-specific contributions, which can neither be deduced from fundamental theory nor inferred from empirical data. Rigorous results provide new indirect ways of assessing the success of models and simulations and are crucial to understanding the connections between different models. This is most obvious in cases where rigorous results map different models on (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  18.  33
    Mathematical Sciences J. V. Grabiner, The origins of Cauchy's rigorous calculus. Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. press, 1981. Pp. x + 252. £17.50. [REVIEW]Jeremy Gray - 1983 - British Journal for the History of Science 16 (3):290-291.
  19. Reconciling Rigor and Intuition.Silvia De Toffoli - 2020 - Erkenntnis 86 (6):1783-1802.
    Criteria of acceptability for mathematical proofs are field-dependent. In topology, though not in most other domains, it is sometimes acceptable to appeal to visual intuition to support inferential steps. In previous work :829–842, 2014; Lolli, Panza, Venturi From logic to practice, Springer, Berlin, 2015; Larvor Mathematical cultures, Springer, Berlin, 2016) my co-author and I aimed at spelling out how topological proofs work on their own terms, without appealing to formal proofs which might be associated with them. In this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  20.  36
    The Pursuit of Rigor: Hilbert's axiomatic method and the objectivity of mathematics.Yoshinori Ogawa - 2004 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 12 (2):89-108.
  21.  3
    The dilemma of statistics: Rigorous mathematical methods cannot compensate messy interpretations and lousy data.Peter Schuster - 2014 - Complexity 20 (1):11-15.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  24
    The Relationship of Derivations in Artificial Languages to Ordinary Rigorous Mathematical Proof.J. Azzouni - 2013 - Philosophia Mathematica 21 (2):247-254.
    The relationship is explored between formal derivations, which occur in artificial languages, and mathematical proof, which occurs in natural languages. The suggestion that ordinary mathematical proofs are abbreviations or sketches of formal derivations is presumed false. The alternative suggestion that the existence of appropriate derivations in formal logical languages is a norm for ordinary rigorous mathematical proof is explored and rejected.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  23.  4
    The Algorithmic-Device View of Informal Rigorous Mathematical Proof.Jody Azzouni - 2024 - In Bharath Sriraman (ed.), Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Cham: Springer. pp. 2179-2260.
    A new approach to informal rigorous mathematical proof is offered. To this end, algorithmic devices are characterized and their central role in mathematical proof delineated. It is then shown how all the puzzling aspects of mathematical proof, including its peculiar capacity to convince its practitioners, are explained by algorithmic devices. Diagrammatic reasoning is also characterized in terms of algorithmic devices, and the algorithmic device view of mathematical proof is compared to alternative construals of informal proof to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  10
    Rigor and formalization.Pawel Pawlowski & Karim Zahidi - 2024 - Synthese 203 (3):1-18.
    This paper critically examines and evaluates Yacin Hamami’s reconstruction of the standard view of mathematical rigor. We will argue that the reconstruction offered by Hamami is premised on a strong and controversial epistemological thesis and a strong and controversial thesis in the philosophy of mind. Secondly, we will argue that Hamami’s reconstruction of the standard view robs it of its original philosophical rationale, i.e. making sense of the notion of rigor in mathematical practice.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  11
    Mathematics and plausible reasoning.George Pólya - 1968 - Princeton, N.J.,: Princeton University Press.
    2014 Reprint of 1954 American Edition. Full facsimile of the original edition, not reproduced with Optical Recognition Software. This two volume classic comprises two titles: "Patterns of Plausible Inference" and "Induction and Analogy in Mathematics." This is a guide to the practical art of plausible reasoning, particularly in mathematics, but also in every field of human activity. Using mathematics as the example par excellence, Polya shows how even the most rigorous deductive discipline is heavily dependent on techniques of guessing, inductive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  26.  39
    Paradoxes and Inconsistent Mathematics.Zach Weber - 2021 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    Logical paradoxes – like the Liar, Russell's, and the Sorites – are notorious. But in Paradoxes and Inconsistent Mathematics, it is argued that they are only the noisiest of many. Contradictions arise in the everyday, from the smallest points to the widest boundaries. In this book, Zach Weber uses “dialetheic paraconsistency” – a formal framework where some contradictions can be true without absurdity – as the basis for developing this idea rigorously, from mathematical foundations up. In doing so, Weber (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  27.  15
    Role of Imagination and Anticipation in the Acceptance of Computability Proofs: A Challenge to the Standard Account of Rigor.Keith Weber - 2022 - Philosophia Mathematica 30 (3):343-368.
    In a 2022 paper, Hamami claimed that the orthodox view in mathematics is that a proof is rigorous if it can be translated into a derivation. Hamami then developed a descriptive account that explains how mathematicians check proofs for rigor in this sense and how they develop the capacity to do so. By exploring introductory texts in computability theory, we demonstrate that Hamami’s descriptive account does not accord with actual mathematical practice with respect to computability theory. We argue (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. The'theorie Des fonctions analytiques'of lagrange and the problem of being rigorous in demonstrations of mathematical-analysis.A. Moretto - 1991 - Verifiche: Rivista Trimestrale di Scienze Umane 20 (1-2):83-122.
  29.  8
    Poincaré: Mathematics & logic & intuition.Colin Mclarty - 1997 - Philosophia Mathematica 5 (2):97-115.
    often insisted existence in mathematics means logical consistency, and formal logic is the sole guarantor of rigor. The paper joins this to his view of intuition and his own mathematics. It looks at predicativity and the infinite, Poincaré's early endorsement of the axiom of choice, and Cantor's set theory versus Zermelo's axioms. Poincaré discussed constructivism sympathetically only once, a few months before his death, and conspicuously avoided committing himself. We end with Poincaré on Couturat, Russell, and Hilbert.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30.  33
    Defining ecology: Ecological theories, mathematical models, and applied biology in the 1960s and 1970s.Paolo Palladino - 1991 - Journal of the History of Biology 24 (2):223 - 243.
    Ever since the early decades of this century, there have emerged a number of competing schools of ecology that have attempted to weave the concepts underlying natural resource management and natural-historical traditions into a formal theoretical framework. It was widely believed that the discovery of the fundamental mechanisms underlying ecological phenomena would allow ecologists to articulate mathematically rigorous statements whose validity was not predicated on contingent factors. The formulation of such statements would elevate ecology to the standing of a rigorous (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  31.  10
    Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning: Induction and analogy in mathematics.George Pólya - 1954 - Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press.
    Here the author of How to Solve It explains how to become a "good guesser." Marked by G. Polya's simple, energetic prose and use of clever examples from a wide range of human activities, this two-volume work explores techniques of guessing, inductive reasoning, and reasoning by analogy, and the role they play in the most rigorous of deductive disciplines.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  32.  73
    Open texture, rigor, and proof.Benjamin Zayton - 2022 - Synthese 200 (4):1-20.
    Open texture is a kind of semantic indeterminacy first systematically studied by Waismann. In this paper, extant definitions of open texture will be compared and contrasted, with a view towards the consequences of open-textured concepts in mathematics. It has been suggested that these would threaten the traditional virtues of proof, primarily the certainty bestowed by proof-possession, and this suggestion will be critically investigated using recent work on informal proof. It will be argued that informal proofs have virtues that mitigate the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  18
    O rigor científico: princípios elementares extraídos de Aristóteles no interesse da teologia.Clodovis Boff - 2015 - Horizonte 13 (39):1559-1579.
    Against the modern tendency to considerate just the formal-empirical knowledge as Science, and this one mathematized as much as possible, here many declarations of Aristotle are raised in order to show that the scientific rigour is not univocal but analogic: it is determined according to the nature of the object to be known. This is a so elementary epistemological rule that not knowing it is understood by that philosopher as apaideusia, i.e., lack of basic education in the knowledge sphere in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  4
    Mathematical logic with special reference to the natural numbers.S. W. P. Steen - 1972 - Cambridge [Eng.]: University Press.
    This book presents a comprehensive treatment of basic mathematical logic. The author's aim is to make exact the vague, intuitive notions of natural number, preciseness, and correctness, and to invent a method whereby these notions can be communicated to others and stored in the memory. He adopts a symbolic language in which ideas about natural numbers can be stated precisely and meaningfully, and then investigates the properties and limitations of this language. The treatment of mathematical concepts in the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  8
    Rigorous Purposes of Analysis in Greek Geometry.Viktor Blåsjö - 2021 - Philosophia Scientiae 25:55-80.
    Analyses in Greek geometry are traditionally seen as heuristic devices. However, many occurrences of analysis in formal treatises are difficult to justify in such terms. I show that Greek analysies of geometrics can also serve formal mathematical purposes, which are arguably incomplete without which their associated syntheses are arguably incomplete. Firstly, when the solution of a problem is preceded by an analysis, the analysis latter proves rigorously that there are no other solutions to the problem than those offered in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  12
    Logic and discrete mathematics: a concise introduction.Willem Conradie - 2015 - Hoboken, NJ, USA: Wiley. Edited by Valentin Goranko.
    A concise yet rigorous introduction to logic and discrete mathematics. This book features a unique combination of comprehensive coverage of logic with a solid exposition of the most important fields of discrete mathematics, presenting material that has been tested and refined by the authors in university courses taught over more than a decade. The chapters on logic - propositional and first-order - provide a robust toolkit for logical reasoning, emphasizing the conceptual understanding of the language and the semantics of classical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  8
    Rigorous information-theoretic derivation of quantum-statistical thermodynamics. II.William Band & James L. Park - 1977 - Foundations of Physics 7 (9-10):705-721.
    Part I of the present work outlined the rigorous application of information theory to a quantum mechanical system in a thermodynamic equilibrium state. The general formula developed there for the best-guess density operator $\hat \rho$ was indeterminate because it involved in an essential way an unspecified prior probability distribution over the continuumD H of strong equilibrium density operators. In Part II mathematical evaluation of $\hat \rho$ is completed after an epistemological analysis which leads first to the discretization ofD H (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  10
    Does mathematical study develop logical thinking?: testing the theory of formal discipline.Matthew Inglis - 2017 - New Jersey: World Scientific. Edited by Nina Attridge.
    "This book is interesting and well-written. The research methods were explained clearly and conclusions were summarized nicely. It is a relatively quick read at only 130 pages. Anyone who has been told, or who has told others, that mathematicians make better thinkers should read this book." MAA Reviews "The authors particularly attend to protecting positive correlations against the self-selection interpretation, merely that logical minds elect studying more mathematics. Here, one finds a stimulating survey of the systemic difficulties people have with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Objectivity and Rigor in Classical Italian Algebraic Geometry.Silvia De Toffoli & Claudio Fontanari - 2022 - Noesis 38:195-212.
    The classification of algebraic surfaces by the Italian School of algebraic geometry is universally recognized as a breakthrough in 20th-century mathematics. The methods by which it was achieved do not, however, meet the modern standard of rigor and therefore appear dubious from a contemporary viewpoint. In this article, we offer a glimpse into the mathematical practice of the three leading exponents of the Italian School of algebraic geometry: Castelnuovo, Enriques, and Severi. We then bring into focus their distinctive (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  4
    Toward a rigorous quantum field theory.Stanley Gudder - 1994 - Foundations of Physics 24 (9):1205-1225.
    This paper outlines a framework that may provide a mathematically rigorous quantum field theory. The framework relies upon the methods of nonstandard analysis. A theory of nonstandard inner product spaces and operators on these spaces is first developed. This theory is then applied to construct nonstandard Fock spaces which extend the standard Fock spaces. Then a rigorous framework for the field operators of quantum field theory is presented. The results are illustrated for the case of Klein-Gordon fields.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  7
    Mathematical logic.Ian Chiswell - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Wilfrid Hodges.
    Assuming no previous study in logic, this informal yet rigorous text covers the material of a standard undergraduate first course in mathematical logic, using natural deduction and leading up to the completeness theorem for first-order logic. At each stage of the text, the reader is given an intuition based on standard mathematical practice, which is subsequently developed with clean formal mathematics. Alongside the practical examples, readers learn what can and can't be calculated; for example the correctness of a (...)
  42.  22
    A Burgessian Critique of Nominalistic Tendencies in Contemporary Mathematics and its Historiography.Karin Usadi Katz & Mikhail G. Katz - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (1):51-89.
    We analyze the developments in mathematical rigor from the viewpoint of a Burgessian critique of nominalistic reconstructions. We apply such a critique to the reconstruction of infinitesimal analysis accomplished through the efforts of Cantor, Dedekind, and Weierstrass; to the reconstruction of Cauchy’s foundational work associated with the work of Boyer and Grabiner; and to Bishop’s constructivist reconstruction of classical analysis. We examine the effects of a nominalist disposition on historiography, teaching, and research.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  43.  8
    Iconic Mathematics: Math Designed to Suit the Mind.Peter Kramer - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Mathematics is a struggle for many. To make it more accessible, behavioral and educational scientists are redesigning how it is taught. To a similar end, a few rogue mathematicians and computer scientists are doing something more radical: they are redesigning mathematics itself, improving its ergonomic features. Charles Peirce, an important contributor to ordinary symbolic logic, also introduced a rigorous but non-symbolic, graphical alternative to it that is easier to picture. In the spirit of this iconic logic, George Spencer-Brown founded iconic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  26
    Abel and his mathematics in contexts.Henrik Kragh Sørensen - 2002 - NTM Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Wissenschaften, Technik und Medizin 10 (1-3):137-155.
    200 years ago, on August 5, 1802, Niels Henrik Abel was born on Finnøy near Stavanger on the Norwegian west coast. During a short life span, Abel contributed to a deep transition in mathematics in which concepts replaced formulae as the basic objects of mathematics. The transformation of mathematics in the 1820s and its manifestation in Abel’s works are the themes of the author’s PhD thesis. After sketching the formative instances in Abel’s well-known biography, this article illustrates two aspects of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  2
    Mathematics of relativity.George Yuri Rainich - 1950 - New York,: Wiley.
    Based on the ideas of Einstein and Minkowski, this concise treatment is derived from the author's many years of teaching the mathematics of relativity at the University of Michigan. Geared toward advanced undergraduates and graduate students of physics, the text covers old physics, new geometry, special relativity, curved space, and general relativity. Beginning with a discussion of the inverse square law in terms of simple calculus, the treatment gradually introduces increasingly complicated situations and more sophisticated mathematical tools. Changes in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  16
    Axioms of Infinity as the Starting Point for Rigorous Mathematics.John P. Burgess - 2012 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 20:17-28.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  10
    The Search for Certainty: A Philosophical Account of Foundations of Mathematics.Marcus Giaquinto - 2002 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK.
    Marcus Giaquinto traces the story of the search for firm foundations for mathematics. The nineteenth century saw a movement to make higher mathematics rigorous; this seemed to be on the brink of success when it was thrown into confusion by the discovery of the class paradoxes. That initiated a period of intense research into the foundations of mathematics, and with it the birth of mathematical logic and a new, sharper debate in the philosophy of mathematics. The Search for Certainty (...)
  48. All science as rigorous science: the principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory.Vasil Penchev - 2020 - Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics eJournal 12 (12):1-15.
    A principle, according to which any scientific theory can be mathematized, is investigated. Social science, liberal arts, history, and philosophy are meant first of all. That kind of theory is presupposed to be a consistent text, which can be exhaustedly represented by a certain mathematical structure constructively. In thus used, the term “theory” includes all hypotheses as yet unconfirmed as already rejected. The investigation of the sketch of a possible proof of the principle demonstrates that it should be accepted (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  13
    Fundamentals of mathematical proof.Charles A. Matthews - 2018 - [place of publication not identified]: [Publisher Not Identified].
    This mathematics textbook covers the fundamental ideas used in writing proofs. Proof techniques covered include direct proofs, proofs by contrapositive, proofs by contradiction, proofs in set theory, proofs of existentially or universally quantified predicates, proofs by cases, and mathematical induction. Inductive and deductive reasoning are explored. A straightforward approach is taken throughout. Plenty of examples are included and lots of exercises are provided after each brief exposition on the topics at hand. The text begins with a study of symbolic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  29
    On the Mathematical Method and Correspondence with Exner: Translated by Paul Rusnock and Rolf George.Bernard Bolzano (ed.) - 2004 - BRILL.
    The Prague Philosopher Bernard Bolzano (1781-1848) has long been admired for his groundbreaking work in mathematics: his rigorous proofs of fundamental theorems in analysis, his construction of a continuous, nowhere-differentiable function, his investigations of the infinite, and his anticipations of Cantor's set theory. He made equally outstanding contributions in philosophy, most notably in logic and methodology. One of the greatest mathematician-philosophers since Leibniz, Bolzano is now widely recognised as a major figure of nineteenth-century philosophy. Praised by Husserl as “one of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000