Results for 'Good's Theorem'

992 found
Order:
  1. Godel's theorem is a red Herring.I. J. Good - 1968 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 19 (February):357-8.
  2.  48
    A modal sequent calculus for a fragment of arithmetic.G. Sambin & S. Valentini - 1980 - Studia Logica 39 (2-3):245-256.
    Global properties of canonical derivability predicates in Peano Arithmetic) are studied here by means of a suitable propositional modal logic GL. A whole book [1] has appeared on GL and we refer to it for more information and a bibliography on GL. Here we propose a sequent calculus for GL and, by exhibiting a good proof procedure, prove that such calculus admits the elimination of cuts. Most of standard results on GL are then easy consequences: completeness, decidability, finite model property, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  3. The curve fitting problem: A bayesian rejoinder.Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay & Robert J. Boik - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (3):402.
    In the curve fitting problem two conflicting desiderata, simplicity and goodness-of-fit pull in opposite directions. To solve this problem, two proposals, the first one based on Bayes's theorem criterion (BTC) and the second one advocated by Forster and Sober based on Akaike's Information Criterion (AIC) are discussed. We show that AIC, which is frequentist in spirit, is logically equivalent to BTC, provided that a suitable choice of priors is made. We evaluate the charges against Bayesianism and contend that AIC (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  4. The curve fitting problem: A bayesian approach.Prasanta S. Bandyopadhayay, Robert J. Boik & Prasun Basu - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (3):272.
    In the curve fitting problem two conflicting desiderata, simplicity and goodness-of-fit, pull in opposite directions. To this problem, we propose a solution that strikes a balance between simplicity and goodness-of-fit. Using Bayes' theorem we argue that the notion of prior probability represents a measurement of simplicity of a theory, whereas the notion of likelihood represents the theory's goodness-of-fit. We justify the use of prior probability and show how to calculate the likelihood of a family of curves. We diagnose the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  5. The Curve Fitting Problem: A Bayesian Approach.Prasanta S. Bandyopadhayay, Robert J. Boik & Prasun Basu - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (5):S264-S272.
    In the curve fitting problem two conflicting desiderata, simplicity and goodness-of-fit, pull in opposite directions. To this problem, we propose a solution that strikes a balance between simplicity and goodness-of-fit. Using Bayes' theorem we argue that the notion of prior probability represents a measurement of simplicity of a theory, whereas the notion of likelihood represents the theory's goodness-of-fit. We justify the use of prior probability and show how to calculate the likelihood of a family of curves. We diagnose the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  6.  11
    The Curve Fitting Problem: A Bayesian Approach.Prasanta S. Bandyopadhayay, Robert J. Boik & Susan Vineberg - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (S3):S264-S272.
    In the curve fitting problem two conflicting desiderata, simplicity and goodness-of-fit, pull in opposite directions. To this problem, we propose a solution that strikes a balance between simplicity and goodness-of-fit. Using Bayes’ theorem we argue that the notion of prior probability represents a measurement of simplicity of a theory, whereas the notion of likelihood represents the theory’s goodness-of-fit. We justify the use of prior probability and show how to calculate the likelihood of a family of curves. We diagnose the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7.  60
    Syntax-directed discovery in mathematics.David S. Henley - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (2):241 - 259.
    It is shown how mathematical discoveries such as De Moivre's theorem can result from patterns among the symbols of existing formulae and that significant mathematical analogies are often syntactic rather than semantic, for the good reason that mathematical proofs are always syntactic, in the sense of employing only formal operations on symbols. This radically extends the Lakatos approach to mathematical discovery by allowing proof-directed concepts to generate new theorems from scratch instead of just as evolutionary modifications to some existing (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  5
    Lo grande, lo pequeño y la mente humana.Roger Penrose, Nancy Cartwright, S. W. Hawking, M. S. Longair & Abner Shimony - 1999 - Cambridge University Press.
    Roger Penrose's original and provocative ideas about the large-scale physics of the Universe, the small-scale world of quantum physics and the physics of the mind have been the subject of controversy and discussion. These ideas were set forth in his best-selling books The Emperor's New Mind and Shadows of the Mind. In this book, he summarises and brings up to date his current thinking in these complex areas. He presents a masterful summary of those areas of physics in which he (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  7
    Reported and enacted actions: Moving beyond reported speech and related concepts.Jeffrey S. Good - 2015 - Discourse Studies 17 (6):663-681.
    This article examines not only how events are verbally reported in everyday and institutional storytelling episodes, but also how the actions witnessed are enacted by participants. This is particularly important to not only the believability of what occurred and is being discussed, but also how ordinary audience members react to stories and how they believe the truthfulness of them. As is seen in data analyzed from multiple sources, the way in which something is both reported and enacted has major implications (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. On the Depth of Szemeredi's Theorem.Andrew Arana - 2015 - Philosophia Mathematica 23 (2):163-176.
    Many mathematicians have cited depth as an important value in their research. However, there is no single widely accepted account of mathematical depth. This article is an attempt to bridge this gap. The strategy is to begin with a discussion of Szemerédi's theorem, which says that each subset of the natural numbers that is sufficiently dense contains an arithmetical progression of arbitrary length. This theorem has been judged deep by many mathematicians, and so makes for a good case (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11. Wittgenstein as his own worst enemy: The case of gödel's theorem.Mark Steiner - 2001 - Philosophia Mathematica 9 (3):257-279.
    Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, Wittgenstein, despite his official 'mathematical nonrevisionism', slips into attempting to refute Gödel's theorem. Actually, Wittgenstein could have used Gödel's theorem to good effect, to support his view that proof, and even truth, are 'family resemblance' concepts. The reason that Wittgenstein did not see all this is that Gödel's theorem had become an icon of mathematical realism, and he was blinded by his own ideology. The essay is a reply to Juliet Floyd's (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  12. Students' conceptual ecologies and the process of conceptual change in evolution.Sherry S. Demastes, Ronald G. Good & Patsye Peebles - 1995 - Science Education 79 (6):637-666.
  13.  52
    Testing the repression hypothesis: Effects of emotional valence on memory suppression in the think – No think task.Anthony J. Lambert, Kimberly S. Good & Ian J. Kirk - 2010 - Consciousness and Cognition 19 (1):281-293.
    It has been proposed that performance in the think – no think task represents a laboratory analogue of the voluntary form of memory repression. The central prediction of this repression hypothesis is that performance in the TNT task will be influenced by emotional characteristics of the material to be remembered. This prediction was tested in two experiments by asking participants to learn paired associates in which the first item was either emotionally positive or emotionally negative . The second word was (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  14.  38
    A semantical proof of De Jongh's theorem.Jaap van Oosten - 1991 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 31 (2):105-114.
    In 1969, De Jongh proved the “maximality” of a fragment of intuitionistic predicate calculus forHA. Leivant strengthened the theorem in 1975, using proof-theoretical tools (normalisation of infinitary sequent calculi). By a refinement of De Jongh's original method (using Beth models instead of Kripke models and sheafs of partial combinatory algebras), a semantical proof is given of a result that is almost as good as Leivant's. Furthermore, it is shown thatHA can be extended to Higher Order Heyting Arithmetic+all trueΠ 2 (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15.  24
    Genetic research involving human biological materials: a need to tailor current consent forms.Sara Chandros Hull, Holly Gooding, Alison P. Klein, Esther Warshauer-Baker, Susan Metosky & Benjamin S. Wilfond - 2004 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 26 (3):1.
  16.  18
    Talking with Lorraine’s Mother and Sister, Five Months after Her Death.E. M. Robinson, G. Good & S. Burke - 2006 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 17 (1):94-96.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. James Maclaurin and Heather Dyke.Thank Goodness That'S. Over - 2008 - In L. Nathan Oaklander (ed.), The philosophy of time. New York: Routledge. pp. 35.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  2
    War and Negative Revelation: A Theoethical Reflection on Moral Injury.Michael S. Yandell - 2022 - Lexington Books.
    From the concrete experience of war, Michael S. Yandell constructs a phenomenology of “negative revelation” in which false or distorted claims of goodness and justice disintegrate and become meaningless, adding depth to the term moral injury.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. The misuse of Sober's selection for/selection of distinction.R. Goode & P. E. Griffiths - 1995 - Biology and Philosophy 10 (1):99-108.
    Elliott Sober''s selection for/selection of distinction has been widely used to clarify the idea that some properties of organisms are side-effects of selection processes. It has also been used, however, to choose between different descriptions of an evolutionary product when assigning biological functions to that product. We suggest that there is a characteristic error in these uses of the distinction. Complementary descriptions of function are misrepresented as mutually excluding one another. This error arises from a failure to appreciate that selection (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  20.  48
    Zarathustra’s Dionysian Modernism.Robert Gooding-Williams - 2001 - Stanford: Stanford University Press.
    In arguing that Nietzsche's _Thus Spoke Zarathustra_ is a philosophical explanation of the possibility of modernism—that is, of the possibility of radical cultural change through the creation of new values—the author shows that literary fiction can do the work of philosophy. Nietzsche takes up the problem of modernism by inventing Zarathustra, a self-styled cultural innovator who aspires to subvert the culture of modernity by creating new values. By showing how Zarathustra can become a creator of new values, notwithstanding the forces (...)
  21.  32
    The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences.David Gooding, Trevor Pinch & Simon Schaffer - 1989 - Cambridge University Press. Edited by David Gooding, Trevor Pinch & Simon Schaffer.
    Contributors; Preface; Introduction; Part I. Instruments in Experiments: 1. Scientific instruments: models of brass and aids to discovery; 2. Glass works: Newton’s prisms and the uses of experiment; 3. A viol of water or a wedge of glass; Part II. Experiment and Argument: 4. Galileo’s experimental discourse; 5. Fresnel, Poisson and the white spot: the role of successful predictions in the acceptance of scientific theories; 6. The rhetoric of experiment; Part III. Representing and Realising: 7. ’Magnetic curves’ and the magnetic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  22.  22
    Zarathustra's Dionysian Modernism.Robert Gooding-Williams - 2007 - Journal of Nietzsche Studies 34 (1):61-78.
  23.  13
    Empiricism in Practice: Teleology, Economy, and Observation in Faraday's Physics.David Gooding - 1982 - Isis 73:46-67.
  24. Harsanyi's 'utilitarian theorem' and utilitarianism.Mathias Risse - 2002 - Noûs 36 (4):550–577.
    1.1 In 1955, John Harsanyi proved a remarkable theorem:1 Suppose n agents satisfy the assumptions of von Neumann/Morgenstern (1947) expected utility theory, and so does the group as a whole (or an observer). Suppose that, if each member of the group prefers option a to b, then so does the group, or the observer (Pareto condition). Then the group’s utility function is a weighted sum of the individual utility functions. Despite Harsanyi’s insistence that what he calls the Utilitarian (...) embeds utilitarianism into a theory of rationality, the theorem has fallen short of having the kind of impact on the discussion of utilitarianism for which Harsanyi hoped. Yet how could the theorem influence this discussion? Utilitarianism is as attractive to some as it is appalling to others. The prospects for this dispute to be affected by a theorem seem dim. Yet a closer look shows how the theorem could make a contribution. To fix ideas, I understand by utilitarianism the following claims: (1) Consequentialism: Actions are evaluated in terms of their consequences only. (2) Bayesianism: An agent's beliefs about possible outcomes are captured probabilistically. (3) Welfarism: The judgement of the relative goodness of states of affairs is based.. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25. Condorcet's Jury Theorem and the Optimum Number of Voters.Jason Brennan - forthcoming - POLITICS.
    Many political theorists and philosophers use Condorcet's Jury Theorem to defend democracy. This paper illustrates an uncomfortable implication of Condorcet's Jury Theorem. Realistically, when the conditions of Condorcet’s Jury Theorem hold, even in very high stakes elections, having more than 100,000 citizens vote does no significant good in securing good political outcomes. On the Condorcet model, unless voters enjoy voting, or unless they produce some other value by voting, then the cost to most voters of voting exceeds (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  21
    Empiricism in Practice: Teleology, Economy, and Observation in Faraday's Physics.David Gooding - 1982 - Isis 73 (1):46-67.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  27.  4
    Gödel's Theorem in Focus.S. G. Shanker - 1987 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 182 (2):253-255.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  28.  53
    What are the functional deficits produced by hippocampal and perirhinal cortex lesions?A. R. Mayes, R. van Eijk, P. A. Gooding, C. L. Isaac & J. S. Holdstock - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (3):460-461.
    A hippocampal patient is described who shows preserved item recognition and simple recognition-based recollection but impaired recall and associative recognition. These data and other evidence suggest that contrary to Aggleton & Brown's target article, Papez circuit damage impairs only complex item-item-context recollection. A patient with perirhinal cortex damage and a delayed global memory deficit, apparently inconsistent with A&B's framework, is also described.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29. Godel's Theorem in Focus.S. G. Shanker (ed.) - 1987 - Routledge.
    A layman's guide to the mechanics of Gödel's proof together with a lucid discussion of the issues which it raises. Includes an essay discussing the significance of Gödel's work in the light of Wittgenstein's criticisms.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  30.  45
    Beauty as Propaganda.Robert Gooding-Williams - 2021 - Philosophical Topics 49 (1):13-33.
    This paper considers W.E.B. Du Bois’s short story, “Jesus Christ in Texas,” in the perspective of his analysis of the concept of beauty in Darkwater (1920); his exposition of the idea that “all art is propaganda” in “Criteria of Negro Art” (1926); and his moral psychology of white supremacy. On my account, Du Bois holds that beautiful art can help to undermine white supremacy by using representations of moral goodness to expand the white supremacist’s ethical horizons. To defend this thesis, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  72
    From phenomenology to field theory: Faraday's visual reasoning.David C. Gooding - 2006 - Perspectives on Science 14 (1):40-65.
    : Faraday is often described as an experimentalist, but his work is a dialectical interplay of concrete objects, visual images, abstract, theoretically-informed visual models and metaphysical precepts. From phenomena described in terms of patterns formed by lines of force he created a general explanation of space-filling systems of force which obey both empirical laws and principles of conservation and economy. I argue that Faraday's articulation of situated experience via visual models into a theory capable of verbal expression owed much to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32.  38
    A Search for Unity in Diversity : The "Permanent Hegelian Deposit" in the Philosophy of John Dewey.James Allan Good - 2005 - Lexington Books.
    This study demonstrates that Dewey did not reject Hegelianism during the 1890s, as scholars maintain, but developed a humanistic/historicist reading that was indebted to an American Hegelian tradition. Scholars have misunderstood the "permanent Hegelian deposit" in Dewey's thought because they have not fully appreciated this American Hegelian tradition and have assumed that his Hegelianism was based primarily on British neo-Hegelianism. ;The study examines the American reception of Hegel in the nineteenth-century by intellectuals as diverse as James Marsh and Frederic Henry (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  33.  23
    A reinstatement, in response to Gillies, of Redhead's argument in support of induction.I. J. Good - 1987 - Philosophy of Science 54 (3):470-472.
  34.  72
    John Dewey's "Permanent Hegelian Deposit" and the Exigencies of War.James Allan Good - 2006 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (2):293-313.
    From 1882 to 1903, Dewey explicitly espoused a Hegelian philosophy. Until recently, scholars agreed that he broke from Hegel no later than 1903, but never adequately accounted for what he called the "permanent deposit" that Hegel left in his mature thought. I argue that Dewey never made a clean break from Hegel. Instead, he drew on the work of the St. Louis Hegelians to fashion a non-metaphysical reading of Hegel, similar to that championed by Klaus Hartmann and other Hegel scholars (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  22
    Metaphysics versus measurement: The conversion and conservation of force in Faraday's physics.David Gooding - 1980 - Annals of Science 37 (1):1-29.
    SummaryFaraday's concept of force is described by six assumptions. These specify a concept that is quite distinct from ‘mechanical’ conceptions of his contemporaries and interpreters. Analysis of the role of these assumptions clarifies Faraday's weighting of experimental evidence and shows how closely-linked Faraday's chemistry and physics were to his theology. It is argued that Faraday was unable to secularize his concept of force by breaking the ties between his physics and his theology of nature. Examination of his basic assumptions also (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36.  91
    A suggested resolution of Miller's paradox.I. J. Good - 1970 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 21 (3):288-289.
  37. The philosophy of exploratory data analysis.I. J. Good - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (2):283-295.
    This paper attempts to define Exploratory Data Analysis (EDA) more precisely than usual, and to produce the beginnings of a philosophy of this topical and somewhat novel branch of statistics. A data set is, roughly speaking, a collection of k-tuples for some k. In both descriptive statistics and in EDA, these k-tuples, or functions of them, are represented in a manner matched to human and computer abilities with a view to finding patterns that are not "kinkera". A kinkus is a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  38.  29
    Review Essay: Jason Stanley's Theory of Propaganda and Ideology.Robert Gooding-Williams - 2017 - Constellations 24 (2):267-273.
  39.  9
    Between Data, Mathematical Analysis and Physical Theory: Research on Earth’s Magnetism in the 19th Century.Gregory A. Good - 2008 - Centaurus 50 (3):290-304.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40. Proximity’s dilemma and the difficulties of moral response to the distant sufferer.The Geography Of Goodness - 2003 - The Monist 86 (3):355-366.
    The work of the French Lithuanian Jewish philosopher, Emmanuel Levinas, describes a perceptive rethinking of the possibility of concrete acts of goodness in the world, a rethinking never more necessary than now, in the wake of the cruel realities of the twentieth century—ten million dead in the First World War, forty million dead in the Second World War, Hiroshima, Nagasaki, the Soviet gulags, the grand slaughter of Mao’s “Great Leap Forward,” the pointless and gory Vietnam War, the Cambodian self-genocide and (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  79
    Dewey's “permanent Hegelian deposit”: A reply to Hickman and Alexander.James Good - 2008 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (4):pp. 577-602.
    I respond to the comments by Larry Hickman and Thomas Alexander about my book, A Search for Unity in Diversity: The “Permanent Hegelian Deposit” in the Philosophy of John Dewey . I focus on four issues: 1) Precisely how do I prefer to characterize Dewey’s debt to Hegel? 2) How do I justify my admittedly controversial reading of Dewey’s World War I criticisms of Hegel? 3) Where do I believe Dewey found ideas in Hegel that led him to articulate the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  34
    Conceptual and Experimental Bases of Faraday's Denial of Electrostatic Action at a Distance.David Gooding - 1978 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 9 (2):117.
  43.  78
    Discussion of Bruno de finetti's paper 'initial probabilities: A prerequisite for any valid induction'.I. J. Good - 1969 - Synthese 20 (1):17 - 24.
  44.  20
    Special section: Lorenzo Simpson' s The Unfinished Project: Sensibilities in conflict.Robert Gooding-Williams - 2007 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 33 (3):275-287.
    In the remarks that follow I concentrate on Lorenzo Simpson's two books, Technology, Time and the Conversations of Modernity and The Unfinished Project: Toward a Postmetaphysical Humanism. Common to both works — what unites them, I believe — is a philosophical orientation that has been deeply influenced by Gadamerian hermeneutics. I begin with a discussion of UP.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  3
    Althusser's Marxism.T. Good - 1976 - Télos 1976 (30):226-230.
  46.  11
    Broca's Brain: Reflections on the Romance of Science.T. Good - 1979 - Télos 1979 (41):200-204.
  47.  33
    Democracy’s History of Inegalitarianism: Symposium on Michael Hanchard, The Spectre of Race: How Discrimination Haunts Western Democracy, Princeton University Press, 2018.Robert Gooding-Williams, David Theo Goldberg, Juliet Hooker & Michael G. Hanchard - 2020 - Political Theory 48 (3):357-377.
  48.  5
    U.S. Coast Survey vs. Naval Hydrographic Office: A Nineteenth-Century Rivalry in Science and PoliticsThomas G. Manning.Gregory A. Good - 1989 - Isis 80 (3):537-538.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  26
    Zarathustra's descent: Incipit tragoedia, incipit parodia.Robert Gooding-Williams - 1995 - Journal of Nietzsche Studies 9:50-76.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  67
    A note on Richard's paradox.I. J. Good - 1966 - Mind 75 (299):431.
1 — 50 / 992