Results for 'Induction (Mathematics) '

741 found
Order:
  1. Justifying induction mathematically: Strategies and functions.Alexander Paseau - 2008 - Logique Et Analyse 51 (203):263.
    If the total state of the universe is encodable by a real number, Hardin and Taylor have proved that there is a solution to one version of the problem of induction, or at least a solution to a closely related epistemological problem. Is this philosophical application of the Hardin-Taylor result modest enough? The paper advances grounds for doubt. [A longer and more detailed sequel to this paper, 'Proving Induction', was published in the Australasian Journal of Logic in 2011.].
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  95
    Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning: Induction and analogy in mathematics.George Pólya - 1954 - Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press.
    Here the author of How to Solve It explains how to become a "good guesser." Marked by G. Polya's simple, energetic prose and use of clever examples from a wide range of human activities, this two-volume work explores techniques of guessing, inductive reasoning, and reasoning by analogy, and the role they play in the most rigorous of deductive disciplines.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  3. Mathematical instrumentalism, Gödel’s theorem, and inductive evidence.Alexander Paseau - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):140-149.
    Mathematical instrumentalism construes some parts of mathematics, typically the abstract ones, as an instrument for establishing statements in other parts of mathematics, typically the elementary ones. Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem seems to show that one cannot prove the consistency of all of mathematics from within elementary mathematics. It is therefore generally thought to defeat instrumentalisms that insist on a proof of the consistency of abstract mathematics from within the elementary portion. This article argues that though (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  14
    Handbook of Mathematical Induction: Theory and Applications.David S. Gunderson - 2010 - Chapman & Hall/Crc.
    Handbook of Mathematical Induction: Theory and Applications shows how to find and write proofs via mathematical induction. This comprehensive book covers the theory, the structure of the written proof, all standard exercises, and hundreds of application examples from nearly every area of mathematics. In the first part of the book, the author discusses different inductive techniques, including well-ordered sets, basic mathematical induction, strong induction, double induction, infinite descent, downward induction, and several variants. He (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  5
    The method of mathematical induction.I. S. Sominskiĭ - 1961 - Boston,: Heath. Edited by L. I. Golovina & I. M. I︠A︡glom.
    The method of mathematical induction: The method of mathematical induction -- Examples and exercises -- The proof of induction of some theorems of elemetary algebra -- Solutions.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  47
    Mathematical reasoning: induction, deduction and beyond.David Sherry - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (3):489-504.
    Mathematics used to be portrayed as a deductive science. Stemming from Polya, however, is a philosophical movement which broadens the concept of mathematical reasoning to include inductive or quasi-empirical methods. Interest in inductive methods is a welcome turn from foundationalism toward a philosophy grounded in mathematical practice. Regrettably, though, the conception of mathematical reasoning embraced by quasi-empiricists is still too narrow to include the sort of thought-experiment which Mueller describes as traditional mathematical proof and which Lakatos examines in Proofs (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  7.  47
    Induction and explanatory definitions in mathematics.Lehet Ellen - 2019 - Synthese 198 (2):1161-1175.
    In this paper, I argue that there are cases of explanatory induction in mathematics. To do so, I first introduce the notion of explanatory definition in the context of mathematical explanation. A large part of the paper is dedicated to introducing and analyzing this notion of explanatory definition and the role it plays in mathematics. After doing so, I discuss a particular inductive definition in advanced mathematics—CW\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${ CW}$$\end{document}-complexes—and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  8.  27
    Mathematical induction and its formation during childhood.Leslie Smith - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (6):669-670.
    I support Rips et al.'s critique of psychology through (1) a complementary argument about the normative, modal, constitutive nature of mathematical principles. I add two reservations about their analysis of mathematical induction, arguing (2) for constructivism against their logicism as to its interpretation and formation in childhood (Smith 2002), and (3) for Piaget's account of reasons in rule learning.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  42
    Monotone inductive definitions in explicit mathematics.Michael Rathjen - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (1):125-146.
    The context for this paper is Feferman's theory of explicit mathematics, T 0 . We address a problem that was posed in [6]. Let MID be the principle stating that any monotone operation on classifications has a least fixed point. The main objective of this paper is to show that T 0 + MID, when based on classical logic, also proves the existence of non-monotone inductive definitions that arise from arbitrary extensional operations on classifications. From the latter we deduce (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10. Why proofs by mathematical induction are generally not explanatory.Marc Lange - 2009 - Analysis 69 (2):203-211.
    Philosophers who regard some mathematical proofs as explaining why theorems hold, and others as merely proving that they do hold, disagree sharply about the explanatory value of proofs by mathematical induction. I offer an argument that aims to resolve this conflict of intuitions without making any controversial presuppositions about what mathematical explanations would be.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  11. Poincaré and Prawitz on mathematical induction.Yacin Hamami - 2015 - In Pavel Arazim & Michal Dancak (eds.), Logica Yearbook 2014. College Publications. pp. 149-164.
    Poincaré and Prawitz have both developed an account of how one can acquire knowledge through reasoning by mathematical induction. Surprisingly, their two accounts are very close to each other: both consider that what underlies reasoning by mathematical induction is a certain chain of inferences by modus ponens ‘moving along’, so to speak, the well-ordered structure of the natural numbers. Yet, Poincaré’s central point is that such a chain of inferences is not sufficient to account for the knowledge acquisition (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  35
    Solving Inductive Reasoning Problems in Mathematics: Not‐so‐Trivial Pursuit.Lisa A. Haverty, Kenneth R. Koedinger, David Klahr & Martha W. Alibali - 2000 - Cognitive Science 24 (2):249-298.
    This study investigated the cognitive processes involved in inductive reasoning. Sixteen undergraduates solved quadratic function–finding problems and provided concurrent verbal protocols. Three fundamental areas of inductive activity were identified: Data Gathering, Pattern Finding, and Hypothesis Generation. These activities are evident in three different strategies that they used to successfully find functions. In all three strategies, Pattern Finding played a critical role not previously identified in the literature. In the most common strategy, called the Pursuit strategy, participants created new quantities from (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13. Mathematical Induction and Explanation.Alan Baker - 2010 - Analysis 70 (4):681-689.
  14.  16
    Epicurean Induction and Atomism in Mathematics.Michael Aristidou - 2023 - Athens Journal of Philosophy 2 (2):101-118.
    In this paper1, we explore some positive elements from the Epicurean position on mathematics. Is induction important in mathematical practice or useful in proof? Does atomism appear in mathematics and in what ways? Keywords: Epicurus, induction, Polya, proof, atomism.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  25
    Mathematical induction in ramified type theory.James R. Royse - 1969 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 15 (1-3):7-10.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16.  14
    Reasoning by Mathematical Induction in Children's Arithmetic.Leslie Smith - 2002 - Elsevier.
    The central argument that Leslie Smith makes in this study is that reasoning by mathematical induction develops during childhood. The basis for this claim is a study conducted with children aged five to seven years in school years one and two.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  20
    Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning. G. Polya Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1954. Vol. I, Induction and Analogy in Mathematics, pp. xii, 280, $5.50. Vol. II, Patterns of Plausible Inference, pp. x, 190, $4.50. The set $9.00.Tibor Rado - 1956 - Philosophy of Science 23 (2):167-167.
  18.  22
    Mathematical induction in ramified type theory.James R. Royse - 1969 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 15 (1‐3):7-10.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  38
    Inductive inference and reverse mathematics.Rupert Hölzl, Sanjay Jain & Frank Stephan - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (12):1242-1266.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  38
    Elementary induction on abstract structures.Yiannis Nicholas Moschovakis - 1974 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications.
    Hailed by the Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society as "easy to use and a pleasure to read," this research monograph is recommended for students and professionals interested in model theory and definability theory. The sole prerequisite is a familiarity with the basics of logic, model theory, and set theory. 1974 edition.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  21.  66
    Ordinal inequalities, transfinite induction, and reverse mathematics.Jeffry L. Hirst - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):769-774.
    If α and β are ordinals, α ≤ β, and $\beta \nleq \alpha$ , then α + 1 ≤ β. The first result of this paper shows that the restriction of this statement to countable well orderings is provably equivalent to ACA 0 , a subsystem of second order arithmetic introduced by Friedman. The proof of the equivalence is reminiscent of Dekker's construction of a hypersimple set. An application of the theorem yields the equivalence of the set comprehension scheme ACA (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  94
    Logical probability, mathematical statistics, and the problem of induction.Hermann Vetter - 1969 - Synthese 20 (1):56 - 71.
    In this paper I want to discuss some basic problems of inductive logic, i.e. of the attempt to solve the problem of induction by means of a calculus of logical probability. I shall try to throw some light upon these problems by contrasting inductive logic, based on logical probability, and working with undefined samples of observations, with mathematical statistics, based on statistical probability, and working with representative random samples.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  27
    On the origin of mathematical induction.Stanisław Kamiński - 1958 - Studia Logica 7 (1):221-241.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  12
    Pure Inductive Logic.Jeffrey Paris & Alena Vencovská - 2011 - Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Alena Vencovská.
    Pure Inductive Logic is the study of rational probability treated as a branch of mathematical logic. This monograph, the first devoted to this approach, brings together the key results from the past seventy years, plus the main contributions of the authors and their collaborators over the last decade, to present a comprehensive account of the discipline within a single unified context.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25.  11
    Revisiting Al-Samaw’al’s table of binomial coefficients: Greek inspiration, diagrammatic reasoning and mathematical induction.Clemency Montelle, John Hannah & Sanaa Bajri - 2015 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 69 (6):537-576.
    In a famous passage from his al-Bāhir, al-Samaw’al proves the identity which we would now write as (ab)n=anbn\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$(ab)^n=a^n b^n$$\end{document} for the cases n=3,4\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$n=3,4$$\end{document}. He also calculates the equivalent of the expansion of the binomial (a+b)n\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$(a+b)^n$$\end{document} for the same values of n and describes the construction of what we now call the Pascal Triangle, showing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  25
    Definition by induction in Quine's new foundations for mathematical logic.Barkley Bosser - 1939 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 4 (2):80-81.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Semantic omega properties and mathematical induction.J. Corcoran - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2:468.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  37
    Henkin Leon. On mathematical induction. American mathematical monthly, vol. 67 , pp. 323–338.H. Hermes - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (1):92-93.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  17
    Fragments of [mathematical formula] based on [mathematical formula]-induction.Kai F. Wehmeier - 1997 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 36 (1).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  28
    The Use of Mathematical Induction by Abū Kāmil Shujā' Ibn Aslam.Mohammad Yadegari - 1978 - Isis 69 (2):259-262.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  17
    On the proof-theoretic strength of monotone induction in explicit mathematics.Thomas Glaß, Michael Rathjen & Andreas Schlüter - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 85 (1):1-46.
    We characterize the proof-theoretic strength of systems of explicit mathematics with a general principle asserting the existence of least fixed points for monotone inductive definitions, in terms of certain systems of analysis and set theory. In the case of analysis, these are systems which contain the Σ12-axiom of choice and Π12-comprehension for formulas without set parameters. In the case of set theory, these are systems containing the Kripke-Platek axioms for a recursively inaccessible universe together with the existence of a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32.  44
    Conditionals, quantification, and strong mathematical induction.Daniel H. Cohen - 1991 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 20 (3):315 - 326.
  33.  10
    A theory for the induction of mathematical functions.L. Rowell Huesmann & Chao-Ming Cheng - 1973 - Psychological Review 80 (2):126-138.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  77
    The Successor Function and Induction Principle in a Hegelian Philosophy of Mathematics.Alan L. T. Paterson - 2000 - Idealistic Studies 30 (1):25-60.
  35. Can Proofs by Mathematical Induction Be Explanatory?Josephine Salverda - 2018 - In John Baldwin (ed.), Truth, Existence and Explanation. Springer Verlag.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  78
    The Justification of Mathematical Induction.George Boolos - 1984 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1984:469 - 475.
  37. Category-based induction in conceptual spaces.Matías Osta-Vélez & Peter Gärdenfors - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Psychology 96.
    Category-based induction is an inferential mechanism that uses knowledge of conceptual relations in order to estimate how likely is for a property to be projected from one category to another. During the last decades, psychologists have identified several features of this mechanism, and they have proposed different formal models of it. In this article; we propose a new mathematical model for category-based induction based on distances on conceptual spaces. We show how this model can predict most of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  38.  36
    Inductively generated formal topologies.Thierry Coquand, Giovanni Sambin, Jan Smith & Silvio Valentini - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 124 (1-3):71-106.
    Formal topology aims at developing general topology in intuitionistic and predicative mathematics. Many classical results of general topology have been already brought into the realm of constructive mathematics by using formal topology and also new light on basic topological notions was gained with this approach which allows distinction which are not expressible in classical topology. Here we give a systematic exposition of one of the main tools in formal topology: inductive generation. In fact, many formal topologies can be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  39. Explanation by induction?Miguel Hoeltje, Benjamin Schnieder & Alex Steinberg - 2013 - Synthese 190 (3):509-524.
    Philosophers of mathematics commonly distinguish between explanatory and non-explanatory proofs. An important subclass of mathematical proofs are proofs by induction. Are they explanatory? This paper addresses the question, based on general principles about explanation. First, a recent argument for a negative answer is discussed and rebutted. Second, a case is made for a qualified positive take on the issue.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  40. The method of infinite descent and the method of mathematical induction.Harriet F. Montague - 1944 - Philosophy of Science 11 (3):178-185.
    The purpose of this paper may be found in the following quotation. “Whenever an argument can be made to lead to a descending infinitude of natural numbers the hypothesis upon which the argument rests becomes untenable. This method of proof is called the method of infinite descent;.... It would be interesting and valuable to compare this method with the method of mathematical induction.”.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  22
    Thomas Foster, Logic, Induction and Sets, (London Mathematical Society Student Texts 56), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 2003, X + 234 pp., £50, ISBN 0 521 82621 7 (hardback), £18.99, 0 521 53361 9 (paperback). [REVIEW]Jan Woleński - 2005 - Studia Logica 81 (1):145-150.
  42. Meta-Induction and Social Epistemology: Computer Simulations of Prediction Games.Gerhard Schurz - 2009 - Episteme 6 (2):200-220.
    The justification of induction is of central significance for cross-cultural social epistemology. Different ‘epistemological cultures’ do not only differ in their beliefs, but also in their belief-forming methods and evaluation standards. For an objective comparison of different methods and standards, one needs (meta-)induction over past successes. A notorious obstacle to the problem of justifying induction lies in the fact that the success of object-inductive prediction methods (i.e., methods applied at the level of events) can neither be shown (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  43.  47
    Mathematics and plausible reasoning.George Pólya - 1954 - Princeton, N.J.,: Princeton University Press.
    2014 Reprint of 1954 American Edition. Full facsimile of the original edition, not reproduced with Optical Recognition Software. This two volume classic comprises two titles: "Patterns of Plausible Inference" and "Induction and Analogy in Mathematics." This is a guide to the practical art of plausible reasoning, particularly in mathematics, but also in every field of human activity. Using mathematics as the example par excellence, Polya shows how even the most rigorous deductive discipline is heavily dependent on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  44.  18
    Necessary use of [image] induction in a reversal.Itay Neeman - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):561 - 574.
    Jullien's indecomposability theorem (INDEC) states that if a scattered countable linear order is indecomposable, then it is either indecomposable to the left, or indecomposable to the right. The theorem was shown by Montalbán to be a theorem of hyperarithmetic analysis, and then, in the base system RCA₀ plus ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}$ induction, it was shown by Neeman to have strength strictly between weak ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}$ choice and ${\mathrm{\Delta }}_{1}^{1}$ comprehension. We prove in this paper that ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}$ induction is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  95
    Is induction epistemologically prior to deduction?George Couvalis - 2004 - Ratio 17 (1):28–44.
    Most philosophers hold that the use of our deductive powers confers an especially strong warrant on some of our mathematical and logical beliefs. By contrast, many of the same philosophers hold that it is a matter of serious debate whether any inductive inferences are cogent. That is, they hold that we might well have no warrant for inductively licensed beliefs, such as generalizations. I argue that we cannot know that we know logical and mathemati- cal truths unless we use (...). Our confidence in our logical and mathematical powers is not justified if we are inductive scep- tics. This means that inductive scepticism leads to a deductive scep- ticism. I conclude that we should either be philosophical sceptics about our knowledge of deduction and induction, or accept that some of our inductive inferences are cogent. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  30
    Induction: A Logical Analysis.Uwe Saint-Mont - 2022 - Foundations of Science 27 (2):455-487.
    The aim of this contribution is to provide a rather general answer to Hume’s problem. To this end, induction is treated within a straightforward formal paradigm, i.e., several connected levels of abstraction. Within this setting, many concrete models are discussed. On the one hand, models from mathematics, statistics and information science demonstrate how induction might succeed. On the other hand, standard examples from philosophy highlight fundamental difficulties. Thus it transpires that the difference between unbounded and bounded inductive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Experimental mathematics, computers and the a priori.Mark McEvoy - 2013 - Synthese 190 (3):397-412.
    In recent decades, experimental mathematics has emerged as a new branch of mathematics. This new branch is defined less by its subject matter, and more by its use of computer assisted reasoning. Experimental mathematics uses a variety of computer assisted approaches to verify or prove mathematical hypotheses. For example, there is “number crunching” such as searching for very large Mersenne primes, and showing that the Goldbach conjecture holds for all even numbers less than 2 × 1018. There (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48. Knowledge of Mathematics without Proof.Alexander Paseau - 2015 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (4):775-799.
    Mathematicians do not claim to know a proposition unless they think they possess a proof of it. For all their confidence in the truth of a proposition with weighty non-deductive support, they maintain that, strictly speaking, the proposition remains unknown until such time as someone has proved it. This article challenges this conception of knowledge, which is quasi-universal within mathematics. We present four arguments to the effect that non-deductive evidence can yield knowledge of a mathematical proposition. We also show (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  49.  7
    C. Spector. Inductively defined sets of natural numbers. Infinitistic methods, Proceedings of the Symposium on Foundations of Mathematics, Warsaw, 2-9 September 1959, Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe, Warsaw, and Pergamon Press, Oxford-London-New York-Paris, 1961, pp. 97–102. [REVIEW]Stephen J. Garland - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (2):295-296.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  53
    A note on Bar Induction in Constructive Set Theory.Michael Rathjen - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (3):253-258.
    Bar Induction occupies a central place in Brouwerian mathematics. This note is concerned with the strength of Bar Induction on the basis of Constructive Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory, CZF. It is shown that CZF augmented by decidable Bar Induction proves the 1-consistency of CZF. This answers a question of P. Aczel who used Bar Induction to give a proof of the Lusin Separation Theorem in the constructive set theory CZF.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 741