Results for 'Carnap'S. Conventionalism'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. The problem with p-rules Thomas Oberdan clemson university.Carnap'S. Conventionalism - 2005 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 68 (1):119-137.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Carnap’s conventionalism in geometry.Stefan Lukits - 2013 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 88 (1):123-138.
    Against Thomas Mormann's argument that differential topology does not support Carnap's conventionalism in geometry we show their compatibility. However, Mormann's emphasis on the entanglement that characterizes topology and its associated metrics is not misplaced. It poses questions about limits of empirical inquiry. For Carnap, to pose a question is to give a statement with the task of deciding its truth. Mormann's point forces us to introduce more clarity to what it means to specify the task that decides between competing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Carnap's conventionalism: The problem with p-rules.Thomas Oberdan - 2005 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 68 (1):119-137.
    Rudolf Carnap's 'Principle of Tolerance' was undoubtedly one of the most infl uential precepts in 20th Century philosophy. Introduced in The Logical Syntax of Language, Carnap's Principle suffered from ambiguities which aroused important philosophical questions from Moritz Schlick and Alberto Coffa. Specifi cally, their questions arise from the application of the Principle to the matter of including extra-logical transformation rules in the defi nition of a language, which Carnap regarded as an important difference between his own conventionalist philosophy of logic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  24
    Carnap's conventionalism : logic, science, and tolerance.Noah Friedman-Biglin - 2014 - Dissertation, University of St Andrews
    In broadest terms, this thesis is concerned to answer the question of whether the view that arithmetic is analytic can be maintained consistently. Lest there be much suspense, I will conclude that it can. Those who disagree claim that accounts which defend the analyticity of arithmetic are either unable to give a satisfactory account of the foundations of mathematics due to the incompleteness theorems, or, if steps are taken to mitigate incompleteness, then the view loses the ability to account for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Carnap's conventionalism.Richard Creath - 1992 - Synthese 93 (1-2):141 - 165.
  6. Carnap's conventionalism.Pierre Wagner - unknown
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7. What is Carnap's conventionalism after all?Norma Yunez-Naude - 2003 - Synthese 137 (1-2):261 - 272.
    As is well known, Carnap's conventionalism was a rejection to Kant's view ofmathematics and was fully developed in his Logische Syntax der Sprache.The purpose of this article is to step back to Der Logische Aufbau der Weltto show that the Logical Syntax of Language is an attempt to solve difficultiesfound in the earlier construction. I first clarify the notion of conventionalism, whichplays a central role in the application of mathematics to the reconstruction of empiricalknowledge. By not strictly distinguishing (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  17
    Carnap’s Metrical Conventionalism versus Differential Topology.Thomas Mormann - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):814-825.
    Geometry was a main source of inspiration for Carnap's conventionalism. Taking Poincaré as his witness, Carnap asserted in his dissertation Der Raum that the metrical structure of space is conventional while the underlying topological structure describes ‘objective’ facts. With only minor modifications he stuck to this account throughout his life. The aim of this paper is to disprove Carnap's contention by invoking some classical theorems of differential topology. It is shown that his metrical conventionalism is indefensible for mathematical (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Carnap's metrical conventionalism versus differential topology.Thomas Mormann - 2004 - Proc. 2004 Biennial Meeting of the PSA, vol. I, Contributed Papers 72 (5):814 - 825.
    Geometry was a main source of inspiration for Carnap’s conventionalism. Taking Poincaré as his witness Carnap asserted in his dissertation Der Raum (Carnap 1922) that the metrical structure of space is conventional while the underlying topological structure describes "objective" facts. With only minor modifications he stuck to this account throughout his life. The aim of this paper is to disprove Carnap's contention by invoking some classical theorems of differential topology. By this means his metrical conventionalism turns out to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. Carnap's principle of tolerance, empiricism, and conventionalism.Thomas Ricketts - 1994 - In Peter Clark & Bob Hale (eds.), Reading Putnam. Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell. pp. 176--200.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  11.  3
    Carnap's Early Conventionalism: An Inquiry Into the Historical Background of the Vienna Circle.Edmund Runggaldier - 1984 - Rodopi.
    Revision of the author's thesis--Oxford University, 1977. Bibliography: p.[142]-144.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  14
    Carnap’s Early Conventionalism.Edmund Runggaldier - 1979 - International Philosophical Quarterly 19 (1):73-84.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  13. Carnap's Early Conventionalism; An Inquiry into the Historical Background of the Vienna Circle.Edmund Runggaldier - 1985 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 21 (2):281-286.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  48
    Geometric conventionalism and carnap's principle of tolerance: We discuss in this paper the question of the scope of the principle of tolerance about languages promoted in Carnap's The Logical Syntax of Language and the nature of the analogy between it and the rudimentary conventionalism purportedly exhibited in the work of Poincaré and Hilbert. We take it more or less for granted that Poincaré and Hilbert do argue for conventionalism. We begin by sketching Coffa's historical account, which suggests that tolerance be interpreted as a conventionalism that allows us complete freedom to select whatever language we wish—an interpretation that generalizes the conventionalism promoted by Poincaré and Hilbert which allows us complete freedom to select whatever axiom system we wish for geometry. We argue that such an interpretation saddles Carnap with a theory of meaning that has unhappy consequences, a theory we believe he did not hold. We suggest that the principle of linguistic tolerance in.David De Vidi & Graham Solomon - 1993 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (5):773-783.
    We discuss in this paper the question of the scope of the principle of tolerance about languages promoted in Carnap's The Logical Syntax of Language and the nature of the analogy between it and the rudimentary conventionalism purportedly exhibited in the work of Poincaré and Hilbert. We take it more or less for granted that Poincaré and Hilbert do argue for conventionalism. We begin by sketching Coffa's historical account, which suggests that tolerance be interpreted as a conventionalism (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  65
    Carnap's early conventionalism. An inquiry into the historical background of the vienna circle.Richard Creath - 1986 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 24 (3):430-431.
  16. Conventionalism in Carnap's Early Philosophy.Edmund Runggaldier - 1977
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  23
    Carnap’s Early Conventionalism[REVIEW]Paolo Dau - 1988 - International Studies in Philosophy 20 (3):143-144.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  8
    Carnap’s Early Conventionalism[REVIEW]Paolo Dau - 1988 - International Studies in Philosophy 20 (3):143-144.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  80
    Carnap's philosophy of mathematics.Benjamin Marschall - 2022 - Philosophy Compass 17 (11):e12884.
    For several decades, Carnap's philosophy of mathematics used to be either dismissed or ignored. It was perceived as a form of linguistic conventionalism and thus taken to rely on the bankrupt notion of truth by convention. However, recent scholarship has revealed a more subtle picture. It has been forcefully argued that Carnap is not a linguistic conventionalist in any straightforward sense, and that supposedly decisive objections against his position target a straw man. This raises two questions. First, how exactly (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  42
    The Methodological Roles of Tolerance and Conventionalism in the Philosophy of Mathematics: Reconsidering Carnap's Logic of Science.Emerson P. Doyle - 2014 - Dissertation, University of Western Ontario
    This dissertation makes two primary contributions. The first three chapters develop an interpretation of Carnap's Meta-Philosophical Program which places stress upon his methodological analysis of the sciences over and above the Principle of Tolerance. Most importantly, I suggest, is that Carnap sees philosophy as contiguous with science—as a part of the scientific enterprise—so utilizing the very same methods and subject to the same limitations. I argue that the methodological reforms he suggests for philosophy amount to philosophy as the explication of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  54
    Carnap's Empiricism, Lost and Found.Robert G. Hudson - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 43:81-88.
    Recent scholarship (by mainly Michael Friedman, but also by Thomas Uebel) on the philosophy of Rudolf Carnap covering the period from the publication of Carnap’s’ 1928 book Der Logische Aufbau der Welt through to the mid to late 1930’s has tended to view Carnap as espousing a form of conventionalism (epitomized by his adoption of the principle of tolerance) and not a form of empirical foundationalism. On this view, it follows that Carnap’s 1934 The Logical Syntax of Language is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Edmund Runggaldier, "Carnap's Early Conventionalism; An Inquiry into the Historical Background of The Vienna Circle". [REVIEW]Charles Lambros - 1985 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 21 (2):281.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  55
    Carnap's criterion of logicality.Denis Bonnay - 2009 - In Pierre Wagner (ed.), Carnap's Logical syntax of language. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 147-165.
    Providing a principled characterization of the distinction between logical and non-logical expressions is a longstanding issue in the philosophy of logic. In the Logical Syntax of Language, Carnap proposes a syntactic solution to this problem, which aims at grounding the claim that logic and mathematics are analytic. Roughly speaking, his idea is that logic and mathematics correspond to the largest part of science for which it is possible to completely specify by "syntactic" means which sentences are valid and which are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24.  10
    Edmund Runggaldier, "Carnap's Early Conventionalism. An Inquiry into the Historical Background of the Vienna Circle". [REVIEW]Richard Creath - 1986 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 24 (3):430.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  96
    Carnap’s 1934 Objections to Wittgenstein’s Say/show Distinction.Alexei Angelides - 2012 - Erkenntnis 76 (2):147-169.
    In sections 18 and 73 of Carnap’s Logical Syntax of Language , Carnap famously presents what he understands to be decisive objections to Wittgenstein’s Tractarian distinction between saying and showing. However, Carnap has been criticized in recent literature for severely misinterpreting that distinction. Against this criticism it is argued that Carnap reads that distinction as applying to two distinct classes of expressions ( Unsinn and sinnlos ) that he holds to emerge from his reading of Tractatus 4.1212 and related Tractarian (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  24
    Carnap’s Construction of the World. [REVIEW]Robert Hanna - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (3):717-720.
    Alan Richardson’s Carnap’s Construction of the World is a well-researched, richly-detailed, and highly instructive study of a crucial moment in the history of the analytic tradition: the transitional stage between the classical or early period dominated by Frege, Moore, and Russell, and the neo-classical or middle period dominated by Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle. This stage marks a shift from ontic analysis to linguistic analysis; from platonism to conventionalism; from realistic metaphysics to anti-metaphysics; from rationalism to empiricism; and from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  35
    Logicism and Principle of Tolerance: Carnap’s Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics.Stefano Domingues Stival - 2023 - History and Philosophy of Logic 44 (4):491-504.
    In this paper, the connection between logicism and the principle of tolerance in Carnap’s philosophy of logic and mathematics is to be presented in terms of the history of its development. Such development is conditioned by two lines of criticism to Carnap’s attempt to combine Logicism and Conventionalism, the first of which comes from Gödel, the second from Alfred Tarski. The presentation will take place in three steps. First, the Logicism of Carnap before the publication of The Logical Syntax (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Conventionalism and the Impoverishment of the Space of Reasons: Carnap, Quine and Sellars.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2015 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 3 (8).
    This article examines how Quine and Sellars develop informatively contrasting responses to a fundamental tension in Carnap’s semantics ca. 1950. Quine’s philosophy could well be styled ‘Essays in Radical Empiricism’; his assay of radical empiricism is invaluable for what it reveals about the inherent limits of empiricism. Careful examination shows that Quine’s criticism of Carnap’s semantics in ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’ fails, that at its core Quine’s semantics is for two key reasons incoherent and that his hallmark Thesis of Extensionalism (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  29.  12
    Intuition and evidential facts in Carnap’s analysis of space.Juan Bautista Bengoetxea - 2019 - Revista de Filosofia Aurora 31 (54).
    One of the reasons for Carnap’s (1922) analysis of space was the confounding status of many arguments around the state of the art on that topic at that time. The unsatisfactory views supplied by mathematicians, physicists and philosophers led Carnap to propose a new conception of space. His proposal, which employs the notion of intuition as a fundamental tool, fared better, but clashed with his conventionalists intentions derived from an allegedly tolerant attitude. The notion of intuition here examined allows us (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Carnap, the principle of tolerance, and empiricism.Robert Hudson - 2010 - Philosophy of Science 77 (3):341-358.
    Kurt Gödel criticizes Rudolf Carnap's conventionalism on the grounds that it relies on an empiricist admissibility condition, which, if applied, runs afoul of his second incompleteness theorem. Thomas Ricketts and Michael Friedman respond to Gödel's critique by denying that Carnap is committed to Gödel's admissibility criterion; in effect, they are denying that Carnap is committed to any empirical constraint in the application of his principle of tolerance. I argue in response that Carnap is indeed committed to an empirical requirement (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  57
    Quine’s 1934 “Lectures on Carnap‘.Gary Hardcastle - unknown
    In November of 1934, over successive Thursdays, the 26-year-old Willard van Orman Quine gave three “Lectures on Carnap” at Harvard University, the ostensive aim of which was a presentation of the “central doctrine” of Carnap’s Logische Syntax der Sprache, “that philosophy is syntax.” These were among Quine’s very first public lectures, and they constituted the American premier of Carnap’s logische Syntax program. As such, these lectures are of considerable significance to the history of analytic philosophy. They show, for example, one (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  52
    Conventionalism, coordination, and mental models: from Poincaré to Simon.Rouslan Koumakhov - 2014 - Journal of Economic Methodology 21 (3):251-272.
    This article focuses on the conventions that sustain social interaction and argues that they are central to Simon's decision-making theory. Simon clearly identifies two kinds of coordination by convention: behavioral mores that shape human actions, and shared mental models that govern human perceptions. This article argues that Poincaré–Carnap's conventionalism provides powerful support for Simon's theory; it contends that this theory offers a more convincing account of decision and coordination than Lewis' concept of convention. Simon's approach to applying conventionalist logic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Carnap and Kuhn: Arch enemies or close allies?Gürol Irzik & Teo Grünberg - 1995 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (3):285-307.
    We compare Carnap's and Kuhn's views on science. Although there are important differences between them, the similarities are striking. The basis for the latter is a pragmatically oriented semantic conventionalist picture of science, which suggests that the view that post-positivist philosophy of science constitutes a radical revolution which has no interesting affinities with logical positivism must be seriously mistaken.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  34.  52
    Carnap and Beth on the Limits of Tolerance.Benjamin Marschall - 2021 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 51 (4):282–300.
    Rudolf Carnap’s principle of tolerance states that there is no need to justify the adoption of a logic by philosophical means. Carnap uses the freedom provided by this principle in his philosophy of mathematics: he wants to capture the idea that mathematical truth is a matter of linguistic rules by relying on a strong metalanguage with infinitary inference rules. In this paper, I give a new interpretation of an argument by E. W. Beth, which shows that the principle of tolerance (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  44
    Carnap and Kuhn: Arch Enemies or Close Allies?Teo Grunberg & Giirol Irzik - 1995 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (3):285-307.
    We compare Carnap's and Kuhn's views on science. Although there are important differences between them, the similarities are striking. The basis for the latter is a pragmatically oriented semantic conventionalist picture of science, which suggests that the view that post-positivist philosophy of science constitutes a radical revolution which has no interesting affinities with logical positivism must be seriously mistaken.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  36. Carnap and Quine on some analytic-synthetic distinctions.Lieven Decock - unknown
    I want to analyse the Quine-Carnap discussion on analyticity with regard to logical, mathematical and set-theoretical statements. In recent years, the renewed interest in Carnap’s work has shed a new light on the analytic-synthetic debate. If one fully appreciates Carnap’s conventionalism, one sees that there was not a metaphysical debate on whether there is an analytic-synthetic distinction, but rather a controversy on the expedience of drawing such a distinction. However, on this view, there can be no longer a single (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  75
    Carnap and the compulsions of interpretation: Reining in the liberalization of empiricism. [REVIEW]Sahotra Sarkar - 2013 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 3 (3):353-372.
    Carnap’s work was instrumental to the liberalization of empiricism in the 1930s that transformed the logical positivism of the Vienna Circle to what came to be known as logical empiricism. A central feature of this liberalization was the deployment of the Principle of Tolerance, originally introduced in logic, but now invoked in an epistemological context in “Testability and Meaning”. Immediately afterwards, starting with Foundations of Logic and Mathematics, Carnap embraced semantics and turned to interpretation to guide the choice of a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38. Normativity and Instrumentalism in David Lewis’ Convention.S. M. Amadae - 2011 - History of European Ideas 37 (3):325-335.
    David Lewis presented Convention as an alternative to the conventionalism characteristic of early-twentieth-century analytic philosophy. Rudolf Carnap is well known for suggesting the arbitrariness of any particular linguistic convention for engaging in scientific inquiry. Analytic truths are self-consistent, and are not checked against empirical facts to ascertain their veracity. In keeping with the logical positivists before him, Lewis concludes that linguistic communication is conventional. However, despite his firm allegiance to conventions underlying not just languages but also social customs, he (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  39.  54
    Jan Wolenski Carnap's metaphilosophy.Carnap'S. Metaphilosophy - 2003 - In Thomas Bonk (ed.), Language, Truth and Knowledge: Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 2--27.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  24
    Carnap's internal and external questions: Part I: Quine's criticisms.I. Carnap'S. Distinctions - 2003 - In Thomas Bonk (ed.), Language, Truth and Knowledge: Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 2--97.
  41. Gödel, Carnap and the Fregean heritage.Gabriella Crocco - 2003 - Synthese 137 (1-2):21 - 41.
    Thorough a detailed analysis of version III of Gödel's Is mathematics syntax of language?, we propose a new interpretation of Gödel's criticism against the conventionalist point of view in mathematics. When one reads carefully Gödel's text, it brings out that, contrary to the opinion of some commentators, Gödel did not overlook the novelty of Carnap's solution, and did not criticise him from an old-fashioned conception of science. The general aim of our analysis is to restate the Carnap/Gödel debate in the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  14
    Conventionalism: From Poincare to Quine.Yemima Ben-Menahem - 2006 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    The daring idea that convention - human decision - lies at the root both of necessary truths and much of empirical science reverberates through twentieth-century philosophy, constituting a revolution comparable to Kant's Copernican revolution. This book provides a comprehensive study of Conventionalism. Drawing a distinction between two conventionalist theses, the under-determination of science by empirical fact, and the linguistic account of necessity, Yemima Ben-Menahem traces the evolution of both ideas to their origins in Poincaré's geometric conventionalism. She argues (...)
  43.  24
    Conventionalism: From Poincare to Quine.Yemima Ben-Menahem - 2006 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    The daring idea that convention - human decision - lies at the root both of necessary truths and much of empirical science reverberates through twentieth-century philosophy, constituting a revolution comparable to Kant's Copernican revolution. This book provides a comprehensive study of Conventionalism. Drawing a distinction between two conventionalist theses, the under-determination of science by empirical fact, and the linguistic account of necessity, Yemima Ben-Menahem traces the evolution of both ideas to their origins in Poincaré's geometric conventionalism. She argues (...)
  44.  34
    Infinite inference and mathematical conventionalism.Douglas Blue - forthcoming - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.
    We argue that (1) a purported example of an infinite inference we humans can actually perform admits a faithful, finitary description, and (2) infinite inference contravenes any view which does not grant our minds uncomputable powers. These arguments block the strategy, dating back to Carnap's Logical Syntax of Language, of using infinitary inference rules to secure the determinacy of arithmetical truth on conventionalist grounds.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Herbert G. Bohnert.Carnap'S. Logicism - 1975 - In Jaakko Hintikka (ed.), Rudolf Carnap, logical empiricist: materials and perspectives. Boston: D. Reidel Pub. Co.. pp. 73--183.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Richard C. Jeffrey.Carnap'S. Inductive Logic - 1975 - In Jaakko Hintikka (ed.), Rudolf Carnap, logical empiricist: materials and perspectives. Boston: D. Reidel Pub. Co.. pp. 73--325.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  20
    Ilkka Niiniluoto Carnap on truth.I. Carnap'S. Early Work - 2003 - In Thomas Bonk (ed.), Language, Truth and Knowledge: Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 2--1.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Bertrand Russell's the analysis of matter: Its historical context and contemporary interest.William Demopoulos & Michael Friedman - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (4):621-639.
    The Analysis of Matter is perhaps best known for marking Russell's rejection of phenomenalism and his development of a variety of Lockean representationalism–-Russell's causal theory of perception. This occupies Part 2 of the work. Part 1, which is certainly less well known, contains many observations on twentieth-century physics. Unfortunately, Russell's discussion of relativity and the foundations of physical geometry is carried out in apparent ignorance of Reichenbach's and Carnap's investigations in the same period. The issue of conventionalism in its (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   116 citations  
  49. Realism.Penelope Maddy - 1990 - In Realism in mathematics. New York: Oxford University Prress.
    The early sections describe the pre‐theoretic realism of the mathematician, survey the basic forms of realism in philosophy, and attempt to disentangle the issues of realism from debates over the nature of truth. The final section begins by laying out traditional Platonism, intuitionism, and formalism. Quine's famous critique of Carnap's conventionalism then leads to Quine's realism, and Putnam's developments thereof, while a different sort of mathematical realism is found in Gödel's writings. Set theoretic realism emerges as an effort to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  49
    Historicism, Entrenchment, and Conventionalism.Nathaniel Jason Goldberg - 2009 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 40 (2):259-276.
    W. V. Quine famously argues that though all knowledge is empirical, mathematics is entrenched relative to physics and the special sciences. Further, entrenchment accounts for the necessity of mathematics relative to these other disciplines. Michael Friedman challenges Quine’s view by appealing to historicism, the thesis that the nature of science is illuminated by taking into account its historical development. Friedman argues on historicist grounds that mathematical claims serve as principles constitutive of languages within which empirical claims in physics and the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000