Results for 'Semantics (Law) '

810 found
Order:
  1. The semantics and metaphysics of natural kinds edited by Helen Beebee and Nigel sabbarton-Leary.S. Law - 2012 - Analysis 72 (3):621-622.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  19
    Semantics of Kripke's style for some modal systems.Wies law Dziobiak - 1976 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 5 (2):63-66.
  3.  25
    Non-existence of a countable strongly adequate matrix semantics for neighbours of E.Wies law Dziobiak - 1981 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 10 (4):170-174.
  4.  18
    A note on incompleteness of modal logics with respect to neighbourhood semantics.Wies law Dziobiak - 1978 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 7 (4):185-189.
  5.  20
    Early Semantics.Lancelot Law Whyte - 1960 - Philosophy 35 (134):272.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Naturalism, evolution and true belief.Stephen Law - 2012 - Analysis 72 (1):41-48.
    Plantinga's Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism aims to show that naturalism is, as he puts it, ‘incoherent or self defeating’. Plantinga supposes that, in the absence of any God-like being to guide the process, natural selection is unlikely to favour true belief. Plantinga overlooks the fact that adherents of naturalism may plausibly hold that there exist certain conceptual links between belief content and behaviour. Given such links, natural selection will favour true belief. A further rather surprising consequence of the existence of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  7.  9
    Force shift: a case study of Cantonese ho2 particle clusters.Jess H.-K. Law, Haoze Li & Diti Bhadra - forthcoming - Natural Language Semantics:1-43.
    This paper investigates force shift, a phenomenon in which the canonical discourse conventions, or force, associated with a clause type can be overridden to yield polar questions with the help of additional force-indicating devices. Previous studies attribute force shift to the presence of a complex question force component operating on semantic content. Based on utterance particles and particle clusters in Cantonese, we analyze force shift as resulting from compositional operations on force-bearing expressions. We propose that a simplex force, such as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  33
    Believing bullshit: how not to get sucked into an intellectual black hole.Stephen Law - 2011 - Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books.
    Playing the mystery card -- "But it fits!" -- Going nuclear -- Moving the semantic goalposts -- "But I just know!" -- Pseudo-profundity -- Piling up the anecdotes -- Pressing your buttons -- Conclusion -- The Tapescrew letters.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  6
    Metonymy and argument alternations in French communication frames.James Law - 2022 - Cognitive Linguistics 33 (2):387-413.
    This study describes metonymic argument alternations, in which a constructional slot can be filled by any of a set of semantic roles that index one another, and provides a diachronic corpus analysis of two such alternations in French. In the Reveal secret frame and other communication frames, the Medium can indexically replace the Speaker and the Topic can indexically replace the Information. A regression analysis shows that while topic for information metonymy is more syntactically and pragmatically restricted, medium for speaker (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  55
    Plantinga's belief-cum-desire argument refuted.Stephen Law - 2011 - Religious Studies 47 (2):245-256.
    In Warrant and Proper Function, Alvin Plantinga develops an argument designed to show that naturalism is self-defeating. One component of this larger argument is what I call Plantinga's belief-cum-desire argument, which is intended to establish something more specific: that if the content of our beliefs does causally effect behaviour (that is to say, semantic content is not epiphenomenal), and if naturalism and current evolutionary doctrine are correct, then the probability that we possess reliable cognitive mechanisms must be either inscrutable or (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Commonsense Metaphysics and Lexical Semantics.Jerry R. Hobbs, William Croft, Todd Davies, Douglas Edwards & Kenneth Laws - 1987 - Computational Linguistics 13 (3&4):241-250.
    In the TACITUS project for using commonsense knowledge in the understanding of texts about mechanical devices and their failures, we have been developing various commonsense theories that are needed to mediate between the way we talk about the behavior of such devices and causal models of their operation. Of central importance in this effort is the axiomatization of what might be called commonsense metaphysics. This includes a number of areas that figure in virtually every domain of discourse, such as granularity, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  12. Laws of Nature, Explanation, and Semantic Circularity.Erica Shumener - 2019 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 70 (3):787-815.
    Humeans and anti-Humeans agree that laws of nature should explain scientifically particular matters of fact. One objection to Humean accounts of laws contends that Humean laws cannot explain particular matters of fact because their explanations are harmfully circular. This article distinguishes between metaphysical and semantic characterizations of the circularity and argues for a new semantic version of the circularity objection. The new formulation suggests that Humean explanations are harmfully circular because the content of the sentences being explained is part of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  13.  55
    Alternatives in different dimensions: a case study of focus intervention.Haoze Li & Jess H.-K. Law - 2016 - Linguistics and Philosophy 39 (3):201-245.
    In Beck, focus intervention is used as an argument for reducing Hamblin’s semantics for questions to Rooth’s focus semantics. Drawing on novel empirical evidence from Mandarin and English, we argue that this reduction is unwarranted. Maintaining both Hamblin’s original semantics and Rooth’s focus semantics not only allows for a more adequate account for focus intervention in questions, but also correctly predicts that focus intervention is a very general phenomenon caused by interaction of alternatives in different dimensions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  41
    On fragments of Medvedev's logic.Miros>law Szatkowski - 1981 - Studia Logica 40 (1):39 - 54.
    Medvedev's intermediate logic (MV) can be defined by means of Kripke semantics as the family of Kripke frames given by finite Boolean algebras without units as partially ordered sets. The aim of this paper is to present a proof of the theorem: For every set of connectives such that the-fragment ofMV equals the fragment of intuitionistic logic. The final part of the paper brings the negative solution to the problem set forth by T. Hosoi and H. Ono, namely: is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  19
    Semantic types of legal norms in German laws: classification and analysis using local linear explanations.Bernhard Waltl, Georg Bonczek, Elena Scepankova & Florian Matthes - 2019 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 27 (1):43-71.
    This paper describes the automated classification of legal norms in German statutes with regard to their semantic type. We propose a semantic type taxonomy for norms in the German civil law domain consisting of nine different types focusing on functional aspects, such as Duties, Prohibitions, Permissions, etc. We performed four iterations in classifying legal norms with a rule-based approach using a manually labeled dataset, i.e., tenancy law, of the German Civil Code ). During this experiment the \ score continuously improved (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  50
    There Is No Distinctively Semantic Circularity Objection to Humean Laws.David Mark Kovacs - 2021 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 51 (4):270-281.
    Humeans identify the laws of nature with universal generalizations that systematize rather than govern the particular matters of fact. Humeanism is frequently accused of circularity: laws explain their instances, but Humean laws are, in turn, grounded by those instances. Unfortunately, this argument trades on controversial assumptions about grounding and explanation that Humeans routinely reject. However, recently an ostensibly semantic circularity objection has been offered, which seeks to avoid reading such assumptions into the Humean view. This paper argues that the new (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  25
    Constructive semantics, admissibility of rules and the validity of Peirce's law.W. De Campos Sanz, T. Piecha & P. Schroeder-Heister - 2014 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 22 (2):297-308.
  18. Semantics, Metaphysics, and Objectivity in the Law.Michael S. Moore - 2016 - In Geert Keil & Ralf Poscher (eds.), Vagueness and Law: Philosophical and Legal Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    The advantages of adopting a realist semantics within linguistics are seen as: first, such semantics can allow for meaningful disagreements between speakers; and second, such semantics minimizes indeterminacy. These two advantages are translated into comparable advantages for such semantics if used in law. Three different versions of realist semantics are distinguished within recent legal theory. Only one of these is deemed capable of delivering the advantages of a truly realist semantics. Although a broad applicability (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  65
    The Semantics and Pragmatics of 'According to the Law'.Jose Juan Moreso & Samuele Chilovi - 2016 - In Alessandro Capone & Francesca Poggi (eds.), Pragmatics and Law: Philosophical Perspectives. Cham: Springer. pp. 61-88.
  20.  48
    Regulation retrieval using industry specific taxonomies.Chin Pang Cheng, Gloria T. Lau, Kincho H. Law, Jiayi Pan & Albert Jones - 2008 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 16 (3):277-303.
    Increasingly, taxonomies are being developed and used by industry practitioners to facilitate information interoperability and retrieval. Within a single industrial domain, there exist many taxonomies that are intended for different applications. Industry specific taxonomies often represent the vocabularies that are commonly used by the practitioners. Their jobs are multi-faceted, which include checking for code and regulatory compliance. As such, it will be very desirable if industry practitioners are able to easily locate and browse regulations of interest. In practice, multiple sources (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  65
    Semantic sources of the concept of law.Gerd Buchdahl - 1967 - Synthese 17 (1):54 - 74.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  30
    The semantic status of laws of logic.Erik Stenius - 1970 - Theoria 36 (3):214-220.
  23. The Semantics and Pragmatics in the Philosophy of Law.Marek Nestina - 2013 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 20:105-121.
  24. Some logico-semantical themes in Karl Olivecrona's philosophy of law: A non-exegetical approach.Lennart Åqvist - 2008 - Theoria 74 (4):271-294.
    The paper deals with certain issues with which Olivecrona was mainly concerned in his Philosophy of Law, notably (i) his views about the logical or syntactical form of imperatives as used in the law, and (ii) his views on the semantics of imperatives in the law and on the question whether and to what extent the notions of truth and falsity are applicable to those imperatives at all. In the light of an important critical notice of Olivecrona's work by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  14
    Ecosystem Vulnerability. New Semantics for International Law.Mariano Longo & Vincenzo Lorubbio - 2023 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 36 (4):1611-1628.
    The effects of climate change and increasing environmental pollution have clearly shown the vulnerability of individuals, local communities, and the natural environment, even in the Western context. However, despite such unquestionable data, International Law is still struggling to find adequate, unambiguous, effective solutions to the issue. Even the ‘human right to a healthy environment’, recognised by the UN General Assembly in 2022, is permeated by an anthropocentric idea of the world, which prevents it from fully dealing with ecosystem issues so (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  1
    Semantics of Power: Written Communication, Formal Documentation and Codified Law in British Malabar.Thapasya Jayaraj & K. C. Navas - forthcoming - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique:1-24.
    Linguistic choices have different attributions beyond their literal meaning according to their contexts. This paper looks at the variations in the discourses seen in the written colonial agreements and treaties during the Malabar conquest. The study employs the archived documents of various discourses during this period as a part of power shifting from the local elites to the colonial power. It explores how power is intertwined in the linguistic choices of different communication files. The study employs a hybrid methodology of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Semantics and pragmatics of the language in the law.Marek Nestina - 2012 - Filozofia 67 (9):718-730.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Foreign Language Learning in Older Adults: Anatomical and Cognitive Markers of Vocabulary Learning Success.Manson Cheuk-Man Fong, Matthew King-Hang Ma, Jeremy Yin To Chui, Tammy Sheung Ting Law, Nga-Yan Hui, Alma Au & William Shiyuan Wang - 2022 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 16.
    In recent years, foreign language learning has been proposed as a possible cognitive intervention for older adults. However, the brain network and cognitive functions underlying FLL has remained largely unconfirmed in older adults. In particular, older and younger adults have markedly different cognitive profile—while older adults tend to exhibit decline in most cognitive domains, their semantic memory usually remains intact. As such, older adults may engage the semantic functions to a larger extent than the other cognitive functions traditionally considered the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  24
    Should Special Science Laws Be Written into the Semantics of Counterfactuals?Daniel Dohrn - 2019 - Kairos 22 (1):86-108.
    Adam Elga has presented an anti-thermodynamic process as a counterexample to Lewis’s default semantics for counterfactuals. The outstanding reaction of Jonathan Schaffer and Boris Kment is revisionary. It sacrifices Lewis’s aim of defining causation in terms of counterfactual dependence. Lewis himself suggested an alternative: «counter-entropic funnybusiness» should make for dissimilarity. But how is this alternative to be spelled out? I discuss a recent proposal: include special science laws, among them the laws of thermodynamics. Although the proposal fails, it serves (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. How to Give a Semantic Analysis of Ceteris Paribus Laws.Kai-Yuan Cheng - 2008 - Cadernos de História E Filosofia da Ciéncia 18 (1).
    The phrase of ceteris paribus , i.e., other things being equal, is widely employed to state laws in non-basic sciences, such as economics, medicine, geography, biology, and psychology. However, what the phrase in question says is highly unclear, which results in severe philosophical problems calling into question the status of special sciences. The main purpose of this paper is to critically examine a lexicographic study of cp proposed by Michael Morreau , who tries to provide an adequate semantic analysis of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. The Role of Kinds in the Semantics of Ceteris Paribus Laws.Bernhard Nickel - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (S10):1729-1744.
    This paper investigates the interaction between semantic theories for cp-laws (roughly, laws that hold “all things equal”) and metaphysical theories of kinds in the special sciences. Its central conclusion is that cp-laws concerning kinds behave differently from cp-laws concerning non-kinds: “ravens are black” which concerns the kind corvus corax, behaves differently from from “albino ravens are white” which concerns the non-kind grouping of albino ravens. I argue that this difference is in the first instance logical: the two sorts of cp-laws (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  32.  8
    Trends in legal knowledge: the semantic web and the regulation of electronic social systems: papers from the B-4 workshop on artificial intelligence and law, May 25th- 27th 2005: XXII World Congress of philosophy IVR '05 Granada, May 24th-29th 2005.Pompeu Casanovas Romeu (ed.) - 2007 - Florence: European Press Academic.
  33.  8
    The Law as a System of Signs.Roberta Kevelson - 2011 - Springer.
    Even if Peirce were well understood and there existed· general agreement among Peirce scholars on what he meant by his semiotics, or philosophy of signs, the undertaking of this book-wliich intends to establish a theoretical foundation for a new approach to understanding the interrelations of law, economics, and politics against referent systems of value-would be a risky venture. But since such general agreement on Peirce's work is lacking, one's sense of adventure in ideas requires further qualification. Indeed, the proverbial nerve (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  34.  75
    Coherence theory reconsidered: Professor Werkmeister on semantics and on the nature of empirical laws.May Brodbeck - 1949 - Philosophy of Science 16 (1):75-85.
    Werkmeister's new book, The Basis and Structure of Knowledge is the second major attempt in recent years to defend the idealistic theory of knowledge. The first was Blanshard's Nature of Thought; and it is worth noticing that both authors, in undertaking the defense of a position long in the shadows, are well aware of contemporary developments in logic and technical philosophy. Werkmeister freely acknowledges his debt to Blanshard; yet his work differs in scope from the latter's in at least two (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. Particularist semantic normativity.Terry Horgan & Matjaž Potrč - 2006 - Acta Analytica 21 (1):45-61.
    We sketch the view we call contextual semantics. It asserts that truth is semantically correct affirmability under contextually variable semantic standards, that truth is frequently an indirect form of correspondence between thought/language and the world, and that many Quinean commitments are not genuine ontological commitments. We argue that contextualist semantics fits very naturally with the view that the pertinent semantic standards are particularist rather than being systematizable as exceptionless general principles.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  22
    Gresham's Law, Conceptual Semantics, and Semiotics of Authoritarianism: Do “Bad” Concepts Drive Out “Good” Ones? [REVIEW]Kirill Postoutenko - 2014 - Contributions to the History of Concepts 9 (1):1-23.
    The aim of this article is to explore to what extent the rule of economics commonly known as Gresham's law can be extrapolated to verbal language . Consequently, the goal of this article is twofold. First, for Gresham's law to be applied simultaneously to money and language, its unfortunate and obscure wording should be clarified. Second, one should identify the contexts in which the validity of the law could be assessed best, and run a very preliminary test. For this purpose, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  79
    Positivism and interpreting legal content: Does law call for a moral semantics?Kenneth Einar Himma - 2009 - Ratio Juris 22 (1):24-43.
    In two fascinating papers, Jules Coleman has been considering an idea, first articulated and defended by Scott Shapiro in his forthcoming book Legality , that law calls for a moral semantics. In a recent paper, Coleman argues it is a conceptual truth that legal content stating behavioral requirements, whether construed as propositions or imperatives, can "truthfully be redescribed as expressing a moral directive or authorization" ( Coleman 2007 , 592). For example, the directive "mail fraud is illegal" expresses , (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  17
    Modeling law search as prediction.Faraz Dadgostari, Mauricio Guim, Peter A. Beling, Michael A. Livermore & Daniel N. Rockmore - 2020 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 29 (1):3-34.
    Law search is fundamental to legal reasoning and its articulation is an important challenge and open problem in the ongoing efforts to investigate legal reasoning as a formal process. This Article formulates a mathematical model that frames the behavioral and cognitive framework of law search as a sequential decision process. The model has two components: first, a model of the legal corpus as a search space and second, a model of the search process that is compatible with that environment. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  13
    Zipf's Law and Avoidance of Excessive Synonymy.Dmitrii Y. Manin - 2008 - Cognitive Science 32 (7):1075-1098.
    Zipf's law states that if words of language are ranked in the order of decreasing frequency in texts, the frequency of a word is inversely proportional to its rank. It is very reliably observed in the data, but to date it escaped satisfactory theoretical explanation. This article suggests that Zipf's law may result from a hierarchical organization of word meanings over the semantic space, which in turn is generated by the evolution of word semantics dominated by expansion of meanings (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  40.  35
    From semantics to semiotics.Ekaterina Velmezova - 2011 - Sign Systems Studies 39 (1):224-234.
    The paper focuses on a particular episode in the (pre)history of semiotics in the USSR in the 1920s–1930s. At that time, an attempt to create an “integral” science was made by linguists, among whom N. Ja. Marr was one of the best-known. Several semantic laws formulated by Marr could be either reformulated in order to be applied to other disciplines (literary studies, anthropology, archeology, biology) or “proved” by the facts or discoveries drawn from them. Another “proof” that these linguistic theories (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. The Law of Non-Contradiction as a Metaphysical Principle.Tuomas E. Tahko - 2009 - Australasian Journal of Logic 7:32-47.
    The goals of this paper are two-fold: I wish to clarify the Aristotelian conception of the law of non-contradiction as a metaphysical rather than a semantic or logical principle, and to defend the truth of the principle in this sense. First I will explain what it in fact means that the law of non-contradiction is a metaphysical principle. The core idea is that the law of non-contradiction is a general principle derived from how things are in the world. For example, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  42.  49
    The Law of Excluded Middle and the Problem of Idealism.Marian Przełecki - 1982 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 18 (1):1-16.
    The law of excluded middle is usually considered as intrinsically connected with the realistic standpoint and incompatible with the idealistic position. This is just what Ajdukiewicz claims in his critique of transcendental idealism. The analysis of Ajdukiewicz's argumentation raises the problem of validity of the law of excluded middle for vague (or incomplete) languages. The problem is being solved by differentiating between the logical (or ontological) and the metalogical (or semantical) law of excluded middle: in contrast to the former, the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  89
    The semantic approach to evolutionary theory.Marc Ereshefsky - 1991 - Biology and Philosophy 6 (1):59-80.
    Paul Thompson, John Beatty, and Elisabeth Lloyd argue that attempts to resolve certain conceptual issues within evolutionary biology have failed because of a general adherence to the received view of scientific theories. They maintain that such issues can be clarified and resolved when one adopts a semantic approach to theories. In this paper, I argue that such conceptual issues are just as problematic on a semantic approach. Such issues arise from the complexity involved in providing formal accounts of theoretical laws (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  44. Psychological laws and nonmonotonic logic.Arnold Silverberg - 1996 - Erkenntnis 44 (2):199-224.
    In this essay I enter into a recently published debate between Stephen Schiffer and Jerry Fodor concerning whether adequate sense can be made of the ceteris paribus conditions in special science laws, much of their focus being on the case of putative psychological laws. Schiffer argues that adequate sense cannot be made of ceteris paribus clauses, while Fodor attempts to overcome Schiffer's arguments, in defense of special science laws. More recently, Peter Mott has attempted to show that Fodor's response to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  45. Law-Abiding Causal Decision Theory.Timothy Luke Williamson & Alexander Sandgren - 2023 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 74 (4):899-920.
    In this paper we discuss how Causal Decision Theory should be modified to handle a class of problematic cases involving deterministic laws. Causal Decision Theory, as it stands, is problematically biased against your endorsing deterministic propositions (for example it tells you to deny Newtonian physics, regardless of how confident you are of its truth). Our response is that this is not a problem for Causal Decision Theory per se, but arises because of the standard method for assessing the truth of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46.  56
    Semantic descent.Joan Weiner - 2005 - Mind 114 (454):321-354.
    Does Frege have a metatheory for his logic? There is an obvious and uncontroversial sense in which he does. Frege introduces and discusses his new logic in natural language; he argues, in response to criticisms of Begriffsschrift, that his logic is superior to Boole's by discussing formal features of both systems. In so far as the enterprise of using natural language to introduce, discuss, and argue about features of a formal system is metatheoretic, there can be no doubt: Frege has (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  47. Law, language, and legal determinacy.Brian Bix - 1993 - New York: Oxford University Press.
  48.  74
    Law, fact and legal language.Lech Morawski - 1999 - Law and Philosophy 18 (5):461-473.
    This paper discusses the difference between the factual and the legal, both as to terms and as to statements, on the analogy of the methodologists' distinction of the observational and the theoretical. No absolute distinction exists, and pure `brute facts' do not exist in law because of the socialisation of physical world and juridification of the social world.; also, the effect of evidentiary constraints. Law/fact distinction depends on `applicability rules'. The problem of `mixed terms' is partly a matter of judicial (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  23
    Harlequin semantics.Michael Johnson - unknown
    This dissertation is about Semantic Uniformity. Semantic Uniformity is the claim that what is true for some expressions is true for them all—at least, when it comes to semantics. In particular, I defend three claims in three chapters, in this order: First, all simple linguistic expressions, and not just some, are non-descriptive. That is, their referents are not determined by fit with our beliefs. Second, all simple linguistic expressions are rigid. Relative to each possible world, construed as a world (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  9
    Review of Law and the semantic web: Legal ontologies, methodologies, legal information retrieval, and applications lecture notes in AI by Benjamins, R., Casanovas, P., Gangemi, A., Selic, B., Springer, Berlin, 2005. [REVIEW]Heiner Reviewer-Stuckenschmidt - 2006 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 14 (1).
1 — 50 / 810