Results for 'artist's intention'

994 found
Order:
  1. The Artist's Intention.William H. Capitan - 1964 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 18 (68/69):323-34.
  2.  39
    The Artist's Intention and G.E.M. Anscombe's Intention.Catherine D. Rau - 1973 - NTU Philosophical Review 3:25-34.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  43
    The Artist's Intentions.Sidney Gendin - 1964 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 23 (2):193-196.
  4.  20
    Aesthetics and the artist's "intention".Lincoln Rothschild - 1979 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 38 (2):190-192.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  84
    The relevance of the artist's intentions.Huw Morris Jones - 1964 - British Journal of Aesthetics 4 (2):138-145.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Hospers on the Artist's Intentions.Mary Sirridge - 1988 - Reason Papers 13:143-151.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Irony and the artist's intentions.Daniel O. Nathan - 1982 - British Journal of Aesthetics 22 (3):245-256.
  8.  80
    The work of art and the artist's intentions.John Kemp - 1964 - British Journal of Aesthetics 4 (2):146-154.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9. The Logic of Our Talk About the Artist's Intention.Ranjan Ghosh - 1987 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 14 (3):287.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. The Artist's Sanction in Contemporary Art.Sherri Irvin - 2005 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (4):315-326.
    I argue that contemporary artists fix the features of their works not only through their actions of making and presenting objects, but also through auxiliary activities such as corresponding with curators and institutions. I refer to such fixing of features as the artist’s sanction: artists sanction features of their work through publicly accessible actions and communications, such as making a physical object with particular features, corresponding with curators and producing artist statements. I show, through an extended example, that in order (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  11.  23
    Work and Object: The Artist's Sanction in Contemporary Art.Sherri Irvin - 2003 - Dissertation, Princeton University
    Is an artwork simply identical to some physical object? While clearly not viable for art forms like literature and music, the view that artworks are physical objects is appealing for the singular visual arts , since it accords with our intuitions about the nature of visual artworks. A traditional challenge to the view holds that physical objects cannot possess representational properties, and thus visual artworks, most of which do have such properties, cannot be identical to physical objects. -/- In chapter (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  40
    The Artist's Study of Nature and its Relationship to Goethean Science.Daan Hoekstra - 2007 - Janus Head 10 (1):329-349.
    Poet and playwright Johann Wolfgang von Goethe’s scientific studies grew out of a disenchantment with the reductionist science of his time. He believed a more accurate description of nature was possible. Goethe’s scientific method paralleled the methodology of art current in his era, and very likely arose, at least in part, from pre-existing traditions of knowledge in the visual arts. The study of similarities between Goethe’s scientific method and the methodology of art could provide insights into both disciplines, and insights (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Defending 'the Artist's Theory': Wollheim's Lost Idea Regained?Graham McFee - 2010 - Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 47 (1):3-26.
    The paper considers an argument of Richard Wollheim’s, originally presented in a 1976 symposium with Goodman and Wiggins, which disappeared when the symposium contribution was ‘reprinted’ in the supplementary essays to the expanded edition of Art and Its Objects (Wollheim, 1980). It lays out the argument’s original context, locating its objectives by means of a comparison with Goodman’s autographic/allographic distinction, with its attendant discussion of the ‘history of production’, and presents Wollheim’s defence of ‘the artist’s theory’. This defence coheres in (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  45
    Heidegger and the objectivity of aesthetic truth.William S. Hamrick - 1971 - Journal of Value Inquiry 5 (2):120-130.
    Heidegger's totally objective view of aesthetic truth, That the meaning of aesthetic experience is revealed only in and through the art-Object, Fails to appreciate the contributions of subjectivity to that meaningfulness. This is shown by pointing out that interpretation of an artwork can be relevant for our aesthetic appreciation and that sometimes subjective factors such as the artist's intentions, And the viewer's personal, Cultural background, Are relevant to interpretation.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  31
    In Defence of Moderate Actual Intentionalism.Frederick Hulbert - 2021 - Aesthetic Investigations 4 (2):236-253.
    The extent to which the artist’s intentions are a relevant consideration in the interpretation of art has long been the subject of critical debate. First, I outline the various philosophical positions which have been established, specifically focusing on the debate between hypothetical intentionalism and moderate actual intentionalism. Then I look at some previous test cases which have, as yet, failed to demonstrate a decisive victory for either side. Finally, I offer two new test cases, one from the field of contemporary (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  40
    Art and Intention.Paisley Nathan Livingston - 2005 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 68 (2):414-415.
    In aesthetics, the topic of intentions comes up most often in the perennial debate between intentionalists and anti-intentionalists over standards of interpretation. The underlying assumptions about the nature and functions of intentions are, however, rarely explicitly developed, even though divergent and at times tendentious premises are often relied upon in this controversy. Livingston provides a survey of contentions about the nature and status of intentions and intentionalist psychology more generally, arguing for an account that recognizes the multiple functions fulfilled by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  17. Intention, Interpretation and Contemporary Visual Art.Hans Maes - 2010 - British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (2):121-138.
    The role of the artist's intention in the interpretation of art has been the topic of a lively and ongoing discussion in analytic aesthetics. First, I sketch the current state of this debate, focusing especially on two competing views: actual and hypothetical intentionalism. Secondly, I discuss the search for a suitable test case, that is, a work of art that is interpreted differently by actual and hypothetical intentionalists, with only one of these interpretations being plausible. Many examples from (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  43
    Who made the paintings: Artists or artificial intelligence? The effects of identity on liking and purchase intention.Li Gu & Yong Li - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Investigating how people respond to and view AI-created artworks is becoming increasingly crucial as the technology’s current application spreads due to its affordability and accessibility. This study examined how AI art alters people’s evaluation, purchase intention, and collection intention toward Chinese-style and Western-style paintings, and whether art expertise plays a role. Study 1 recruited participants without professional art experience and found that those who made the paintings would not change their liking rating, purchase intention, and collection (...). In addition, they showed ingroup preference, favoring Chinese-style relative to Western-style paintings, in line with previous evidence on cultural preference in empirical aesthetics. Study 2 further investigated the modulation effect of art expertise. Art experts evaluated less favorably AI-generated paintings relative to artist-made paintings, while non-experts showed no preference. There was also an interaction effect between the author and the art expertise and interaction between the painting style and the art expertise. Collectively, the findings in this study showed that who made the art matters for experts and that the painting style affects aesthetic evaluation and ultimate reception of it. These results would also provide implications for AI-art practitioners. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  1
    The Analytic of the Emotions I.P. M. S. Hacker - 1976 - In Robert C. Solomon (ed.), The passions. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press. pp. 37–59.
    The emotions distinctive of human beings, as opposed to other animals, are emotions that presuppose possession of a language and hence powers of intellect and rational will. The objects distinctive of human emotions presuppose mastery of a language and possession of rational abilities. Music itself has been considered to be the purest artistic expression of human emotions and of the striving of the human will. The emotions, in particular temporary emotions, have characteristic multiple associations, manifestations, and forms of expression. This (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  11
    Intentional Fallacy.Nicolas Michaud - 2018-05-09 - In Robert Arp, Steven Barbone & Michael Bruce (eds.), Bad Arguments. Wiley. pp. 357–359.
    This chapter focuses on one of the common fallacies in Western philosophy, 'intentional fallacy (IF)'. The IF is an odd kind of fallacy. Rather than being a fallacy focused on logic and argumentation, it is a fallacy that focuses on art, relating to how we judge art and engage in literary criticism. The IF focuses on the fact that we often think that there is one right interpretation of a work of art. According to David Fenner, the IF “states that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  32
    Art and Intention: A Philosophical Study.Paisley Nathan Livingston - 2005 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65 (3):299-305.
    In aesthetics, the topic of intentions comes up most often in the perennial debate between intentionalists and anti-intentionalists over standards of interpretation. The underlying assumptions about the nature and functions of intentions are, however, rarely explicitly developed, even though divergent and at times tendentious premises are often relied upon in this controversy. Livingston provides a survey of contentions about the nature and status of intentions and intentionalist psychology more generally, arguing for an account that recognizes the multiple functions fulfilled by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  22.  41
    Interpretation and Intention: The Debate between Hypothetical and Actual Intentionalism.Noël Carroll - 2000 - Metaphilosophy 31 (1-2):75-95.
    Regarded for decades as a fallacy, intentionalist interpretation is beginning to attract a following among philosophers of art. Intentionalism is the doctrine that the actual intentions of artists are relevant to the interpretation of the artworks they create – just as actual intentions are relevant to the interpretation of the everyday words and deeds of other people. Although there are several forms of actual intentionalism, I defend the form known as modest actual intentionalism, which holds that the correct interpretation of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  23.  36
    Distinguishing intention and function in art appreciation.Glenn Parsons & Allen Carlson - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (2):153 - 154.
    We applaud Bullot and Reber's attempt to encompass the function of artworks within their psycho-historical model of art appreciation. However, we suggest that in order to fully realize this aim, they require a clearer distinction between an artist's intentions toward an artwork and its proper functions. We also show how such a distinction improves the internal coherence of their model.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Interpretation and Intention: The Debate between Hypothetical and Actual Intentionalism.NoËl Carroll - 2000 - Metaphilosophy 31 (1&2):75-95.
    Regarded for decades as a fallacy, intentionalist interpretation is beginning to attract a following among philosophers of art. Intentionalism is the doctrine that the actual intentions of artists are relevant to the interpretation of the artworks they create – just as actual intentions are relevant to the interpretation of the everyday words and deeds of other people. Although there are several forms of actual intentionalism, I defend the form known as modest actual intentionalism, which holds that the correct interpretation of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  25. The ethical implications of the intentional fallacy: How we ought to address the art of immoral artists.Rosanna Sparacino - 2019 - Stance 12 (1):23-31.
    I argue that biographical information is akin to other non-aesthetic, social, historical, or political information. As such, artist’s biographies are always relevant and important when interpreting art. While the meaning and value of a piece of art is not determined by any single piece of contextual information, neither is its meaning and value ever entirely separated from context. In some cases, however, a piece of art that is technically magnificent may be experienced as repugnant when the artist has committed egregious (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Failures of Intention and Failed-Art.Michel-Antoine Xhignesse - 2020 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 50 (7):905-917.
    This paper explores what happens when artists fail to execute their goals. I argue that taxonomies of failure in general, and of failed-art in particular, should focus on the attempts which generate the failed-entity, and that to do this they must be sensitive to an attempt’s orientation. This account of failed-attempts delivers three important new insights into artistic practice: there can be no accidental art, only deliberate and incidental art; art’s intention-dependence entails the possibility of performative failure, but not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  27. Art and intention: a philosophical study.Paisley Livingston - 2005 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In Art and intention Paisley Livingston develops a broad and balanced perspective on perennial disputes between intentionalists and anti-intentionalists in philosophical aesthetics and critical theory. He surveys and assesses a wide range of rival assumptions about the nature of intentions and the status of intentionalist psychology. With detailed reference to examples from diverse media, art forms, and traditions, he demonstrates that insights into the multiple functions of intentions have important implications for our understanding of artistic creation and authorship, the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  28.  62
    The artistic design stance and the interpretation of Paleolithic art.Johan De Smedt & Helen De Cruz - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (2):139-140.
    The artistic design stance is an important part of art appreciation, but it remains unclear how it can be applied to artworks for which art historical context is no longer available, such as Ice Age art. We propose that some of the designer's intentions can be gathered noninferentially through direct experience with prehistoric artworks.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  36
    Artist-Audience Communication: Tolstoy Reclaimed.Saam Trivedi - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 38 (2):38.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Journal of Aesthetic Education 38.2 (2004) 38-52 [Access article in PDF] Artist-Audience Communication: Tolstoy Reclaimed Saam Trivedi Whoever is really conversant with art recognizes in [Tolstoy's What is Art?] the voice of the master.1There has to be some presumption that, as one of the greatest artists who ever lived, Tolstoy might actually have known what he was talking about.2It is widely accepted in contemporary Anglo-American aesthetics that, despite (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  29
    Cognitive Constraints on the Visual Arts: An Empirical Study of the Role of Perceived Intentions in Appreciation Judgements.Jean-Luc Jucker & Justin L. Barrett - 2011 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 11 (1-2):115-136.
    What influences people’s appreciation of works of art? In this paper, we provide a new cognitive approach to this big question, and the first empirical results in support of it. As a work of art typically does not activate intuitive cognition for functional artefacts, it is represented as an instance of non-verbal symbolic communication. By application of Sperber and Wilson’s Relevance Theory of communication, we hypothesize that understanding the artist’s intention plays a crucial role in intuitive art appreciation judgements. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  15
    Art Subjects: Making Artists in the American University (review).Theodore Gracyk - 2005 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 39 (1):119-122.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Art Subjects: Making Artists in the American UniversityTheodore GracykArt Subjects: Making Artists in the American University, by Howard Singerman. Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press, 1999, 296 pp., $19.95 paper.Howard Singerman's Art Subjects is a study of the training of visual artists in American universities from 1912 to the present. More precisely, the book is an account of how two philosophies ofeducation have competed to inform (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  56
    Aesthetic meanings and aesthetic emotions: How historical and intentional knowledge expand aesthetic experience.Paul J. Silvia - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (2):157-158.
    This comment proposes that Bullot & Reber's (B&R's) emphasis on historical and intentional knowledge expands the range of emotions that can be properly viewed as aesthetic states. Many feelings, such as anger, contempt, shame, confusion, and pride, come about through complex aesthetic meanings, which integrate conceptual knowledge, beliefs about the work and the artist's intentions, and the perceiver's goals and values.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Arthur Danto’s Andy Warhol: the Embodiment of Theory in Art and the Pragmatic Turn.Stephen Snyder - forthcoming - Leitmotiv:135-151.
    Arthur Danto’s recent book, Andy Warhol, leads the reader through the story of the iconic American’s artistic life highlighted by a philosophical commentary, a commentary that merges Danto’s aesthetic theory with the artist himself. Inspired by Warhol’s Brillo Box installation, art that in Danto’s eyes was indiscernible from the everyday boxes it represented, Danto developed a theory that is able to differentiate art from non-art by employing the body of conceptual art theory manifest in what he termed the ‘artworld’. The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Interpreting AI-Generated Art: Arthur Danto’s Perspective on Intention, Authorship, and Creative Traditions in the Age of Artificial Intelligence.Raquel Cascales - 2023 - Polish Journal of Aesthetics 71 (4):17-29.
    Arthur C. Danto did not live to witness the proliferation of AI in artistic creation. However, his philosophy of art offers key ideas about art that can provide an interesting perspective on artwork generated by artificial intelligence (AI). In this article, I analyze how his ideas about contemporary art, intention, interpretation, and authorship could be applied to the ongoing debate about AI and artistic creation. At the same time, it is also interesting to consider whether the incorporation of AI (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  13
    Creative Agency as Executive Agency: Grounding the Artistic Significance of Automatic Images.Claire Anscomb - 2021 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 79 (4):415-427.
    This article examines the artistic potential of forms of image-making that involve registering the features of real objects using mind-independent processes. According to skeptics, these processes limit an agent’s intentional control over the features of the resultant “automatic images,” which in turn limits the artistic potential of the work, and the form as a whole. I argue that this is true only if intentional control is understood to mean that an agent produces the features of the work by their own (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36. Gender Ideology and the “Artistic” Fabrication of Human Sex: Nature as Norm or the Remaking of the Human?Michele M. Schumacher - 2016 - The Thomist 80 (3):363-423.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Gender Ideology and the “Artistic” Fabrication of Human Sex: Nature as Norm or the Remaking of the Human?Michele M. SchumacherUntil quite recently,” the famous English novelist C. S. Lewis remarked in 1959, “it was taken for granted that the business of the artist was to delight and instruct his public”: that is to say, to address simultaneously their passions and their intellects. “There were, of course, different publics.... And (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  58
    History and Intentions in the Experience of Artworks.Alessandro Pignocchi - 2014 - Topoi 33 (2):477-486.
    The role of personal background knowledge—in particular knowledge about the context of production of an artwork—has been only marginally taken into account in cognitive approaches to art. Addressing this issue is crucial to enhancing these approaches’ explanatory power and framing their collaboration with the humanities (Bullot and Reber 2012). This paper sketches a model of the experience of artworks based on the mechanisms of intention attribution, and shows how this model makes it possible to address the issue of personal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  17
    Intention, description and the aesthetic: the by-product argument.Leon Culbertson - 2016 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 43 (3):440-453.
    Stephen Mumford argues that positive aesthetic value is a by-product of both sport and art, and that the principal aim of the artist and the player or athlete could not be to produce positive aesthetic value. Three features of Mumford’s by-product argument are considered. It is argued that problems arise as a result of failure to appreciate Best’s distinction between the evaluative and conceptual uses of ‘aesthetic’, the nature of the descriptions Mumford gives of the intention of the artist (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  12
    Lucky artists.Christopher Prodoehl - forthcoming - Analytic Philosophy.
    Imagine an artist creating new work, a painter applying paint to canvas with a brush, for example. Assuming she acts intentionally, is she responsible for the work she creates? Is she responsible, in particular, for whatever value her finished work has? In the first part of the paper, I formulate an argument for the claim she is not; I call this the Luck Argument. According to that argument, an important aspect of the work's value is due to luck, so not (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  23
    L’Artiste et L’Adversité.Anna Caterina Dalmasso - 2015 - Chiasmi International 17:201-224.
    Résumé -/- Anna Caterina Dalmasso L’artiste et l’adversité. Hasard et création chez Merleau-Ponty -/- À plusieurs reprises, Merleau-Ponty tisse une correspondance entre art et histoire, entre pratique artistique et action politique : plus précisément il nous invite à former le concept d’histoire sur l’exemple de l’art. À première vue, un tel rapprochement pourrait paraître abstrait, sinon provocateur, l’art étant souvent conçu comme un domaine qui semble avoir peu à faire avec l’espace de l’action. Mais, nous pouvons aujourd’hui comprendre davantage l’intérêt (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Intentional mind-wandering as intentional omission: the surrealist method.Santiago Arango-Muñoz & Juan Pablo Bermúdez - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):7727-7748.
    Mind-wandering seems to be paradigmatically unintentional. However, experimental findings have yielded the paradoxical result that mind-wandering can also be intentional. In this paper, we first present the paradox of intentional mind-wandering and then explain intentional mind-wandering as the intentional omission to control one’s own thoughts. Finally, we present the surrealist method for artistic production to illustrate how intentional omission of control over thoughts can be deployed towards creative endeavors.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42. Artists Draw A Blank.Tim Gilman - 2011 - Continent 1 (3):208-212.
    continent. 1.3 (2011): 208-212. … intervals of destructuring paradoxically carry the momentum for the ongoing process by which thought and perception are brought into relation toward transformative action. —Brian Massumi, Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation 1 Facing a blank canvas or blank page is a moment of pure potential, one that can be enervating or paralyzing. It causes a pause, a hesitation, in anticipation of the moment of inception—even of one that never comes. The implication is that the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. A fallacy in the intentional fallacy.James Downey - 2007 - Philosophy and Literature 31 (1):149-152.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:A Fallacy in the Intentional FallacyJames DowneyAccording to a famous argument by W. K. Wimsatt and Monroe Beardsley, the intention of the author is neither available nor desirable as a standard by which to judge the success of a work of literary art. I wish to focus on the former allegation. The author's intention is not available as a standard by which to judge a work's success, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  18
    Motion, Emotion, and Love: The Nature of Artistic Performance.Thomas Carson Mark - 2012 - Gia Publications.
    Dynamically transforming the elements of any performing artist’s craft, this practical guide is a must-have for musicians, dancers, and actors. The handbook shows how artistic performance is embodied in the unification of three critical elements—motion, emotion, and love—demonstrating how it offers experiences and opportunities distinct from the nonperforming arts. Step-by-step guidelines are provided for building intentional and inspirational practice time, thereby enhancing the relationships between the source, the performer, and the audience. Illustrating how intentional movement invokes emotions from both the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Attempting art: an essay on intention-dependence.Michel-Antoine Xhignesse - 2017 - Dissertation, Mcgill University
    Attempting art: an essay on intention-dependenceIt is a truism among philosophers that art is intention-dependent—that is to say, art-making is an activity that depends in some way on the maker's intentions. Not much thought has been given to just what this entails, however. For instance, most philosophers of art assume that intention-dependence entails concept-dependence—i.e. possessing a concept of art is necessary for art-making, so that what prospective artists must intend is to make art. And yet, a mounting (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  41
    On art and intention.Steven Farrelly-Jackson - 1997 - Heythrop Journal 38 (2):172–179.
    The author discusses a puzzle about the place of intention in art, a puzzle first articulated by Richard Wollheim in his well‐known lecture ‘On Drawing an Object’. The puzzle arises if we try to hold jointly three commonly‐held claims, viz. Art is intentional; The artist, in making a work of art, needs to observe what he has done, in order to know what he has done; A necessary condition of intentional action is that when an agent acts intentionally then (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  32
    The artistic failure of.Hugh Mercer Curtler - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 38 (1):1-11.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Journal of Aesthetic Education 38.1 (2004) 1-11 [Access article in PDF] The Artistic Failure of Crime and Punishment Crime and Punishment Hugh Mercer Curtler This essay begins by noting some fundamental differences between poets, in the broad sense of that term, and philosophers, or those who reflect discursively. It then moves to an examination of the epilogue to Crime and Punishment where Dostoevsky abandons poetry in order to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  17
    The artistic failure of crime and punishment.Hugh Mercer Curtler - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 38 (1):1-11.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Journal of Aesthetic Education 38.1 (2004) 1-11 [Access article in PDF] The Artistic Failure of Crime and Punishment Crime and Punishment Hugh Mercer Curtler This essay begins by noting some fundamental differences between poets, in the broad sense of that term, and philosophers, or those who reflect discursively. It then moves to an examination of the epilogue to Crime and Punishment where Dostoevsky abandons poetry in order to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  10
    The Artistic Failure of Crime and Punishment.Hugh Mercer Curtler - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 38 (1):1.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Journal of Aesthetic Education 38.1 (2004) 1-11 [Access article in PDF] The Artistic Failure of Crime and Punishment Crime and Punishment Hugh Mercer Curtler This essay begins by noting some fundamental differences between poets, in the broad sense of that term, and philosophers, or those who reflect discursively. It then moves to an examination of the epilogue to Crime and Punishment where Dostoevsky abandons poetry in order to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  5
    On Art and Intention.Steven Farrelly-Jackson - 1997 - Heythrop Journal 38 (2):172-179.
    The author discusses a puzzle about the place of intention in art, a puzzle first articulated by Richard Wollheim in his well‐known lecture ‘On Drawing an Object’. The puzzle arises if we try to hold jointly three commonly‐held claims, viz. (1) Art is intentional; (2) The artist, in making a work of art, needs to observe what he has done, in order to know what he has done; (3) A necessary condition of intentional action is that when an agent (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 994