Results for 'parenthetical verbs'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Parenthetical verbs.J. O. Urmson - 1952 - Mind 61 (244):480-496.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  2.  8
    Parenthetical Verbs.J. O. Urmson - 1952 - [Basil Blackwell].
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  3.  48
    The parenthetical use of the verb 'believe'.M. J. Charlesworth - 1965 - Mind 74 (295):415-420.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Observations on embedding verbs, evidentiality, and presupposition.Mandy Simons - 2007
    This paper discusses the semantically parenthetical use of clauseembedding verbs such as see, hear, think, believe, discover and know. When embedding verbs are used in this way, the embedded clause carries the main point of the utterance, while the main clause serves some discourse function. Frequently, this function is evidential, with the parenthetical verb carrying information about the source and reliability of the embedded claim, or about the speaker’s emotional orientation to it. Other functions of (...) uses of verbs are discussed. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  5. On double access, cessation and parentheticality.Daniel Altshuler, Valentine Hacquard, Thomas Roberts & Aaron Steven White - 2015 - In S. D'Antonio, M. Wiegand, M. Moroney & C. Little (eds.), Proceedings of SALT 25. pp. 18-37.
    Arguably the biggest challenge in analyzing English tense is to account for the double access interpretation, which arises when a present tensed verb is embedded under a past attitude—e.g., "John said that Mary is pregnant". Present-under-past does not always result in a felicitous utterance, however—cf. "John believed that Mary is pregnant". While such oddity has been noted, the contrast has never been explained. In fact, English grammars and manuals generally prohibit present-under-past. Work on double access, on the other hand, has (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Chungmin Lee.Verbs Of Change - 1973 - Foundations of Language 9:384.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  81
    From A Rational Point Of View.Tim Henning - 2018 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    When we discuss normative reasons, oughts, requirements of rationality, hypothetical imperatives (or “anankastic conditionals”), motivating reasons and so on, we often use verbs like “believe” and “want” to capture a relevant subject’s perspective. According to the received view about sentences involving these verbs, what they do is describe the subject’s mental states. Many puzzles concerning normative discourse have to do with the role that mental states consequently appear to play in this discourse. This book uses tools from formal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8. Joachim ballweg and Helmut frosch.Non-Stative Verbs - 1981 - In Hans-Jürgen Eikmeyer & Hannes Rieser (eds.), Words, Worlds, and Contexts: New Approaches in Word Semantics. W. De Gruyter. pp. 6--210.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  8
    Multiculturalism and the possibility of transcultural educational and philosophical ideals, Harvey Siegel.Verbs Names - 1999 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (2).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Identificacion de requisitos: Un enfoque basado en taxonomia verbal.on A. Verb TaxOnomy & Ricardo A. Gacitúa - 2001 - Theoria 10:67-78.
  11. Je Miller.Stative Verbs In Russian - forthcoming - Foundations of Language.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Eve V. Clark.Negative Verbs in Children'S. Speech - 1981 - In W. Klein & W. Levelt (eds.), Crossing the Boundaries in Linguistics. Reidel. pp. 253.
  13. En guise de conclusion: Catégories et sous-catégories du verbe espagnol.Et Sous-Catégories du Verbe Espagnol - 2008 - In Frank Alvarez-Pereyre (ed.), Catégories et catégorisation: une perspective interdisciplinaire. Dudley, MA: Peeters. pp. 141.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  23
    Friends, Lovers or Nothing: Men and Women Differ in Their Perceptions of Sex Robots and Platonic Love Robots.Morten Nordmo, Julie Øverbø Næss, Marte Folkestad Husøy & Mads Nordmo Arnestad - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Physical and emotional intimacy between humans and robots may become commonplace over the next decades, as technology improves at a rapid rate. This development provides new questions pertaining to how people perceive robots designed for different kinds of intimacy, both as companions and potentially as competitors. We performed an randomized experiment where participants read of either a robot that could only perform sexual acts, or only engage in non-sexual platonic love relationships. The results of the current study show that females (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15. Representing knowledge.Peter van Elswyk - 2021 - The Philosophical Review 130 (1):97-143.
    A speaker's use of a declarative sentence in a context has two effects: it expresses a proposition and represents the speaker as knowing that proposition. This essay is about how to explain the second effect. The standard explanation is act-based. A speaker is represented as knowing because their use of the declarative in a context tokens the act-type of assertion and assertions represent knowledge in what's asserted. I propose a semantic explanation on which declaratives covertly host a "know"-parenthetical. A (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  16.  58
    Un/qualified declaratives.Peter van Elswyk - 2018 - Dissertation, Rutgers University, New Brunswick
    Declarative sentences in English are either unqualified or qualified with an epistemic expression like a parenthetical verb. In this dissertation, I defend parentheticalism, the view that most apparently unqualified declaratives in English covertly contain the verb "know" with a first-person subject in parenthetical position. Paired with a multidimensional semantics for parenthetical verbs, parentheticalism predicts that the use of an apparently unqualified declarative represents the speaker as knowing the at-issue proposition expressed by the declarative in the context. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Assertion, belief, and ‘I believe’-guarded affirmation.Anders Nes - 2016 - Linguistics and Philosophy 39 (1):57-86.
    According to a widely held view of assertion and belief, they are each governed by a tacitly acknowledged epistemic norm, and the norm on assertion and norm on belief are so related that believing p is epistemically permissible only if asserting it is. I call it the Same Norm View. A very common type of utterance raises a puzzle for this view, viz. utterances in which we say ‘I believe p' to convey somehow guarded affirmation of the proposition that p. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18. On the autonomy of linguistic meaning.Mitchell S. Green - 1997 - Mind 106 (422):217-243.
    Frege and many following him, such as Dummett, Geach, Stenius and Hare, have envisaged a role for illocutionary force indicators in a logically perpspicuous notation. Davidson has denied that such expressions are even possible on the ground that any putative force indicator would be used by actors and jokers to heighten the drama of their performances. Davidson infers from this objection a Thesis of the Autonomy of Linguistic Meaning: symbolic representation necessarily breaks any close tie with extra-linguistic purpose. A modified (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  19. In the Middle.Catherine Brown - 2000 - Journal of Medieval and Early Modern Studies 30:547-574.
    Things do not begin to live except in the middle.--Gilles Deleuze, DialoguesA Land of UnlikenessThe English novel The Go-Between begins a tale of memory and loss with two sentences a historian could love: "The past is a foreign country. They do things differently there." The novel's narrator should know: he is a librarian, someone who, as the memory ghost of his twelve-year-old self will remind him, spends his days cataloguing the relics of the book-past. And many who now live with (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Embedding Speech Acts.Manfred Krifka - unknown
    Speech acts have sometimes been considered as unembeddable, for principled reasons. In this paper, I argue that speech acts can be embedded under certain circumstances. In particular, I consider denegation and conjunction of speech acts, quantification into speech acts, conditionalization of speech acts, the embedding of speech acts by verbs like say and wonder, speechact-modifying adverbials like frankly, clauses commenting on speech acts, like certain uses of because-clauses, parentheticals, and appositive relative clauses. A crucial distinction is made between speech (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  21.  35
    Parentheticality, assertion strength, and polarity.Todor Koev - 2019 - Linguistics and Philosophy 44 (1):113-140.
    Sentences with slifting parentheticals The formal analysis of natural language, Mouton, The Hague, 1973) grammaticalize an intriguing interaction between truth-conditional meaning and speech act function. In such sentences, the assertion strength of the slifted clause is modulated by the parenthetical, which provides evidential support :480–496, 1952; Asher in J Semant 17:31–50, 2000; Rooryck in Glot Int 5:125–133, 2001; Jayez and Rossari in: Corblin, de Swart Handbook of French semantics, CSLI, Stanford, 2004; Davis et al. in Proc Semant Linguist Theory (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22. Semantic Verbs Are Intensional Transitives.Justin D’Ambrosio - 2019 - Mind 128 (509):213-248.
    In this paper I show that we have strong empirical and theoretical reasons to treat the verbs we use in our semantic theorizing—particularly ‘refers to ’, ‘applies to ’, and ‘is true of ’—as intensional transitive verbs. Stating our semantic theories with intensional vocabulary allows us to partially reconcile two competing approaches to the nature and subject-matter of semantics: the Chomskian approach, on which semantics is non-relational, internalistic, and concerns the psychology of language users, and the Lewisian approach, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23. Parenthetical hedged performatives$.Stefan Schneider - 2010 - In Gunther Kaltenböck, Wiltrud Mihatsch & Stefan Schneider (eds.), New approaches to hedging. Bingley, UK: Emerald. pp. 9--267.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  15
    Parentheticals and the dialogicity of signs.Barbara Sonnenhauser - 2009 - Sign Systems Studies 37 (1/2):169-203.
    The term ‘parenthetical’ is applied to an almost unlimited range of linguistic phenomena, which share but one common feature, namely their being used parenthetically. Parenthetic use is mostly described in terms of embedding an expression into some host sentence. Actually, however, it is anything but clearwhat it means for an expression to be used parenthetically, from both a syntactic and a semantic point of view.Given that in most, if not all, cases the alleged host sentence can be considered syntactically (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  20
    Parentheticals and the dialogicity of signs.Barbara Sonnenhauser - 2009 - Sign Systems Studies 37 (1/2):169-203.
    The term ‘parenthetical’ is applied to an almost unlimited range of linguistic phenomena, which share but one common feature, namely their being used parenthetically. Parenthetic use is mostly described in terms of embedding an expression into some host sentence. Actually, however, it is anything but clearwhat it means for an expression to be used parenthetically, from both a syntactic and a semantic point of view.Given that in most, if not all, cases the alleged host sentence can be considered syntactically (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  24
    Parenthetic Doubt.Andrew Belsey - 1991 - Philosophy Now 2:45-46.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Intensional verbs and quantifiers.Friederike Moltmann - 1997 - Natural Language Semantics 5 (1):1-52.
    This paper discusses the semantics of intensional transitive verbs such as 'need', 'want','recognize', 'find', and 'hire'. It proposes new linguistic criteria for intensionality and defends two semantic analyses for two different classes of intensional verbs. The paper also includes a systematic classification of intensional verbs according to the type of lexical meaning they involve.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  28.  90
    Intensional verbs and their intentional objects.Friederike Moltmann - 2008 - Natural Language Semantics 16 (3):239-270.
    The complement of intensional transitive verbs, like any nonreferential complement, can be replaced by a ‘special quantifier’ or ‘special pronoun’ such as 'something', 'the same thing', or 'what'. In this paper, I will defend the ‘Nominalization Theory’ of special quantifiers against a range of apparent counterexamples involving intensional transitive verbs.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  29. The Verb ‘Be’ in Ancient Greek (Reprint with a New Introductory Essay).C. H. Kahn - unknown
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  30. Factive Verbs and Protagonist Projection.Wesley Buckwalter - 2014 - Episteme 11 (4):391-409.
    Nearly all philosophers agree that only true things can be known. But does this principle reflect actual patterns of ordinary usage? Several examples in ordinary language seem to show that ‘know’ is literally used non-factively. By contrast, this paper reports five experiments utilizing explicit paraphrasing tasks, which suggest that non-factive uses are actually not literal. Instead, they are better explained by a phenomenon known as protagonist projection. It is argued that armchair philosophical orthodoxy regarding the truth requirement for knowledge withstands (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  31.  16
    On verbs and time.Dorit Abusch - unknown
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  32. Attitude verbs’ local context.Kyle Blumberg & Simon Goldstein - 2022 - Linguistics and Philosophy 46 (3):483-507.
    Schlenker (Semant Pragmat 2(3):1–78, 2009; Philos Stud 151(1):115–142, 2010a; Mind 119(474):377–391, 2010b) provides an algorithm for deriving the presupposition projection properties of an expression from that expression’s classical semantics. In this paper, we consider the predictions of Schlenker’s algorithm as applied to attitude verbs. More specifically, we compare Schlenker’s theory with a prominent view which maintains that attitudes exhibit belief projection, so that presupposition triggers in their scope imply that the attitude holder believes the presupposition (Karttunen in Theor Linguist (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Verbs and times.Zeno Vendler - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (2):143-160.
  34. On verb-initial and verb-final word orders in lokaa.Mark Baker - manuscript
    Verb phrases seems to be head initial in affirmative sentences in Lokaa (a Niger-Congo language of the Cross River area of Nigeria) but head final in negative clauses and gerunds. This article aspires to give a comprehensive description of this phenomenon, together with a theoretical analysis. It considers how a full range of grammatical elements are ordered in both kinds of clauses—including direct objects, second objects, particles, weak pronouns, complement clauses, serial verbs, adverbs, prepositional phrases, tense/mood particles, and auxiliary (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. The verb "to be" in greek philosophy.Lesley Brown - 1994 - In Stephen Everson (ed.), Language. Cambridge University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  36.  69
    Names, verbs and sentences.Nicholas Denyer - 1998 - Philosophy 73 (4):619-623.
    Metaphysicians often declare that there are large ontological differences (properties versus individuals, universals versus particulars) correlated with the linguistic distinction between names and verbs. Gaskin argues against all such declarations on the grounds that we may quantify with equal ease over the referents of both types of expression. However, his argument must be wrong, given the massive differences between first- and second-order qualification. Its only grain of truth is that these differences show up only in the logic of relations, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Depictive Verbs and the Nature of Perception.Justin D'Ambrosio - manuscript
    This paper shows that direct-object perceptual verbs, such as "hear", "smell", "taste", "feel", and "see", share a collection of distinctive semantic behaviors with depictive verbs, among which are "draw'', "paint", "sketch", and "sculpt". What explains these behaviors in the case of depictives is that they are causative verbs, and have lexical decompositions that involve the creation of concrete artistic artifacts, such as pictures, paintings, and sculptures. For instance, "draw a dog" means "draw a picture of a dog", (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  95
    Small verbs, complex events: Analyticity without synonymy.Paul M. Pietroski - 2003 - In Louise M. Antony (ed.), Chomsky and His Critics. Malden Ma: Blackwell. pp. 179--214.
    This chapter contains section titled: Hidden Tautologies Minimal Syntax.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  39.  43
    Performatives and Parentheticals.Diane Blakemore - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91:197 - 213.
    Diane Blakemore; XI*—Performatives and Parentheticals, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 197–214, https://doi.org/.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40.  13
    Does verb bias modulate syntactic priming?Sarah Bernolet & Robert J. Hartsuiker - 2010 - Cognition 114 (3):455-461.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  41. Chapter 5: Intensional Transitive Verbs and their 'Objects'.Friederike Moltmann - 2013 - In Abstract Objects and the Semantics of Natural Language. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter gives a truthmaker-based account of the semantics of 'reifying' quantifiers like 'something' when they act as complements of intensional transitive verbs ('need', 'look for'). It argues that such quantifiers range over 'variable satisfiers' of the attitudinal object described by the verb (e.g. the need or the search).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  42.  26
    XI*—Performatives and Parentheticals.Diane Blakemore - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91 (1):197-214.
    Diane Blakemore; XI*—Performatives and Parentheticals, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, Pages 197–214, https://doi.org/.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  39
    Verbs and Adverbs, and Some Other Modes of Grammatical Combination.David Wiggins - 1986 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86:273 - 304.
    David Wiggins; XIV*—Verbs and Adverbs, and Some Other Modes of Grammatical Combination, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 86, Issue 1, 1 June 1986.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44. Familiar Verbs Are Not Always Easier Than Novel Verbs: How German Pre‐School Children Comprehend Active and Passive Sentences.Miriam Dittmar, Kirsten Abbot-Smith, Elena Lieven & Michael Tomasello - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (1):128-151.
    Many studies show a developmental advantage for transitive sentences with familiar verbs over those with novel verbs. It might be that once familiar verbs become entrenched in particular constructions, they would be more difficult to understand (than would novel verbs) in non-prototypical constructions. We provide support for this hypothesis investigating German children using a forced-choice pointing paradigm with reversed agent-patient roles. We tested active transitive verbs in study 1. The 2-year olds were better with familiar (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  69
    Parataxis and parentheticals.Michael Hand - 1993 - Linguistics and Philosophy 16 (5):495 - 507.
    I have proposed that the complementizerthat has a pragmatic property of demonstrativity, analogous to that ascribed by demonstrative analyses of the semantics of the complementizer but not impinging on the syntactic analysis of sentential embedding. My account explains a number of phenomena, including the illocutionary peculiarities of parentheticals, the pragmatics ofthat-omission, and consequently the distributional statistics ofthat-omission and related grammatical features of embeddings reported in the literature. By this means these phenomena are theoretically unified under a single hypothesis.Furthermore, this demonstrativity (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  84
    Verbs, Times and Objects.Thomas Crowther - 2019 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 27 (4):475-497.
    ABSTRACTThe aim of the paper is to demonstrate the fruitfulness of the influential verb typology developed by Zeno Vendler for recent debates in the philosophy of perception. Section one explains t...
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  14
    Reporting Verbs in Court Judgments of the Common Law System: A Corpus-Based Study.Wei Yu - 2020 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 34 (2):525-560.
    Professionals in various disciplines adopt significantly different lexicons to report their discoveries and arguments. Scientists discover, philosophers argue, whereas legal practitioners apply and consider. Reporting, as a ubiquitous linguistic phenomenon, has its disciplinary characteristics. In court judgments, it reflects the way judges identify the evidence of different documents or other courts. In the self-built court judgment corpus, the paper focuses on the way that judicial arguments are constructed through reporting verbs. On the basis of the analysis of the representation (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  90
    Pejorative Verbs and the Prospects for a Unified Theory of Slurs.Adam Sennet & David Copp - 2020 - Analytic Philosophy 61 (2):130-151.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  12
    XIV*—Verbs and Adverbs, and Some Other Modes of Grammatical Combination.David Wiggins - 1986 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86 (1):273-306.
    David Wiggins; XIV*—Verbs and Adverbs, and Some Other Modes of Grammatical Combination, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 86, Issue 1, 1 June 1986.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50. Certain Verbs Are Syntactically Explicit Quantifiers.Anna Szabolcsi - 2011 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6:5.
    Quantification over individuals, times, and worlds can in principle be made explicit in the syntax of the object language, or left to the semantics and spelled out in the meta-language. The traditional view is that quantification over individuals is syntactically explicit, whereas quantification over times and worlds is not. But a growing body of literature proposes a uniform treatment. This paper examines the scopal interaction of aspectual raising verbs (begin), modals (can), and intensional raising verbs (threaten) with quantificational (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000