85 found
Order:
See also
Profile: David Rosenthal (CUNY Graduate Center)
  1. Two Concepts of Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1986 - Philosophical Studies 49 (May):329-59.
    No mental phenomenon is more central than consciousness to an adequate understanding of the mind. Nor does any mental phenomenon seem more stubbornly to resist theoretical treatment. Consciousness is so basic to the way we think about the mind that it can be tempting to suppose that no mental states exist that are not conscious states. Indeed, it may even seem mysterious what sort of thing a mental state might be if it is not a conscious state. On this way (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   284 citations  
  2. Sensory Qualities, Consciousness, and Perception.David M. Rosenthal - 2005 - In Consciousness and Mind. Clarendon Press. pp. 175-226.
  3. Thinking That One Thinks.David M. Rosenthal - 1993 - In Martin Davies & Glyn W. Humphreys (eds.), Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays. Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   84 citations  
  4. Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - unknown
    One phenomenon pertains roughly to being awake. A person or other creature is conscious when it's awake and mentally responsive to sensory input; otherwise it's unconscious. This kind of consciousness figures most often in everyday discourse.
    Direct download  
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   23 citations  
  5.  65
    Explaining Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 2002 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press. pp. 109-131.
  6.  20
    The Nature of Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 2004 - Mind 113 (451):581-588.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   29 citations  
  7. How Many Kinds of Consciousness?David M. Rosenthal - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (4):653-665.
    Ned BlockÕs influential distinction between phenomenal and access consciousness has become a staple of current discussions of consciousness. It is not often noted, however, that his distinction tacitly embodies unargued theoretical assumptions that favor some theoretical treatments at the expense of others. This is equally so for his less widely discussed distinction between phenomenal consciousness and what he calls reflexive consciousness. I argue that the distinction between phenomenal and access consciousness, as Block draws it, is untenable. Though mental states that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   17 citations  
  8. A Theory of Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1997 - In Ned Block, Owen J. Flanagan & Guven Guzeldere (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness. MIT Press.
  9. Consciousness, the Self and Bodily Location.David M. Rosenthal - 2010 - Analysis 70 (2):270-276.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  10. The Nature of Mind.M. Rosenthal David (ed.) - 1991 - Oxford University Press.
    This anthology brings together readings mainly from contemporary philosophers, but also from writers of the past two centuries, on the philosophy of mind. Some of the main questions addressed are: is a human being really a mind in relation to a body; if so, what exactly is this mind and how it is related to the body; and are there any grounds for supposing that the mind survives the disintegration of the body?
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   18 citations  
  11. The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory Quality.David M. Rosenthal - 1991 - Philosophical Issues 1:15-36.
  12. Consciousness, Content, and Metacognitive Judgments.David M. Rosenthal - 2000 - Consciousness and Cognition 9 (2):203-214.
    Because metacognition consists in our having mental access to our cognitive states and mental states are conscious only when we are conscious of them in some suitable way, metacognition and consciousness shed important theoretical light on one another. Thus, our having metacognitive access to information carried by states that are not conscious helps con?rm the hypothesis that a mental state.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   13 citations  
  13. The Mind and Its Expression.G. E. M. Anscombe, R. Rhees & David M. Rosenthal - unknown
    pain' and ┌I think that p┐ express the pain and the thought that p, themselves. The book is most impressive. It is packed with careful argument, and addresses a remarkable range of important issues about the mind. I have very much enjoyed studying it.
    Direct download (2 more)  
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  14. Metacognition and Higher-Order Thoughts.David M. Rosenthal - 2000 - Consciousness and Cognition 9 (2):231-242.
    Because there is a fair amount of overlap in the points by Balog and Rey, I will organize this response topically, referring specifically to each commentator as rele- vant. And, because much of the discussion focuses on my higher-order-thought hypothesis independent of questions about metacognition, I will begin by addressing a cluster of issues that have to do with the status, motivation, and exact formulation of that hypothesis.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   11 citations  
  15.  25
    The Colors and Shapes of Visual Experiences.David M. Rosenthal - 1999 - In Denis Fisette (ed.), Consciousness and Intentionality: Models and Modalities of Attribution. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 95--118.
    red and round. According to common sense, the red, round thing we see is the tomato itself. When we have a hallucinatory vision of a tomato, however, there may be present to us no red and round phys- ical object. Still, we use the words 'red' and 'round' to describe that situation as well, this time applying them to the visual experience itself. We say that we have a red, round visual image, or a visual experience of a red disk, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   12 citations  
  16. Self-Knowledge and Moore's Paradox.David M. Rosenthal - 1995 - Philosophical Studies 77 (2-3):195 - 209.
    As G. E. Moore famously observed, sentences such as 'It's raining but I don't think it is', though they aren't contradictory, cannot be used to make coherent assertions.' The trouble with such sentences is not a matter of their truth conditions; such sentences can readily be true. Indeed, it happens often enough with each of us that we think, for example, that it isn't raining even though it is. This shows that such sentences are not literally contradictory. But even though (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   10 citations  
  17. Consciousness and Higher-Order Thought.David M. Rosenthal - 2002 - In L. Nagel (ed.), Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. Macmillan.
    The problem of consciousness is to say what it is for some of our thoughts, feelings, and sensations to be conscious, given that others are not. This is different from saying what it is for a person to be conscious or not conscious. Even when people are conscious, many of their thoughts and sensations typically are not. And there's nothing problematic about a person's being conscious; it's just the person's being awake and responsive to sensory input.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  18. Being Conscious of Ourselves.David M. Rosenthal - 2004 - The Monist 87 (2):161-184.
  19. The Timing of Conscious States.David M. Rosenthal - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (2):215-20.
    Striking experimental results by Benjamin Libet and colleagues have had an impor- tant impact on much recent discussion of consciousness. Some investigators have sought to replicate or extend Libet’s results (Haggard, 1999; Haggard & Eimer, 1999; Haggard, Newman, & Magno, 1999; Trevena & Miller, 2002), while others have focused on how to interpret those findings (e.g., Gomes, 1998, 1999, 2002; Pockett, 2002), which many have seen as conflicting with our commonsense picture of mental functioning.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   7 citations  
  20. Unity of Consciousness and the Self.David M. Rosenthal - 2003 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (3):325-352.
    The so-called unity of consciousness consists in the compelling sense we have that all our conscious mental states belong to a single conscious subject. Elsewhere I have argued that a mental state's being conscious is a matter of our being conscious of that state by having a higher-order thought (HOT) about it. Contrary to what is sometimes argued, this HOT model affords a natural explanation of our sense that our conscious states all belong to a single conscious subject. HOTs often (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  21. Phenomenal Consciousness and What It's Like.David M. Rosenthal - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1):156--57.
    be realized. Whatever gets access to phenomenal awareness is represented within this absent together.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   5 citations  
  22. State Consciousness and Transitive Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1994 - Consciousness and Cognition 2 (3):355-63.
  23. Color, Mental Location, and the Visual Field.David M. Rosenthal - 2001 - Consciousness and Cognition 10 (1):85-93.
    Color subjectivism is the view that color properties are mental properties of our visual sensations, perhaps identical with properties of neural states, and that nothing except visual sensations and other mental states exhibits color properties. Color phys- icalism, by contrast, holds that colors are exclusively properties of visible physical objects and processes.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   5 citations  
  24. The Kinds of Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - unknown
    I begin by considering Ned Block's widely accepted distinction between phenomenal and access consciousness. I argue that on Block's official characterization a mental state's being access conscious is not a way the state's being conscious in any intuitive sense; that if phenomenal consciousness itself corresponds to an intuitive way of a state's being conscious, it literally implies access consciousness; and that Block misconstrues the theoretical significance of the commonsense distinction. These considerations point to the view that mental states' being conscious (...)
    Direct download  
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  25.  39
    Moore's Paradox and Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1995 - Philosophical Perspectives 9:313-33.
  26.  10
    On Being Accessible to Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):621-621.
  27.  25
    Sensory Quality and the Relocation Story.David M. Rosenthal - 1999 - Philosophical Topics 26 (1/2):321-350.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  28. The Identity Theory.David M. Rosenthal - 1994 - In Samuel D. Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind. Blackwell.
    In Descartes's time the issue between materialists and their opponents was framed in terms of substances. Materialists such as Thomas Hobbes and Pierre Gassendi maintained that people are physical systems with abilities that no other physical systems have; people, therefore, are special kinds of physical substance. Descartes's DUALISM, by contrast, claimed that people consist of two distinct substances that interact causally: a physical body and a nonphysical, unextended substance. The traditional.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  29.  50
    Introspection and Self-Interpretation.David M. Rosenthal - 2000 - Philosophical Topics 28 (2):201-33.
  30.  87
    Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem.David M. Rosenthal (ed.) - 1971 - Prentice-Hall.
    An expanded and updated edition of this classic collection.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   8 citations  
  31. Subjective Character and Reflexive Content. [REVIEW]David M. Rosenthal - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (1):191-198.
    I. Zombies and the Knowledge Argument John Perry.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  32.  90
    Explicarea Conştiinţei.David M. Rosenthal - unknown
    Dintre fenomenele mentale, nici unul nu pare să reziste atât de bine explicaţiei precum conştiinţa. Parţial, dificultatea se datorează faptului că folosim termenul „conştient” şi alţii înrudiţi să dea seama de anumite fenomene distincte ale căror legături nu sunt întotdeauna clare. Iar acest lucru duce adesea la amestecarea acestor fenomene distincte. De aceea, orice încercare de a explica conştiinţa trebuie să înceapă prin a distinge diferitele lucruri pe care le numim conştiinţă. Un astfel de fenomen este strâns legat de simplul (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  33. Intentionality.David M. Rosenthal - 1987 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1):151-184.
    At the level of our platitudinous background knowledge about things, speech is the expression of thought. And understanding what such expressing involves is central to understanding the relation between thinking and speaking. Part of what it is for a speech act to express a mental state is that the speech act accurately captures the mental state and can convey to others what mental state it is. And for this to occur, the speech act at least must have propositional content that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  34. Consciousness and the Mind.David M. Rosenthal - 2002 - Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly 51 (July):227-251.
    Everyone — or almost everyone — was agreed that what is [mental] … has a common quality in which its essence is expressed: namely the quality of being conscious — unique, indescribable, but needing no description. All that is conscious … is [mental], and conversely all that is [mental] is conscious; that is self-evident and to contradict it is nonsense.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  35. Dualism.David M. Rosenthal - 1998 - In E. Craig (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.
    Dualism is the view that mental phenomena are, in some respect, nonphysical. The best-known version is due to Descartes, and holds that the mind is a nonphysical substance. Descartes argued that, because minds have no spatial properties and physical reality is essentially extended in space, minds are wholly nonphysical. Every human being is accordingly a composite of two objects: a physical body, and a nonphysical object that is that human being's mind. On a weaker version of dualism, which contemporary thinkers (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  36. Emotions and the Self.David M. Rosenthal - 1983 - In K. Irani & Gerald E. Myers (eds.), Emotion: Philosophical Studies. Haven.
    Much of the perplexity that motivates modern discussion of the nature of mind derives indirectly from the striking success of physical explanation. Not only has physics itself advanced at a remarkable pace in the last four centuries; every hope has been held out that, in principle, all science can be understood and ultimately studied in terms of mechanisms proper to physics. Seeing all natural phenomena as explicable in terms appropriate to physics, however, makes the mental seem to be a singularity (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  37.  1
    XV-Unity of Consciousness and the Self.David M. Rosenthal - 2003 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (1):325-352.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  38. Multiple Drafts and Higher-Order Thoughts. [REVIEW]David M. Rosenthal - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (4):911-18.
    whatever it is that occurs in between the two. Though superficially tempting, this idea heightens the air of mystery surrounding consciousness. As far..
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  39. Multiple Drafts and the Facts of the Matter.David M. Rosenthal - 1995 - In Thomas Metzinger (ed.), Conscious Experience. Ferdinand Schoningh. pp. 275--290.
  40. Will and the Theory of Judgment.David M. Rosenthal - unknown
    Contemporary discussions typically give somewhat sort shrift to the theory of judgment Descartes advances in the Fourth Meditation.' One reason for this relative neglect is presumably the prima facie implausibility of the theory. It sounds odd to say that, in believing something, one's mental affirmation is an act of free will, on a par with freely deciding what to do. In addition, Descartes advances the theory as a way to explain the possibility of human error, which doubtless strikes many as (...)
    Direct download  
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  41. Apperception, Sensation, and Dissociability.David M. Rosenthal - 1997 - Mind and Language 2 (2):206-23.
  42.  25
    Mentality and Neutrality.David M. Rosenthal - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (13):386-415.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  43.  3
    The Disappearance of Introspection.David M. Rosenthal & William Lyons - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (2):425.
  44. Experience and the Physical.David M. Rosenthal - 2006 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 13 (10-11):117-28.
    Strawson’s challenging and provocative defence of panpsychism1 begins by sensibly insisting that physicalism, properly understood, must unflinchingly countenance the occurrence of conscious experiences. No view, he urges, will count as ‘real physicalism’ (p. 4) if it seeks to get around or soften that commitment, as versions of socalled physicalism sometimes do. Real physicalism (hereinafter physicalism tout court) must accordingly reject any stark opposition of mental and physical, which is not only invoked by many followers of Descartes, but even countenanced by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  45.  37
    Higher-Order Thoughts and the Appendage Theory of Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1993 - Philosophical Psychology 6 (2):155-66.
    Theories of what it is for a mental state to be conscious must answer two questions. We must say how we're conscious of our conscious mental states. And we must explain why we seem to be conscious of them in a way that's immediate. Thomas Natsoulas distinguishes three strategies for explaining what it is for mental states to be conscious. I show that the differences among those strategies are due to the divergent answers they give to the foregoing questions. Natsoulas (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   2 citations  
  46.  25
    First-Person Operationalism and Mental Taxonomy.David M. Rosenthal - 1994 - Philosophical Topics 22 (1/2):319-349.
  47. Why Are Verbally Expressed Thoughts Conscious?David M. Rosenthal - 1990 - Bielefeld Report.
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  48.  21
    Explaining Consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1993 - In David J. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings. Oxford University Press. pp. 406--421.
  49.  85
    Addendum to Introduction.David M. Rosenthal - 2000 - In Materialism and the Mind-Body Problem. Hackett.
    Mind-body materialism is at its most inviting in the context of trying to give a unified treatment of the natural world. And the principle challenge it faces is to do justice to the distinguishing features of mental phenomena, which set them off from nonmental, physical reality. This challenge it not easy to meet. In 1971 I suggested that the difficulty in meeting it makes especially appealing the eliminative materialism of Feyerabend and Rorty. If adopting the materialist view that mental phenomena (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  50.  16
    Perception: A Representative Theory by Frank Jackson. [REVIEW]David M. Rosenthal - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy 82 (1):28-41.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 85