Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Dusting Off Educational Studies: a methodology for implementing certain proposals of John Wilson’s.J. C. Walker - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 18 (1):3-16.
    J C Walker; Dusting Off Educational Studies: a methodology for implementing certain proposals of John Wilson’s, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 18, I.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Five Decades of Structure: A Retrospective View.Juan Vicente Mayoral - 2012 - Theoria 27 (3):261-280.
    This paper is an introduction to the special issue commemorating the 50th anniversary of the publication of _The Structure of Scientific Revolutions_ by Thomas Kuhn. It introduces some main ideas of _Structure_, as its change in historical perspective for the interpretation of scientific progress, the role and nature of scientific communities, the incommensurability concept, or the new-world problem, and summarizes some philosophical reactions. After this introduction, the special issue includes papers by Alexander Bird, Paul Hoyningen-Huene and George Reisch on different (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From Nuisance Variables to Explanatory Theories: A Reformulation of the Third Variable Problem.Brian D. Haig - 1992 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 24 (2):78-97.
  • Regulation of science by ‘Peer review’.Malcolm Atkinson - 1994 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (2):147-158.
    Impositiion of selection and opportunity for censorship meust be regarded as aberrations of a communication system for science. Future historians might wonder why these faults evinced so little concern. Because editorial decisiions pre-empt scientific debate, editors and their advisers assume a heavy responsibility for nurturing fresh conjectures and for maintaining unbiased speedy communication. Evidently this responsibility has not always been honoured.Available evidence of inappropriate rejection confirms the expectable, if not adequately anticipated, tendency for reviewers to oppose innovation; so that although (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Seeing and telling the invisible: problems of a new epistemic category in the second half of the eighteenth century.Nathalie Vuillemin - 2024 - Intellectual History Review 34 (2):389-400.
    The invisible object, in the eighteenth century, is not an evidence. It is the result of textual and semantic learning. Which concrete strategies are used to construct and depict objects out of sight? How do we make them a cognitive reality acceptable to a scientific community? This paper first highlights the conditions for the emergence of a field of microscopic knowledge and its epistemological consequences. Then we consider the microscopic gaze in terms of learning, situated between the act of observation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rethinking Neuroscientific Methodology: Lived Experience in Behavioral Studies.Nedah Nemati - forthcoming - Biological Theory:1-14.
    The role of experience in the process of behavioral refinement has been undertheorized by philosophers of neuroscience and neuroscientists. By examining sleep studies in behavioral neurobiology, I show that scientists frequently invoke a variety of lived experiences—what I call experientially derived notions—to refine the behavior under investigation. Of note, these behaviors must remain sufficiently fuzzy throughout experimentation to permit refinement. The aim of this article is to recognize that neuroscientists’ use of lived experience necessarily helps refine behaviors and render those (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explaining as Mediated Action.Alexsandro Pereira de Pereira, Paulo Lima Junior & Renato Felix Rodrigues - 2016 - Science & Education 25 (3-4):343-362.
    Explaining is one of the most important everyday practices in science education. In this article, we examine how scientific explanations could serve as cultural tools for members of a group of pre-service physics teachers. Specifically, we aim at their use of explanations about forces of inertia in non-inertial frames of reference. A basic assumption of our study is that explanatory tools (e.g., typical explanations learned) shape the ways we think and speak about the world. Drawing on the theory of mediated (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A remark on the completeness of the computational model of mind.William Demopoulos - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):135-135.
  • Why Images?Megan Delehanty - 2010 - Medicine Studies 2 (3):161-173.
    Given that many imaging technologies in biology and medicine are non-optical and generate data that is essentially numerical, it is a striking feature of these technologies that the data generated using them are most frequently displayed in the form of semi-naturalistic, photograph-like images. In this paper, I claim that three factors underlie this: (1) historical preferences, (2) the rhetorical power of images, and (3) the cognitive accessibility of data presented in the form of images. The third of these can be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Paving the Way for an Evolutionary Social Constructivism.Andreas De Block & Bart Du Laing - 2007 - Biological Theory 2 (4):337-348.
    The idea has recently taken root that evolutionary theory and social constructivism are less antagonistic than most theorists thought, and we have even seen attempts at integrating constructivist and evolutionary approaches to human thought and behaviour. We argue in this article that although the projected integration is possible, indeed valuable, the existing attempts have tended to be vague or overly simplistic about the claims of social constructivist. We proceed by examining how to give more precision and substance to the research (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Living in the “space of reasons”: The “rationality debate” revisited.David Davies - 1999 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (3):231 – 244.
    Two questions are central to the “rationality debate” in the philosophy of social science. First, should we acknowledge differences in basic norms of epistemic and agential rationality, or in the content of perceptual experience, as the “best explanation” of radical differences in belief and practice? Second, can genuine understanding be achieved between cultures and research traditions that so differ in their beliefs and practices? I survey a number of responses to these questions, and suggest that one of these, “dialogical optimism”, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Critique Without Critics?Marcelo Dascal - 1997 - Science in Context 10 (1):39-62.
    The ArgumentTwo dominant models of criticism are identified and analyzed. One is selfconsciously normative. It conceives of criticism as subject to strict logical rules. The other views itself as essentially descriptive and accounts for the critical activity in terms of social factors. In spite of their different origins and purposes, it is argued that both models share a reductionistic thrust, which minimizes the role of the critic qua agent. It is further agreed that neither provides an adequate account of critical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Epistemological and ethical considerations in conceptualizing and implementing human resource management.H. Peter Dachler & Georges Enderle - 1989 - Journal of Business Ethics 8 (8):597 - 606.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Epistemic Engagement, Aesthetic Value, and Scientific Practice.Adrian Currie - 2023 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 74 (2):313-334.
    I develop an account of the relationship between aesthetics and knowledge, focusing on scientific practice. Cognitivists infer from ‘partial sensitivity’—aesthetic appreciation partly depends on doxastic states—to ‘factivity’, the idea that the truth or otherwise of those beliefs makes a difference to aesthetic appreciation. Rejecting factivity, I develop a notion of ‘epistemic engagement’: partaking genuinely in a knowledge-directed process of coming to epistemic judgements, and suggest that this better accommodates the relationship between the aesthetic and the epistemic. Scientific training (and other (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Epistemological strata and the rules of right reason.Robert C. Cummins, Pierre Poirier & Martin Roth - 2004 - Synthese 141 (3):287 - 331.
    It has been commonplace in epistemology since its inception to idealize away from computational resource constraints, i.e., from the constraints of time and memory. One thought is that a kind of ideal rationality can be specified that ignores the constraints imposed by limited time and memory, and that actual cognitive performance can be seen as an interaction between the norms of ideal rationality and the practicalities of time and memory limitations. But a cornerstone of naturalistic epistemology is that normative assessment (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Objectivity in experimental inquiry: Breaking data-technique circles.Sylvia Culp - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (3):438-458.
    I respond to H. M. Collins's claim (1985, 1990, 1993) that experimental inquiry cannot be objective because the only criterium experimentalists have for determining whether a technique is "working" is the production of "correct" (i.e., the expected) data. Collins claims that the "experimenters' regress," the name he gives to this data-technique circle, cannot be broken using the resources of experiment alone. I argue that the data-technique circle, can be broken even though any interpretation of the raw data produced by techniques (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Anatomy, metaphysics, and values: The ape brain debate reconsidered. [REVIEW]Christopher Cosans - 1994 - Biology and Philosophy 9 (2):129-165.
    Conventional wisdom teaches that Thomas Huxley discredited Richard Owen in their debate over ape and human brains. This paper reexamines the dispute and uses it as a test case for evaluating the metaphysical realist, internal realist, and social constructivist theories of scientific knowledge. Since Owen worked in the Kantian tradition, his anatomical research illustrates the implications of internal realism for scientific practice. As an avowed Cartesian, Huxley offered a well developed attack on Owen''s position from a metaphysical realist perspective. Adrian (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle's anatomical philosophy of nature.Christopher E. Cosans - 1998 - Biology and Philosophy 13 (3):311-339.
    This paper explores the anatomical foundations of Aristotle's natural philosophy. Rather than simply looking at the body, he contrives specific procedures for revealing unmanifest phenomena. In some cases, these interventions seem extensive enough to qualify as experiments. At the work bench, one can observe the parts of animals in the manner Aristotle describes, even if his descriptions seem at odds with 20th century textbooks. Manipulating animals allows us to recover his teleological thought more fully. This consideration of Aristotle as a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Science, objectivity and moral values.Alberto Cordero - 1992 - Science & Education 1 (1):49-70.
  • Relevant features and statistical models of generalization.James E. Corter - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):653-654.
  • Commercialization of the University and Problem Choice by Academic Biological Scientists.Mark H. Cooper - 2009 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 34 (5):629-653.
    Based on data from a survey of biological scientists at 125 American universities, this article explores how the commercialization of the university affects the problems academic scientists pursue and argues that this reorientation of scientific agendas results in a shift from science in the public interest to science for private goods. Drawing on perspectives from Bourdieu on how actors employ strategic practices toward the accumulation of social capital and acquire dispositional and perceptional tendencies that in turn recondition social structures, the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • From computational metaphor to consensual algorithms.Kenneth Mark Colby - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):134-135.
  • A better best system account of lawhood.Jonathan Cohen & Craig Callender - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 145 (1):1 - 34.
    Perhaps the most significant contemporary theory of lawhood is the Best System (/MRL) view on which laws are true generalizations that best systematize knowledge. Our question in this paper will be how best to formulate a theory of this kind. We’ll argue that an acceptable MRL should (i) avoid inter-system comparisons of simplicity, strength, and balance, (ii) make lawhood epistemically accessible, and (iii) allow for laws in the special sciences. Attention to these problems will bring into focus a useful menu (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  • Conceptual Problems in the Foundations of Mechanics.Ricardo Lopes Coelho - 2012 - Science & Education 21 (9):1337-1356.
  • Did Freud rely on the tally argument to meet the argument from suggestibility?F. Cioffi - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):230-231.
  • Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality: A reply to Jerry Fodor.Paul M. Churchland - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (June):167-87.
    The doctrine that the character of our perceptual knowledge is plastic, and can vary substantially with the theories embraced by the perceiver, has been criticized in a recent paper by Fodor. His arguments are based on certain experimental facts and theoretical approaches in cognitive psychology. My aim in this paper is threefold: to show that Fodor's views on the impenetrability of perceptual processing do not secure a theory-neutral foundation for knowledge; to show that his views on impenetrability are almost certainly (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   209 citations  
  • Plasticity: conceptual and neuronal.Paul M. Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):133-134.
  • Neuroscience and psychology: should the labor be divided?Patricia Smith Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):133-133.
  • Mental models in data interpretation.Clark A. Chinn & William F. Brewer - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (3):219.
    This paper presents a cognitive account of the process of evaluating scientific data. Our account assumes that when individuals evaluate data, they construct a mental model of a data-interpretation package, in which the data and theoretical interpretations of the data are integrated. We propose that individuals attempt to discount data by seeking alternative explanations for events within the mental model; data-interpretation packages are accepted when the individual cannot find alternative accounts for these events. Our analysis indicates that there are many (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Human Reason in Context.Szu-Ting Chen - 2017 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 26:13-28.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two projects for understanding the mind: A response to Morris and Richardson. [REVIEW]Nick Chater & Martin Pickering - 1997 - Minds and Machines 7 (4):553-569.
    We respond to Morris and Richardson 's claim that Pickering and Chater's arguments about the lack of a relation between cognitive science and folk psychology are flawed. We note that possible controversies about the appropriate uses for the two terms do not affect our arguments. We then address their claim that computational explanation of knowledge-rich processes has proved possible in the domains of problem solving, scientific discovery, and reasoning. We argue that, in all cases, computational explanation is only possible for (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The scaffolding of psychoanalysis.Peter Caws - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):229-230.
  • Viewing behaviorism selectively.A. Charles Catania - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):701-702.
  • Switching gestalts on gestalt psychology: On the relation between science and philosophy.Jordi Cat - 2007 - Perspectives on Science 15 (2):131-177.
    : The distinction between science and philosophy plays a central role in methodological, programmatic and institutional debates. Discussions of disciplinary identities typically focus on boundaries or else on genealogies, yielding models of demarcation and models of dynamics. Considerations of a discipline's self-image, often based on history, often plays an important role in the values, projects and practices of its members. Recent focus on the dynamics of scientific change supplements Kuhnian neat model with a role for philosophy and yields a model (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Can educational research be scientific?Wilfred Carr - 1983 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 17 (1):35–43.
    Wilfred Carr; Can Educational Research be Scientific?, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 17, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 35–43, https://doi.org/10.1111.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Can Educational Research be Scientific?Wilfred Carr - 1983 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 17 (1):35-43.
    Wilfred Carr; Can Educational Research be Scientific?, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 17, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 35–43, https://doi.org/10.1111.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • With a friend like Professor Grünbaum does psychoanalysis need any enemies?Arthur Caplan - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):228-229.
  • Toward a cognitive science of category learning.Robert L. Campbell & Wendy A. Kellogg - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):652-653.
  • Kane and Double on the Principle of Rational Explanation.Neil Campbell - 2017 - Dialogue 56 (1):45-63.
    En utilisant le cadre théorique développé par Jaegwon Kim, soit l’opposition entre le réalisme explicatif et l’irréalisme explicatif, ainsi que quelques observations sur la métaphysique et l’épistémologie de l’explication, je réexamine le désaccord opposant Robert Kane à Richard Double au sujet du principe de l’explication rationnelle. Je défends la position de Kane sur la double rationalité et je soutiens que le principe proposé par Double possède un champ d’application plus limité qu’il le prétend. Je montre aussi que, contrairement à ce (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Comment on "the natural selection model of conceptual evolution".Donald T. Campbell - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (3):502-507.
  • Abductive reasoning in cognitive neuroscience: weak and strong reverse inference.Fabrizio Calzavarini & Gustavo Cevolani - 2022 - Synthese 200 (2):1-26.
    Reverse inference is a crucial inferential strategy used in cognitive neuroscience to derive conclusions about the engagement of cognitive processes from patterns of brain activation. While widely employed in experimental studies, it is now viewed with increasing scepticism within the neuroscience community. One problem with reverse inference is that it is logically invalid, being an instance of abduction in Peirce’s sense. In this paper, we offer the first systematic analysis of reverse inference as a form of abductive reasoning and highlight (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • String Theory, Non-Empirical Theory Assessment, and the Context of Pursuit.Frank Cabrera - 2021 - Synthese 198:3671–3699.
    In this paper, I offer an analysis of the radical disagreement over the adequacy of string theory. The prominence of string theory despite its notorious lack of empirical support is sometimes explained as a troubling case of science gone awry, driven largely by sociological mechanisms such as groupthink (e.g. Smolin 2006). Others, such as Dawid (2013), explain the controversy by positing a methodological revolution of sorts, according to which string theorists have quietly turned to nonempirical methods of theory assessment given (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Whence Philosophy of Biology?Jason M. Byron - 2007 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (3):409-422.
    A consensus exists among contemporary philosophers of biology about the history of their field. According to the received view, mainstream philosophy of science in the 1930s, 40s, and 50s focused on physics and general epistemology, neglecting analyses of the 'special sciences', including biology. The subdiscipline of philosophy of biology emerged (and could only have emerged) after the decline of logical positivism in the 1960s and 70s. In this article, I present bibliometric data from four major philosophy of science journals (Erkenntnis, (...)
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Substantial causes and nomic determination.Henry Byerly - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (1):57-81.
    I characterize a notion of causal agency that is the causitive component of many transitive verbs. The agency of what I call substantial causes relates objects physically to systems with which they interact. Such agent causation does not reduce to conditionship relations, nor does it cease to play a role in scientific discourse. I argue, contrary to regularity theories, that causal claims do not in general depend for their sense on generalities nor do they entail the existence of laws. Clarification (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Assessing the field of science and religion: Advice from the next generation.Michael S. Burdett - 2017 - Zygon 52 (3):747-763.
    The field of science and religion is undergoing a transition today requiring assessment of its past movements and identifying its future trajectories by the next generation of science and religion scholars. This essay provides such assessment and advice. To focus efforts on the past, I turn to Ian Barbour's own stock taking of the field some forty years ago in an essay entitled “Science and Religion Today” before giving some personal comments where I argue that much of the field has (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Drie kanttekeningen bij Hans Radder.Filip Buekens - 2007 - Krisis 8 (1):87-94.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Essay Review: History and Methodology: Fact and Theory. An Aspect of Philosophy of ScienceFact and Theory. An aspect of philosophy of science. O'NeilW. M. . Pp. xiv + 193. £3.30.Gerd Buchdahl - 1970 - History of Science 9 (1):93-101.
  • Philosophy of Science circa 1950–2000: Some Things we (should have) Learned.Harold I. Brown - 2014 - Diogenes 61 (2):45-58.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophie des sciences, 1950-2000 : qu'avons-nous appris?Harold I. Brown & Brigitte Rollet - 2014 - Diogène 242 (2):68-90.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Practical reasoning and science education: Implications for theory and practice.Nancy W. Brickhouse, William B. Stanley & James A. Whitson - 1993 - Science & Education 2 (4):363-375.