Results for 'time preference'

995 found
Order:
  1.  80
    Pure time preference.Rosemary Lowry & Martin Peterson - 2011 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92 (4):490-508.
    Pure time preference is a preference for something to come at one point in time rather than another merely because of when it occurs in time. In opposition to Sidgwick, Ramsey, Rawls, and Parfit we argue that it is not always irrational to be guided by pure time preferences. We argue that even if the mere difference of location in time is not a rational ground for a preference, time may nevertheless (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  2. Pure time preference in intertemporal welfare economics.J. Paul Kelleher - 2017 - Economics and Philosophy 33 (3):441-473.
    Several areas of welfare economics seek to evaluate states of affairs as a function of interpersonally comparable individual utilities. The aim is to map each state of affairs onto a vector of individual utilities, and then to produce an ordering of these vectors that can be represented by a mathematical function assigning a real number to each. When this approach is used in intertemporal contexts, a central theoretical question concerns the evaluative weight to be applied to utility coming at different (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  3. ‘Pure’ Time Preferences Are Irrelevant to the Debate over Time Bias: A Plea for Zero Time Discounting as the Normative Standard.Preston Greene - 2021 - Australasian Philosophical Review 5 (3):254-265.
    I find much to like in Craig Callender's [2022] arguments for the rational permissibility of non-exponential time discounting when these arguments are viewed in a conditional form: viz., if one thinks that time discounting is rationally permissible, as the social scientist does, then one should think that non-exponential time discounting is too. However, time neutralists believe that time discounting is rationally impermissible, and thus they take zero time discounting to be the normative standard. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  62
    ‘Pure Time Preference’: Reply to Lowry and Peterson.Jens Johansson & Simon Rosenqvist - 2016 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97 (3):435-441.
    A pure time preference is a preference for something to occur at one point in time rather than another, merely because of when it occurs in time. Such preferences are widely regarded as paradigm examples of irrational preferences. However, Rosemary Lowry and Martin Peterson have recently argued that, for instance, a pure time preference to go to the opera tonight rather than next month may be rationally permissible, even if the amounts of intrinsic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  16
    Pure Time Preference.Martin Peterson Rosemary Lowry - 2011 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92 (4):490-508.
    Pure time preference is a preference for something to come at one point in time rather than another merely because of when it occurs in time. In opposition to Sidgwick, Ramsey, Rawls, and Parfit we argue that it is not always irrational to be guided by pure time preferences. We argue that even if the mere difference of location in time is not a rational ground for a preference, time may nevertheless (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6. All Time Preferences?Krister Bykvist - 1999 - Theoria 65 (1):36-54.
  7. Time preference, the environment and the interests of future generations.E. Wesley & F. Peterson - 1993 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 6 (2):107-126.
    The behavior of individuals currently living will generally have long-term consequences that affect the well-being of those who will come to live in the future. Intergenerational interdependencies of this nature raise difficult moral issues because only the current generation is in a position to decide on actions that will determine the nature of the world in which future generations will live. Although most are willing to attach some weight to the interests of future generations, many would argue that it is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  17
    Time Preference.Paul Ziff - 1990 - Dialectica 44 (1‐2):43-54.
  9.  59
    Pure Time Preference: Reply to Johansson and Rosenqvist.Rosemary Lowry & Martin Peterson - 2017 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 98 (1):442-445.
    Johansson and Rosenqvist reject our argument for the rational permissibility of pure time preferences. Johansson and Rosenqvist's main objection is that where two options, X and Y, have equal intrinsic value, there will be a reason to be indifferent between X and Y, and therefore a reason to not hold a PTP for X or Y. In this reply, we argue that if two options have equal intrinsic value, it does not follow that you have a reason to be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  8
    Pure Time Preference: Reply to Johansson and Rosenqvist.Rosemary Lowry & Martin Peterson - 2016 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97 (3):442-445.
    Johansson and Rosenqvist reject our argument for the rational permissibility of pure time preferences (PTP). Johansson and Rosenqvist's main objection is that where two options, X and Y, have equal intrinsic value, there will be a reason to be indifferent between X and Y, and therefore a reason to not hold a PTP for X or Y. In this reply, we argue that if two options have equal intrinsic value, it does not follow that you have a reason to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  40
    Attachment and time preference.James S. Chisholm - 1999 - Human Nature 10 (1):51-83.
    This paper investigates hypotheses drawn from two sources: (1) Belsky, Steinberg, and Draper’s (1991) attachment theory model of the development of reproductive strategies, and (2) recent life history models and comparative data suggesting that environmental risk and uncertainty may be potent determinants of the optimal tradeoff between current and future reproduction. A retrospective, self-report study of 136 American university women aged 19–25 showed that current recollections of early stress (environmental risk and uncertainty) were related to individual differences in adult (...) preference and adult sexual behavior, and that individual differences in time preference were related to adult attachment organization and sexual behavior. These results are consistent with the hypothesis that perceptions of early stress index environmental risk and uncertainty and mediate the attachment process and the development of reproductive strategies. On this view individual differences in time preference are considered to be part of the attachment theoretical construct of an internal working model, which itself is conceived as an evolved algorithm for the contingent development of alternative reproductive strategies. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  12.  12
    Time preference, government, and the process of de-civilization – from monarchy to democracy.Hans-Hermann Hoppe - 1994 - Journal des Economistes Et des Etudes Humaines 5 (2-3):319-352.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  53
    Risk and time preferences of entrepreneurs: evidence from a Danish field experiment.Steffen Andersen, Amalia Di Girolamo, Glenn W. Harrison & Morten I. Lau - 2014 - Theory and Decision 77 (3):341-357.
    To understand how small business entrepreneurs respond to government policy one has to know their risk and time preferences. Are they risk averse, or have high discount rates, such that they are hard to motivate? We have conducted a set of field experiments in Denmark that will allow a direct characterization of small business entrepreneurs in terms of these traits. We build on experimental tasks that are well established in the literature. The results do not suggest that small business (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Pure and Impure Time Preferences.Andrew J. Latham, Kristie Miller & James Norton - 2021 - Australasian Philosophical Review 5 (3):277-283.
    This paper investigates two assumptions of the exponential discounted utility theory (EDU) to which Callender draws our attention: namely that we can cleanly distinguish pure from impure temporal preferences, and that past discounting can be ignored. Drawing on recent empirical work in this area, we argue that in so far as one might have thought that past-directed preferences are more pure than future ones, then there is evidence that people’s pure preferences (in so far as we can make sense of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  17
    Familiarity and time preferences: Decision making about treatments for migraine headaches and Crohn's disease.Gretchen B. Chapman, Richard Nelson & Daniel B. Hier - 1999 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 5 (1):17.
  16.  92
    Climate Ethics: Justifying a Positive Social Time Preference.Joseph Heath - 2017 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 14 (4):435-462.
    _ Source: _Page Count 28 Recent debates over climate change policy have made it clear that the choice of a social discount rate has enormous consequences for the amount of mitigation that will be recommended. The social discount rate determines how future costs are to be compared to present costs. Philosophers, however, have been almost unanimous in endorsing the view that the only acceptable social rate of time preference is zero, a view that, taken literally, has either absurd (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  17. Climate Ethics: Justifying a Positive Social Time Preference.Joseph Heath - 2017 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 14 (4):435–462.
    Recent debates over climate change policy have made it clear that the choice of a social discount rate has enormous consequences for the amount of mitigation that will be recommended. The social discount rate determines how future costs are to be compared to present costs. Philosophers, however, have been almost unanimous in endorsing the view that the only acceptable social rate of time preference is zero, a view that, taken literally, has either absurd or extremely radical implications. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  49
    Lifetime Uncertainty and Time Preference.Nicolas Drouhin - 2001 - Theory and Decision 51 (2/4):145-172.
    Despite Fisher's (1930) psychological intuitions of and the formal treatment given by Yaari (1965, Review of Economic Studies 32, 137), the intertemporal model of choice is mainly a model with certain lifetime. The purpose of this paper is to reconsider this assumption, starting from a very simple two-period model of choice with lifetime uncertainty. We examine the comparative statics of the model at the first two orders and replace the concept of `pure time preference' by taking into account (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Existential Risk, Astronomical Waste, and the Reasonableness of a Pure Time Preference for Well-Being.S. J. Beard & Patrick Kaczmarek - 2024 - The Monist 107 (2):157-175.
    In this paper, we argue that our moral concern for future well-being should reduce over time due to important practical considerations about how humans interact with spacetime. After surveying several of these considerations (around equality, special duties, existential contingency, and overlapping moral concern) we develop a set of core principles that can both explain their moral significance and highlight why this is inherently bound up with our relationship with spacetime. These relate to the equitable distribution of (1) moral concern (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  53
    The only ethical argument for positive δ? Partiality and pure time preference.Andreas Mogensen - 2022 - Philosophical Studies 179 (9):2731-2750.
    I consider the plausibility of discounting for kinship, the view that a positive rate of pure intergenerational time preference is justifiable in terms of agent-relative moral reasons relating to partiality between generations. I respond to Parfit's objections to discounting for kinship, but then highlight a number of apparent limitations of this approach. I show that these limitations largely fall away when we reflect on social discounting in the context of decisions that concern the global community as a whole, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  21.  12
    Weakness of Will and Time Preference.Naoyuki Shiono - 2008 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 16 (1-2):37-55.
  22.  12
    Evaluation Scale or Output Format: The Attentional Mechanism Underpinning Time Preference Reversal.Yan-Bang Zhou, Qiang Li, Qiu-Yue Li & Hong-Zhi Liu - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Time preference reversals refers to systematic inconsistencies between preferences and valuations in intertemporal choice. When faced with a pair of intertemporal options, people preferred the smaller-sooner option but assign a higher price to the larger-later one. Different hypotheses postulate that the differences in evaluation scale or output format between the choice and the bid tasks cause the preference reversal. However, these hypotheses have not been distinguished. In the present study, we conducted a hybrid task, which shares the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  43
    Rationality and time preference.Mark Vorobej - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 25 (3):407-423.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  23
    A Life History Approach to Understanding Youth Time Preference.Deborah E. Schechter & Cyrilla M. Francis - 2010 - Human Nature 21 (2):140-164.
    Following from life history and attachment theory, individuals are predicted to be sensitive to variation in environmental conditions such that risk and uncertainty are internalized by cognitive, affective, and psychobiological mechanisms. In turn, internalizing of environmental uncertainty is expected to be associated with attitudes toward risk behaviors and investments in education. Native American youth aged 10–19 years (n = 89) from reservation communities participated in a study examining this pathway. Measures included family environmental risk and uncertainty, present and future (...) perspective, adolescent attachment, attitudes toward risk, investments in education, and salivary cortisol. Results support the idea that environmental risk and uncertainty are internalized during development. In addition, internalizing mechanisms significantly predicted attitudes toward risk and education: (1) lower scores on future time perspective and higher cortisol predicted higher scores on risk attitudes, and (2) higher scores on future time perspective and lower scores on problems with attachment predicted higher self-reported school performance. Gender differences were seen, with males anticipating a shorter lifespan than females, which predicted higher scores on risk attitudes and lower school performance. Implications for research on adolescent problem behavior and academic achievement are discussed. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25. Time-biases and Rationality: The Philosophical Perspectives on Empirical Research about Time Preferences.Tomasz Żuradzki - 2016 - In Jerzy Stelmach, Bartosz Brożek & Łukasz Kurek (eds.), The Emergence of Normative Orders. Copernicus Press. pp. 149-187.
    The empirically documented fact is that people’s preferences are time -biased. The main aim of this paper is to analyse in which sense do time -biases violate the requirements of rationality, as many authors assume. I will demonstrate that contrary to many influential views in psychology, economy and philosophy it is very difficult to find why the bias toward the near violates the requirements rationality. I will also show why the bias toward the future violates the requirements of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  10
    Martín de Azpilcueta: The Spanish Scholastic on Usury and Time-Preference.Pedro J. Caranti - 2020 - Studia Humana 9 (2):28-36.
    Martín de Azpilcueta and his fellow Spanish Scholastics writing and teaching at the University of Salamanca during Spain’s Golden Age are rightly pointed to by historians of economic thought as being major contributors toward, if not outright founders of modern economic theory. Among these is the theory of time-preference for which Azpilcueta has repeatedly been given the credit for discovering. However, this discovery is a curious one given how the same man, Azpilcueta, condemned usury in general during his (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. On exchange, monetary credit transactions, barter, time preference, interest rates, and productivity.William Barnett Ii & Walter Block - 2006 - Etica E Politica 8 (2):116-126.
    We attempt in this paper to tie together several basic insights of praxeology, and several that are not at all that basic. These include the following: that gains from exchange are subjective; that this applies to profits and interest; that credit transactions can occur under barter; that interest arises from time preference even under a pure time preference theory of interest; and that productivity can, under disequilibrium conditions, affect the various rates of interest.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  21
    Garrett on the Irrationality of Pure Time Preferences.Jeremiah Joven Joaquin - 2019 - Acta Analytica 34 (3):363-367.
    In “Experience and Time,” Brian Garrett poses a challenge to friends of the rationality of pure time preferences. In this discussion note, we accept the challenge and provide two kinds of cases wherein some pure time preferences could be deemed rational.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  13
    High Time for a Change? A Response to Callender on Rationality and Time Preferences.Ian Robertson - 2021 - Australasian Philosophical Review 5 (3):296-301.
    Craig Callender attempts to overturn conventional wisdom within decision theory by contending that rational intertemporal choices need not always conform to an exponential discounting function. He argues that there are cases in which hyperbolic discounting is the height of rationality. This paper does not seek to undermine Callender’s conclusions, but instead raises two interrelated theoretical concerns with his way securing them. The first concern is with his dismissal of influential dual-system explanations of rationality. It is argued that Callender’s criticisms of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  12
    Time to Listen: Most Regular Patrons of Music Venues Prefer Lower Volumes.Elizabeth Francis Beach & Megan Gilliver - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  40
    The time frame of preferences, dispositions, and the validity of advance directives for the mentally ill.Julian Savulescu & Donna Dickenson - 1998 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 5 (3):225-246.
  32.  15
    Of Time Gals and Mega Men: Empirical Findings on Gender Differences in Digital Game Genre Preferences and the Accuracy of Respective Gender Stereotypes.Benjamin P. Lange, Peter Wühr & Sascha Schwarz - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12:657430.
    We investigated the accuracy of gender stereotypes regarding digital game genre preferences. In Study 1, 484 female and male participants rated their preference for 17 game genres (gender differences). In Study 2, another sample of 226 participants rated the extent to which the same genres were presumably preferred by women or men (gender stereotypes). We then compared the results of both studies in order to determine the accuracy of the gender stereotypes. Study 1 revealed actual gender differences for most (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  62
    Measuring the time stability of Prospect Theory preferences.Stefan Zeisberger, Dennis Vrecko & Thomas Langer - 2012 - Theory and Decision 72 (3):359-386.
    Prospect Theory (PT) is widely regarded as the most promising descriptive model for decision making under uncertainty. Various tests have corroborated the validity of the characteristic fourfold pattern of risk attitudes implied by the combination of probability weighting and value transformation. But is it also safe to assume stable PT preferences at the individual level? This is not only an empirical but also a conceptual question. Measuring the stability of preferences in a multi-parameter decision model such as PT is far (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  34.  17
    Ear Preference in a Simple Reaction-Time Task.J. Richard Simon - 1967 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 75 (1):49.
  35.  76
    Absolute and Relative Time-Consistent Revealed Preferences.Thomas Demuynck - 2009 - Theory and Decision 66 (3):283-299.
    We introduce an Absolute (Relative) Time-consistent Axiom of Revealed Preference which characterizes the consistency of a choice function with the property of absolute (relative) time-consistency and impatience. The axiom requires that the absolute (relative) time-consistent and impatient closure of the revealed preference relation does not conflict with the strict revealed preference relation.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  14
    Preference for Object Relative Clauses in Chinese Sentence Comprehension: Evidence From Online Self-Paced Reading Time.Kunyu Xu, Jeng-Ren Duann, Daisy L. Hung & Denise H. Wu - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Priorities, Preferences, Timing.Raymond Geuss - 2008 - In Philosophy and Real Politics. Princeton University Press. pp. 30-34.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  6
    Human preferences for time-dependent and response-dependent reinforcement schedules.Robert W. Schaeffer - 1979 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 14 (4):293-296.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  9
    Preference and information about the time and the occurrence of shock delivery.W. R. Safarjan & M. R. D’Amato - 1977 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 10 (5):355-357.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  28
    Observing and influencing preferences in real time. Gaze, morality and dynamic decision-making.Philip Pärnamets - unknown
    Preference formation and choice are dynamic cognitive processes arising from interactions between decision-makers and their immediate choice environment. This thesis examines how preferences and decisions are played out in visual attention, captured by eye-movements, as well as in group contexts. Papers I-II make use of the Choice Blindness paradigm. Paper I compares participants’ eye movements and pupil dilation over the course of a trial when participants detect and fail to detect the false feedback concerning their choices. Results indicate objective (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  17
    Patients' preference for the timing and location of follow‐up following day case arthroscopic knee surgery – The results of a questionnaire.Peter Hull, Ganaps Perianayagam, Muhammad Korim, Charlie Lewis & Stuart Brooks - 2009 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 15 (2):405-407.
  42.  11
    Future Time Perspective in Occupational Teams: Do Older Workers Prefer More Familiar Teams?Laura U. A. Gärtner & Guido Hertel - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  9
    Morningness‐Eveningness Preference, Time Perspective, and Passage of Time Judgments.Alessia Beracci, Marco Fabbri & Monica Martoni - 2022 - Cognitive Science 46 (2):e13109.
    Recent studies have shown that making accurate passage of time judgments (POTJs) for long-time intervals is an important cognitive ability. Different temporal domains, such as circadian typology (biological time) and time perspective (psychological time), could have an effect on subjective POTJs, but few studies have investigated the reciprocal influences among these temporal domains. The present study is the first systematic attempt to fill this gap. A sample of 222 participants (53.20% females; 19–60 years) filled in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  70
    Stability Over Time in the Preferences of Older Persons for Life-Sustaining Treatment.Ines M. Barrio-Cantalejo, Pablo Simón-Lorda, Adoración Molina-Ruiz, Fátima Herrera-Ramos, Encarnación Martínez-Cruz, Rosa Maria Bailon-Gómez, Antonio López-Rico & Patricia Peinado Gorlat - 2013 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 10 (1):103-114.
    Objective: To measure the stability of life-sustaining treatment preferences amongst older people and analyse the factors that influence stability. Design: Longitudinal cohort study. Setting: Primary care centres, Granada (Spain). Eighty-five persons age 65 years or older. Participants filled out a questionnaire with six contexts of illness (LSPQ-e). They had to decide whether or not to receive treatment. Participants completed the questionnaire at baseline and 18 months later. Results: 86 percent of the patients did not change preferences. Sex, age, marital status, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  14
    Commentary on" The Time Frame of Preferences, Dispositions, and the Validity of Advance Directives for the Mentally Ill".Dan W. Brock - 1998 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 5 (3):251-253.
  46.  18
    Commentary on" The Time Frame of Preferences, Dispositions, and the Validity of Advance Directives for the Mentally Ill".Sally Burgess - 1998 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 5 (3):255-258.
  47.  7
    Morningness‐Eveningness Preference, Time Perspective, and Passage of Time Judgments.Alessia Beracci, Marco Fabbri & Monica Martoni - 2022 - Cognitive Science 46 (2):e13109.
    Cognitive Science, Volume 46, Issue 2, February 2022.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  28
    Does quantum time have a preferred direction?Bryan W. Roberts - unknown
    This paper states and proves a precise sense in which, if all the measurable properties of an ordinary quantum mechanical system are ultimately derivable from position, then time in quantum mechanics can have no preferred direction. In particular, I show that when the position observable forms a complete set of commuting observables, Galilei invariant quantum mechanics is guaranteed to be time reversal invariant.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  29
    Negotiation for Time Optimization in Construction Projects with Competitive and Social Welfare Preferences.Qingfeng Meng, Zhen Li, Jianguo Du, Huimin Liu & Xiang Ding - 2019 - Complexity 2019:1-13.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  80
    Discounting, Preferences, and Paternalism in Cost-Effectiveness Analysis.Gustav Tinghög - 2012 - Health Care Analysis 20 (3):297-318.
    When assessing the cost effectiveness of health care programmes, health economists typically presume that distant events should be given less weight than present events. This article examines the moral reasonableness of arguments advanced for positive discounting in cost-effectiveness analysis both from an intergenerational and an intrapersonal perspective and assesses if arguments are equally applicable to health and monetary outcomes. The article concludes that behavioral effects related to time preferences give little or no reason for why society at large should (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 995