Results for 'The Doctrine of the Mean'

1000+ found
Order:
See also
  1. Defending the Doctrine of the Mean Against Counterexamples: A General Strategy.Nicholas Colgrove - 2024 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly (Online First):1-24.
    Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean states that each moral virtue stands opposed to two types of vice: one of excess and one of deficiency, respectively. Critics claim that some virtues—like honesty, fair-mindedness, and patience—are counterexamples to Aristotle’s doctrine. Here, I develop a generalizable strategy to defend the doctrine of the mean against such counterexamples. I argue that not only is the doctrine of the mean defensible, but taking it seriously also allows us to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Courage, the Doctrine of the Mean, and the Possibility of Evaluative and Emotional Coherence.Michael Stocker - 1989 - In Plural and conflicting values. New York: Oxford University Press.
    According to Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean, virtue and a good life involve a mean of feeling and action. This chapter focuses on David Pear's claim that the Doctrine is conceptually incoherent. It argues that there are serious difficulties in understanding what it could be for courage and its feelings to be in a mean. Courage involves plural and incommensurable values, victory and danger, and the respective emotions, confidence and fear––it is difficult to see how (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  29
    The doctrine of the mean.Whitney J. Oates - 1936 - Philosophical Review 45 (4):382-398.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  4.  48
    The doctrine of the mean in Aristotle's ethical and political theory.I. Evrigenis - 1999 - History of Political Thought 20 (3):393-416.
    The purpose of this paper is to examine the exposition of the doctrine of the mean in the ethical treatises and to determine the role and scope of mesotes within Aristotle's ethical and political theory. The examination of mesotes will reveal the strong connections, for Aristotle, between man, the city, experience, prudence, excellence and eudaimonia. Ultimately, the doctrine of the mean is, in the words of L.W. Rosenfield, an ‘analytical concept’, a component instrumental to Aristotle's theory. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. The doctrine of the mean.Charles M. Young - 1996 - Topoi 15 (1):89-99.
    English translation, with Chinese source text, of a seminal Chinese classic.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6.  11
    The doctrine of the mean in the eudemian ethics.Inara Zanuzzi - 2017 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 20:255-288.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  43
    The Doctrine of the Mean (Zhongyong) and Division into Three.Pang Pu - 2008 - Contemporary Chinese Thought 40 (4):10-23.
  8. The central doctrine of the mean.Rosalind Hursthouse - 2006 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 96--115.
    The prelims comprise: The Doctrine of the Mean outside Aristotle's Ethical Works The “Mean” in Action and Feeling The Central Doctrine of the Mean Virtue as a Mean Disposition and the Moral Education of the Passions Acknowledgments References Further reading.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  9.  52
    The Doctrine of the Mean in Aristotle's Rhetoric.Lawrence W. Rosenfield - 1965 - Theoria 31 (3):191-198.
  10.  60
    On the Quantitative Doctrine of the Mean.Joe Mintoff - 2013 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (4):445-464.
    Aristotle's doctrine of the mean is expressed in quantitative terms, but this has been hard for some people to take literally, its more elaborate versions sometimes being described as “extremely silly.” Roughly two books of the Nicomachean Ethics are permeated with talk of character traits which are either deficient or excessive, however, and the aim of this paper is to examine how the doctrine might meet the objections of its critics.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  64
    Physiological theory and the doctrine of the mean in Plato and Aristotle.Theodore James Tracy - 1969 - The Hague,: Mouton.
  12. Islamic Ethics and the Doctrine of the Mean.Hossein Atrak - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations at University of Tabriz 8 (14):131-147.
    Originally introduced by Plato and Aristotle, the doctrine of the mean is the most prevalent theory of ethics among Islamic scholars. According to this doctrine, every virtue or excellence of character lies in the observance of the mean, whereas vices are the excess or deficiency of the soul in his functions. Islamic scholars have been influenced by the doctrine, but they have also developed and re-conceptualized it in innovative ways. Kindi, Miskawayh, Avicenna, Raghib Isfahani, Nasir (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  44
    The doctrine of the mean. Confucius - unknown
  14.  30
    The Archer and Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean.Glen Koehn - 2012 - Peitho 3 (1):155-168.
    It is sometimes claimed that Aristotle’s doctrine of the Mean is false or unhelpful: moral virtues are not typically flanked by two opposing vices as he claimed. However, an explicit restatement of Aristotle’s view in terms of sufficiency for an objective reveals that the Mean is more widely applicable than has sometimes been alleged. Understood as a special case of sufficiency, it is essential to many judgments of right and wrong. I consider some objections by Rosalind Hursthouse (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.J. O. Urmson - 1973 - American Philosophical Quarterly 10 (3):223 - 230.
    Aristotle's doctrine of the mean is not a counsel to perform mean or moderate actions. It states that excellence of character is a mean state with regard to the having and displaying of emotions. All emotions are morally neutral; character is shown by displaying emotions on the right occasions, Not too often or too rarely, Not too strongly or too weakly, For sufficient and only sufficient reasons, Etc. The difficulties for such a view presented by justice (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  16. Doctrines of the Mean and the Debate Concerning Skills in Fourth-Century Medicine, Rhetoric and Ethics.D. S. Hutchinson - 1988 - Apeiron 21 (2):17 - 52.
  17.  22
    Iv physiology and the doctrine of the mean in Aristotle.Theodore James Tracy - 1969 - In Physiological theory and the doctrine of the mean in Plato and Aristotle. The Hague,: Mouton. pp. 157-333.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  41
    A Plausible Doctrine of the Mean.Jeffrey J. Fisher - 2018 - Review of Metaphysics 72 (1):53-75.
    While Aristotle is often lauded, especially by virtue ethicists, for his focus on and insight into virtue, a central aspect of his conception of virtue—the doctrine of the mean—is often derided as false if not indeed absurd. The reason for this disparity in reaction to Aristotle is that the doctrine of the mean has been severely misinterpreted as stating that there are a variety of parameters in which one must achieve a mean. Such a (...) is false, but it is not Aristotle’s. In this paper, the author gives a more accurate account of the doctrine of the mean than has heretofore been given. According to this account, the doctrine simply states that virtue disposes one to feel one’s passions with an appropriate intensity. The author closes by considering Hursthouse’s famous criticisms of the doctrine of the mean, and he shows that they fail to be reasons for rejecting the doctrine. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  57
    Aristotle’s Conception of Ethical and Natural Virtue: How the Unity Thesis sheds light on the Doctrine of the Mean.Anselm Winfried Müller - 2004 - In Matthias Lutz-Bachmann & Jan Szaif (eds.), Was Ist Das Für den Menschen Gute? / What is Good for a Human Being?: Menschliche Natur Und Güterlehre / Human Nature and Values. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 18-53.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20.  90
    IV*—A False Doctrine of the Mean.Rosalind Hursthouse - 1981 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 81 (1):57-72.
    Rosalind Hursthouse; IV*—A False Doctrine of the Mean, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 81, Issue 1, 1 June 1981, Pages 57–72, https://doi.org/10.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  21.  56
    The Practical Import of Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.J. E. Tiles - 1992 - Apeiron 25 (4):1 - 14.
  22. Nāgārjuna and the doctrine of "skillful means".John Schroeder - 2000 - Philosophy East and West 50 (4):559-583.
    The role of "skillful means" is examined in relation to the important Mahāyāna philosopher Nāgārjuna, and it is argued that the doctrine of "emptiness" is best understood as a critical reflection on the nature of Buddhist praxis. Whereas traditional Western scholarship sees Nāgārjuna as struggling with certain metaphysical problems, a "skillful means" reading situates his philosophy within a debate about the nature and efficacy of Buddhist practice. Thus, a "skillful means" reading of Nāgārjuna does not ask what it means (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23.  45
    Christian Virtues and the Doctrine of the Mean.Robert B. Kruschwitz - 1986 - Faith and Philosophy 3 (4):416-428.
  24.  13
    The Practical Import of Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.J. E. Tiles - 1995 - Apeiron 28 (4):1-14.
  25.  46
    Nagarjuna and the Doctrine of "Skillful Means".John Schroeder - 2000 - Philosophy East and West 50 (4):559-583.
    The role of "skillful means" is examined in relation to the important Mahāyāna philosopher Nāgārjuna, and it is argued that the doctrine of "emptiness" is best understood as a critical reflection on the nature of Buddhist praxis. Whereas traditional Western scholarship sees Nāgārjuna as struggling with certain metaphysical problems, a "skillful means" reading situates his philosophy within a debate about the nature and efficacy of Buddhist practice. Thus, a "skillful means" reading of Nāgārjuna does not ask what it means (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26. Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.J. O. Urmson - 1973 - [Department of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh].
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  27.  41
    Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature.Nahum Brown - 2016 - Kritike 10 (2):122-131.
    Aristotle's famous claim that human beings are animals with rationality has a subtle and complicated articulation in his doctrine of the mean. This paper offers textual analysis of Aristotle's discussion of the mean as a resource for coming to terms with the thesis that humans naturally deliberate over the essence of their nature. Unlike other animals who tend to act without deliberation and without mediation, human beings are the animals who are capable of giving an account of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. The Doctrine of Descent in Jerónimo Pardo: Meaning, Inference, Truth.Paloma Pérez-Ilzarbe - 1996 - In Ignacio Angelelli & María Cerezo (eds.), Studies on the History of Logic: Proceedings of the III. Symposium on the History of Logic. Berlin, Germany: Walter de Gruyter.
    The complexity of the scholastic view of descent stems from the attempt to find a reply to three different questions at the same time: those pertaining to the meaning of propositions, the relationships of inference between propositions, and the truth conditions of propositions. From each of these issues there arises a different sequence of developments to this doctrine, each of which has its own problems and solutions. Initially, the concept of descent is introduced in response to the problem of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  13
    The doctrine of the intelligent design from the point of view of the cognitive science of religion.Wojciech Piotr Grygiel - 2020 - Scientia et Fides 8 (1):165-181.
    The doctrine of the Intelligent Design offers an intuitive explanation of why the ordering in the Universe is authored by an intentional agency. Due to its appeal to common-sense perception, this doctrine is endorsed even by scientifically literate circles despite of its obvious contradiction with the discoveries of science. In this article, an attempt to apply the tools of the cognitive science of religion to the appraisal of the methodological and epistemic status of the ID doctrine is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  64
    Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.Peter Losin - 1987 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 4 (3):329 - 341.
  31.  41
    When organizations are too good: Applying Aristotle's doctrine of the mean to the corporate ethical virtues model.Muel Kaptein - 2017 - Business Ethics: A European Review 26 (3):300-311.
    Aristotle's doctrine of the mean states that a virtue is the mean state between two vices: a deficient and an excessive one. The Corporate Ethical Virtues Model defines the mean and the corresponding deficient vice for each of its seven virtues. This paper defines for each of these virtues the corresponding excessive vice and explores why organizations characterized by these excessive vices increase the likelihood that their employees will behave unethically. The excessive vices are patronization, pompousness, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  32.  15
    Physiological Theory and the Doctrine of the Mean in Plato and Aristotle. [REVIEW]E. D. Phillips - 1972 - The Classical Review 22 (3):419-420.
  33.  9
    Physiological Theory and the Doctrine of the Mean in Plato and Aristotle. [REVIEW]Anthony Preus - 1970 - Studi Internazionali Di Filosofia 2:181-184.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  13
    Nagarjuna and the Doctrine of "Skillful Means".John Schroeder - 2000 - Philosophy East and West 50 (4):559-583.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Nāgārjuna and the Doctrine of "Skillful Means"John SchroederAlthough a number of Buddhist scholars have examined the doctrine of "skill-in-means" (upāya-kauśalya) in Mahāyāna Buddhist literature, it is surprising that no one has yet developed this important concept in relation to Nāgārjuna. Given that upāya is a central doctrine in the early Mahāyāna texts, and given that Nāgārjuna is a central philosopher of this tradition, it is unfortunate (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. The doctrine of triple effect and why a rational agent need not intend the means to his end, I.Frances M. Kamm - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1):21–39.
    In this article I am concerned with whether it could be morally significant to distinguish between doing something 'in order to bring about an effect' as opposed to 'doing something because we will bring about an effect'. For example, the Doctrine of Double Effect tells us that we should not act in order to bring about evil, but even if this is true is it perhaps permissible to act only because an evil will thus occur? I discuss these questions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  36.  95
    Recent Philosophical Work on the Doctrine of the Eucharist.James M. Arcadi - 2016 - Philosophy Compass 11 (7):402-412.
    The doctrine of the Eucharist has been one of the more fruitful locales of philosophical reflection within Christian theology. The central philosophical question has been, ‘what is the state of affairs such that it is apt to say of a piece of bread, “This is the body of Christ”?’ In this article, I offer a delineation of various families of answers to this question as they have been proffered in the history of the church. These families are distinguished by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  27
    Physiological Theory and the Doctrine of the Mean in Plato and Aristotle. [REVIEW]Anthony Preus - 1970 - Studi Internazionali Di Filosofia 2:181-184.
  38.  21
    The Doctrine of Triple Effect and Why a Rational Agent Need Not Intend the Means to His End.Frances M. Kamm - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:21-39.
    In this article I am concerned with whether it could be morally significant to distinguish between doing something 'in order to bring about an effect' as opposed to 'doing something because we will bring about an effect'. For example, the Doctrine of Double Effect tells us that we should not act in order to bring about evil, but even if this is true is it perhaps permissible to act only because an evil will thus occur? I discuss these questions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  39.  23
    The Doctrine of Triple Effect and Why a Rational Agent Need Not Intend the Means to His End.Frances Kamm & John Harris - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:21-39.
    In this article I am concerned with whether it could be morally significant to distinguish between doing something 'in order to bring about an effect' as opposed to 'doing something because we will bring about an effect'. For example, the Doctrine of Double Effect tells us that we should not act in order to bring about evil, but even if this is true is it perhaps permissible to act only because an evil will thus occur? I discuss these questions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  40.  8
    The Doctrine of Triple Effect and Why a Rational Agent Need Not Intend the Means to His End.Frances Kamm - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:41-57.
    Frances Kamm sets out to draw and make plausible distinctions that would show how and why it is, in some circumstances, permissible to kill some to save many more, but is not so in others. To do so she draws on a famous, and famously artificial, example of Judith Thomson, which illustrates the fact that people intutitively reject some instances of such killings but not others. The irrationality, implausibility and in many cases the self-defeating nature of such distinctions I had (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  41.  57
    The doctrine of triple effect and why a rational agent need not intend the means to his end, II.John Harris - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 (1):41–57.
    In this article I am concerned with whether it could be morally significant to distinguish between doing something 'in order to bring about an effect' as opposed to 'doing something because we will bring about an effect'. For example, the Doctrine of Double Effect tells us that we should not act in order to bring about evil, but even if this is true is it perhaps permissible to act only because an evil will thus occur? I discuss these questions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  8
    Zhong yong yuan lun: ru jia qing gan xing shang xue zhi chuang fa yu qian bian = A study on the doctrine of the mean: the creation and evolution of confucianism's moral.Shaohan Yang - 2015 - Beijing Shi: She hui ke xue wen xian chu ban she.
    《中庸原論:儒家情感形上學之創發與潛變》認為,孔子的心性之學包括兩個部分,即「心學」與「情學」。 儒學內化就是道德情感與良知之心內化為天命之性,成為道德實踐的內在本體和形上根據。 《中庸》作為思孟學派的早期作品,承擔着為儒學建立道德本體和尋找道德終極根源的形上課題。在這兩個課題中,道德情感都具有本質的意義,《中庸》初步建立起來的儒家形上學可以說是一種情感形上學。 宋明時期,孔子的「心學」得到充分發展,朱子是孔子「心學」之認知派,陸王是孔子「心學」之良知派,孔子的「情學」卻隱而不彰。 直到明末,劉蕺山才重新認識到道德情感的重要地位,並在一定程度上復歸了思孟學派心性情為一的義理結構。 楊少涵,河南桐柏人,副教授,碩士生導師。1999年7月畢業於鄭州大學,獲文學學士學位。2006年3月畢業於南京政治學院上海分院,獲哲學碩士學位。2009年6月畢業於上海復旦大學,獲哲學博士學位。201 1年6月於上海師范大學博士后出站。現任為華僑大學哲學與社會發展學院副教授。先后在《哲學研究》、《光明日報》等報刊上發表論文二十余篇。校理古籍《中庸集說》(衛湜著,漓江出版社,2011年)一部。.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  6
    The Doctrine of the Resurrection of the Body in the Theological Thought of Thomas Burnet.Ciprian Simuţ - 2020 - Perichoresis 18 (2):31-45.
    The issue of the resurrection of the body has given rise to a plethora of interpretations. There is a natural need to clarify such issues, since there cannot be a separation between faith in Christ and the resurrection of the body. The two go hand in hand, because one cannot go without the other. In the context of debates spawned by the need to understand, Thomas Burnet seems like a study theologian and a clean hearted man, who wrote for the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  43
    An Aristotelian Doctrine of the Mean in the Mencius?Howard J. Curzer - 2012 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 11 (1):53-62.
    Xiahui. While Confucius’ actions are intermediate between the actions of these three sages, the sages’ character traits do not bracket Confucius’ character traits. Instead, the failings of the three sages are skew to each other. Boyi lacks righteousness; Y i Yin lacks benevolence; and L iu Xiahui lacks wisdom. The comparison of the sages centers on the question of when to resign an advisory position. According to Mencius, one should resign only if one’s advice will not be heeded, or if (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  33
    On Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean - A Criticism against the Doctrine of the Moderation -. 김도형 - 2019 - Journal of Ethics: The Korean Association of Ethics 1 (124):37-55.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  17
    The Doctrine of Triple Effect and Why a Rational Agent Need Not Intend the Means to His End.John Harris - 2000 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74:41-57.
    Frances Kamm sets out to draw and make plausible distinctions that would show how and why it is, in some circumstances, permissible to kill some to save many more, but is not so in others. To do so she draws on a famous, and famously artificial, example of Judith Thomson, which illustrates the fact that people intutitively reject some instances of such killings but not others. The irrationality, implausibility and in many cases the self-defeating nature of such distinctions I had (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47.  8
    9. Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.J. O. Urmson - 1980 - In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. University of California Press. pp. 157-170.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48.  76
    Commentary on Charles M. young's “the doctrine of the mean”.J. David Blankenship - 1996 - Topoi 15 (1):101-106.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The Doctrine of Double Effect: Intention and Permissibility.William J. FitzPatrick - 2012 - Philosophy Compass 7 (3):183-196.
    The Doctrine of Double Effect (DDE) is an influential non-consequentialist principle positing a role for intention in affecting the moral permissibility of some actions. In particular, the DDE focuses on the intend/foresee distinction, the core claim being that it is sometimes permissible to bring about as a foreseen but unintended side-effect of one’s action some harm it would have been impermissible to aim at as a means or as an end, all else being equal. This article explores the meaning (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  50. Revising the Doctrine of Double Effect.Jeff McMahan - 1994 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 11 (2):201-212.
    The Doctrine of Double Effect has been challenged by the claim that what an agent intends as a means may be limited to those effects that are precisely characterized by the descriptions under which the agent believes that they are minimally causally necessary for the production of other effects that the agent seeks to bring about. If based on so narrow a conception of an intended means, the traditional Doctrine of Double Effect becomes limitlessly permissive. In this paper (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000