Results for 'consequentia'

49 found
Order:
  1. La" consequentia mirabilis": desarrollo histórico e implantaciones filosóficas.Ignacio Miralbell - 1987 - Thémata: Revista de Filosofía 4:79-96.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  4
    Consequentia mirabilis: una regola logica tra matematica e filosofia.Fabio Bellissima & Paolo Pagli - 1996 - Firenze: L.S. Olschki. Edited by Paolo Pagli.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3. Le consequentiae nella logica medievale.Lorenzo Pozzi - 1978 - Padova: Liviana.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  30
    Hegel and the Consequentia Mirabilis.Elena Ficara - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (4):357-364.
    In this paper I argue that Hegel’s treatment of dialectical inferences, in particular of Plato’s dialectics in the Lectures on the History of Philosophy, belongs to the history of the logical rule that, from Gerolamo Cardano to Bertrand Russell, is known as consequentia mirabilis. In 1906 Russell formalises it as follows: and its correspondent positive form as My paper has two parts. First, I show that dialectical inferences, for Hegel, involve sentences of the form and. Hegel, following Plato, stresses (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  16
    Consequentia mirabilis: Una regola logica tra matematica e filosofia. Fabio Bellissima, Paolo Pagli.Carla Rita Palmerino - 1998 - Isis 89 (4):715-716.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  24
    Consequentia Mirabilis, Antiskeptizismus und Antinomien Über Bolzanos Beweis, daß es wenigstens eine Wahrheit an sich, daß es der Wahrheiten mehre, ja unendlich viele gebe.Stefania Centrone - 2012 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 66 (4):539-565.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  10
    There is no consequentia mirabilis in Greek mathematics.F. Acerbi - 2019 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 73 (3):217-242.
    The paper shows that, contrary to what has been held since the sixteenth-century mathematician Christoph Clavius, there is no application of consequentia mirabilis (CM) in Greek mathematical works. This is shown by means of a detailed discussion of the logical structure of the proofs where CM is allegedly employed. The point is further enlarged to a critical assessment of the unsound methodology applied by many interpreters in seeking for specific logical rules at work in ancient mathematical texts.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  23
    Entailment and Truthmaking: The Consequentia Rerum from Boethius to the Ars Meliduna.Enrico Donato - forthcoming - History and Philosophy of Logic:1-15.
    In Categories 12 (14b11–22), Aristotle famously claims that [1] true sentences and reality stand in a mutually implicative relationship, and that [2] reality causes the truth of sentences but not vice versa. In this paper, I first argue that Boethius’ reading of the above passage led medieval logicians to assess [1] and [2] within the framework of a theory of consequence. Then, I consider two important questions raised by Boethius and later logicians in relation to [1] and [2], and, namely, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  48
    Buridan's consequentia: consequence and inference within a token-based semantics.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2005 - History and Philosophy of Logic 26 (4):277-297.
    I examine the theory of consequentia of the medieval logician, John Buridan. Buridan advocates a strict commitment to what we now call proposition-tokens as the bearers of truth-value. The analysis of Buridan's theory shows that, within a token-based semantics, amendments to the usual notions of inference and consequence are made necessary, since pragmatic elements disrupt the semantic behaviour of propositions. In my reconstruction of Buridan's theory, I use some of the apparatus of modern two-dimensional semantics, such as two-dimensional matrices (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  10. Proposizioni condizionali," consequentiae" e paradossi dell'implicazione in Paolo Veneto.F. Bottin - 1976 - Medioevo 2:289-330.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  33
    Robert Fland's Consequentiae: An Edition.Paul Vincent Spade - 1976 - Mediaeval Studies 38 (1):54-84.
  12.  24
    On Some Consequentiae in Walter Burleigh.Arthur N. Prior - 1953 - New Scholasticism 27 (4):433-446.
  13.  10
    Consequentia mirabilis: Una regola logica tra matematica e filosofia by Fabio Bellissima; Paolo Pagli. [REVIEW]Carla Palmerino - 1998 - Isis 89:715-716.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Robert Fland's Consequentiae.Spade Pv - 1976 - Mediaeval Studies 38:54-84.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  52
    Formalizing medieval logic: Suppositio, consequentiae and obligationes (review).Mary Sirridge - 2009 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (3):pp. 469-470.
    The overarching aim of this excellent book is to demonstrate the common ground between medieval logic and logical theories of the twentieth century by analyzing some important medieval approaches to three important topics in medieval logic and then showing that in each case, once we determine what is really going on in the medieval theory, it can be formalized in such a way as to show how it resembles one or more developments in twentieth-century logical theory. Analysis in terms of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  75
    Formalizing Medieval Logical Theories: Suppositio, Consequentiae and Obligationes.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2007 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This book presents novel formalizations of three of the most important medieval logical theories: supposition, consequence and obligations. In an additional fourth part, an in-depth analysis of the concept of formalization is presented - a crucial concept in the current logical panorama, which as such receives surprisingly little attention.Although formalizations of medieval logical theories have been proposed earlier in the literature, the formalizations presented here are all based on innovative vantage points: supposition theories as algorithmic hermeneutics, theories of consequence analyzed (...)
  17.  56
    Marsilius of Inghen on the Definition of consequentia.Graziana Ciola - 2018 - Vivarium 56 (3-4):272-291.
    _ Source: _Volume 56, Issue 3-4, pp 272 - 291 This paper offers an analysis of Marsilius of Inghen’s definition of _consequentia_ and of his treatment of logical validity as presented in the first book of his treatise on _Consequentiae_. Comparing Marsilius of Inghen’s, John Buridan’s, and Albert of Saxony’s theories, the author argues that Marsilius’ account is based on a conception of consequence as a relation of entailment among propositions rather than as a type of conditional sentence and, thus, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  36
    Later Medieval Consequentiae.Joseph T. Clark - 1952 - Philosophical Studies of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 3:53-53.
  19.  42
    William of Ockham and Consequentiae.Joseph T. Clark - 1952 - Philosophical Studies of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 3:54-55.
  20.  37
    Charles S. Peirce and the Medieval Doctrine of consequentiae.Francesco Bellucci - 2016 - History and Philosophy of Logic 37 (3):244-268.
    In 1898 C. S. Peirce declares that the medieval doctrine of consequences had been the starting point of his logical investigations in the 1860s. This paper shows that Peirce studied the scholastic theory of consequentiae as early as 1866–67, that he adopted the scholastics’ terminology, and that that theory constituted a source of logical doctrine that sustained Peirce for a lifetime of creative and original work.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  26
    Marsilius of Inghen on incipit and desinit in Consequentiae II, Chapters 4-5.Graziana Ciola - 2017 - Vivarium 55 (1-3):170-198.
    In this paper, the author offers an introduction to Marsilius of Inghen’s treatment of expositiones of sentences de incipit and de desinit in his treatise on Consequentiae, with an analysis of the various modi exponendi presented by Marsilius and an edition of the text. The author argues that, in the split between physical and logical approaches to the issues arising in analyses of incipit and desinit, Marsilius’ theory presents some hybrid features, but tends towards the logical end of the spectrum.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  6
    Bellisima, Fabio / Pagli, Paolo: Consequentia Mirabilis. Una regola logica tra matematica e filosofia, Leo S. Olschki, Firenze, 1996, 231 págs. [REVIEW]Carlos Ortiz de Landázuri - 1998 - Anuario Filosófico:878-880.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  47
    A 17th-century debate on the consequentia mirabilis.Gabriel Nuchelmans - 1992 - History and Philosophy of Logic 13 (1):43-58.
    In modern times the so?called consequentia mirabilis (if not-P, then P). then P) was first enthusiastically applied and commented upon by Cardano (1570) and Clavius (1574). Of later passages where it occurs Saccheri?s use (1697) has drawn a good deal of attention. It is less known that about the middle of the 17th century this remarkable mode of arguing became the subject of an interesting debate, in which the Belgian mathematician Andreas Tacquet and Christiaan Huygens were the main representatives (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  13
    Formalizing Medieval Logic: Suppositio, Consequentiae and Obligationes : Dutilh NovaesCatarina.Formalizing medieval logical theories: suppositio, consequentiae and obligationes. [REVIEW]Mary Sirridge - 2009 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (3):469-470.
  25.  51
    Form and Matter in Later Latin Medieval Logic: The Cases of Suppositio and Consequentia.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2012 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 50 (3):339-364.
  26. Note sur une maxime cartésienne «A nosse ad esse valet consequentia», AT, VII, 520, 5.Dan Arbib - 2013 - Revue Philosophique De Louvain 111 (3):491-512.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  30
    A further examination of Saccheri's use of the "consequentia mirabilis".Cyril F. A. Hoormann - 1976 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 17 (2):239-247.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  20
    Ab Esse ad Posse Non Valet Consequentia.Daniel Dohrn - 2024 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 53 (2):391-409.
    While knowledge of mere possibilities is difficult to understand, knowledge of possibilities that are actual seems unproblematic (as far as we know the actual world). The principle that what is actual is possible has been near-universally accepted. After summarizing some sporadic dissent, I present a proposal for how the validity of the principle might be restricted. While the principle certainly holds for sufficiently inclusive objective and epistemic possibilities, it may not hold when the accessibility of possibilities is contextually restricted.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  17
    The Scholastic Logic of Statistical Hypotheses: proprietates terminorum, consequentiae, necessitas moralis, and probabilitas.Miroslav Hanke - 2019 - Journal of Early Modern Studies 8 (1):61-82.
    Among the important conceptual innovations introduced in the second scholasticism era and motivated by theological debates following the Council of Trent were the theories of moral necessity and moral implication. As they were centred upon a view of moral necessity as a form of necessity weaker than physical necessity, and moral implication as weaker than physical implication, some interpretations of moral necessity encouraged the logic of statistical hypotheses and probability. Three branches of this debate are studied in this paper: the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  27
    Ockham's Inventory of Bonae Consequentiae.Joseph T. Clark - 1952 - Philosophical Studies of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 3:55-59.
  31.  55
    Formalizing Medieval Logical Theories: Suppositio, Consequentiae and Obligationes. [REVIEW]Mikko Yrjönsuuri - 2009 - Vivarium 47 (4):480-482.
  32.  13
    Review: A. N. Prior, The Logic of Negative Terms in Boethius; A. N. Prior, On Some Consequentiae in Walter Burleigh. [REVIEW]Johannes Bendiek - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 20 (1):83-83.
  33. La regola del descensus. Un esempio di procedura logica di prova nel Medioevo.Alfredo Di Giorgio - 2013 - In Alfredo Di Giorgio & Daniele Chiffi (eds.), Prova e Giustificazione. Torino TO, Italia: pp. 19-50.
    In epoca medievale si è molto discusso su alcuni concetti chiave come prova o giustificazione. La teoria della prova contenuta nei trattati di logica medievale prende il nome tecnico di consequentia, che è un tipo di ragionamento fondato sul passaggio dalla concessione (o negazione) di uno o più enunciati denominati antecedenti alla concessione (o negazione) di uno o più enunciati denominati conseguenti. Questo tipo di teoria ha avuto un correlato a livello dei singoli termini che compongono l’enunciato all'interno della (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Ex impossibili quodlibet sequitur.Calvin G. Normore - 2015 - Vivarium 53 (2-4):353-371.
    _ Source: _Volume 53, Issue 2-4, pp 353 - 371 While agreeing with Professor D’Ors’ thesis that the notion of logical consequence cannot be exhaustively characterized, I depart from Professor d’Ors’ conclusion that the very notion of good consequence is primitive and can only be identified with the set of acceptable rules of inference, and from his conviction that modal notions such as necessity and impossibility are equivocal and gain such clarity as they have by their interaction with rules of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. Providence in St. Albert the Great.David Torrijos-Castrillejo - 2016 - Revista Ciências da Religião: História E Sociedade 14:14-44.
    In these pages, we expose the main traits of St. Albert the Great’s doctrine of providence and fate, considered by Palazzo the keystone of his philosophical system. To describe it we examine his systematic works, primarily his Summa of Theology. His discussion follows clearly the guidelines of the Summa of Alexander of Hales, in order to delve into the set of problems faced over the centuries by theological tradition. Albert also restates the reflections of different authors like Boethius or Saint (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  19
    Contingentia Mundi. Leibniz on the World's Contingency.Nicholas Rescher - 2001 - Studia Leibnitiana 33 (2):145 - 162.
    Leibniz' Metaphysik sieht sich mit folgender Aporie konfrontiert: (1) Notwendigerweise gilt: Gott verwirklicht die beste mögliche Wahl. (2) Notwendigerweise gilt: die mögliche Welt, die auf die Beschreibung der tatsächlichen Welt antwortet, ist die beste aller möglichen Welten. (3) Die Existenz der tatsächlichen Welt (als die von Gott erschaffene) ist nicht notwendig, sondern möglich. Diese drei Sätze - die alle von Leibniz anerkannt worden sind - sind gemeinsam allem Anschein nach inkonsistent. Um diese Inkonsistenz zu vermeiden, entwickelt Leibniz eine komplexe Strategie, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37. Miracles and the Laws of Nature.George I. Mavrodes - 1985 - Faith and Philosophy 2 (4):333-346.
    Construing miracles as “violations,” I argue that a law of nature must specify some kind of possibility. But we must have here a sense of possibility for which the ancient rule of logic---ab esse ad posse valet consequentia---does not hold. We already have one example associated with the concept of statute law, a law which specifies what is legally possible but which is not destroyed by a violation. If laws of nature are construed as specifying some analogous sense of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  10
    Buridan on ‘Ex impossibili quodlibet’, ‘Ex contradictione quodlibet’, and ‘Ex falso quodlibet’.Wolfgang Lenzen - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    Buridan endorsed the principles that any impossible, and a fortiori any self-contradictory, proposition entails each proposition. These principles are usually referred to as ‘Ex impossibili quodlibet’ (EIQ) and ‘Ex contradictione quodlibet’ (ECQ). Buridan further considered the instance ECCQ according to which any proposition follows from the conjunction of two contradictory propositions. Buridan showed how ECCQ can be proven by means the usual laws of conjunction and disjunction. Furthermore, he discovered that EIQ can be derived from ECCQ by means of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Miracles and laws of nature.E. J. Lowe - 1987 - Religious Studies 23 (2):263-78.
    Construing miracles as \textquotedblleft{}violations,\textquotedblright I argue that a law of nature must specify some kind of possibility. But we must have here a sense of possibility for which the ancient rule of logic---ab esse ad posse valet consequentia---does not hold. We already have one example associated with the concept of statute law, a law which specifies what is legally possible but which is not destroyed by a violation. If laws of nature are construed as specifying some analogous sense of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  40.  29
    Das Problem der apagogischen Beweise in Bolzanos Beyträgen und seiner Wissenschaftslehre.Stefania Centrone - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (2):127 - 157.
    This paper analyzes and evaluates Bolzano's remarks on the apagogic method of proof with reference to his juvenile booklet "Contributions to a better founded presentation of mathematics" of 1810 and to his ?Theory of science? (1837). I shall try to defend the following contentions: (1) Bolzanos vain attempt to transform all indirect proofs into direct proofs becomes comprehensible as soon as one recognizes the following facts: (1.1) his attitude towards indirect proofs with an affirmative conclusion differs from his stance to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  29
    The Analysis of Deductive Validity in Martin Le Maistre’s Tractatus consequentiarum.Miroslav Hanke - 2014 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 88 (1):29-46.
    The paper focuses on the concepts of truth, truth-making and truth-preservation and their role in defining deductive validity as analysed by the late-medieval nominalist scholar Martin Le Maistre in his Tractatus consequentiarum. This treatise, examined from the point of view of fourteenth-century British and Parisian influences, can be characterised as a critical adoption of the previous logical tradition and as the analysis of validity in term of truth-preservation. Part of this analysis is a study of self-referential phenomena, in particular, of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  18
    Pono tibi istam:“Tu curris”. Uno sguardo alla teoria medievale delle obbligazioni.Riccardo Strobino - 2008 - Doctor Virtualis 8:139-161.
    La teoria delle obbligazioni rappresenta un significativo esempio di come un insieme di tecniche logiche possa essere applicato, in maniera feconda, a contesti disputazionali in cui la dimensione dialogica e l’interazione tra soggetti coinvolti in un confronto dialettico hanno un ruolo di primo piano.L’attenzione che numerosi studiosi hanno manifestato nei confronti di questa parte della logica modernorum negli ultimi quarat’anni testimonia la profondità e la difficoltà dei problemi teorici che stanno alla base della teoria.Molte interpretazioni sono state avanzate circa le (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Peirce and Philo.Jay Zeman - manuscript
    conditional with his discussions of the hypothetical proposition. Peirce spoke often of the consequentia de inesse ,1 the concept of which is intimately linked with the material, or "Philonian" conditional; indeed, we shall see him calling himself a Philonian. And it is not uncommon to hear Peirce—at least prior to the last decade of his life—declared a Philonian, whose fundamental analysis of the conditional was essentially the same as that of Philo (and of more modern types like Russell and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Die Unterscheidung zwischen einfacher und bedingter Notwendigkeit in der Philosophiae Consolatio des Boethius.Hermann Weidemann - 1998 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 1.
    In this paper I shall attempt to show that the difference which Boethius has in mind when distinguishing between conditional and simple necessity in the fifth book of Philosophiae Consolatio is not, as already Thomas Aquinas presumed, the difference between a necessitas consequentiae and the corresponding necessitas consequentis, but rather the difference between the necessity of a given state of affairs which is necessary in the sense that at the moment of its existence its present existence is unchangeable, and the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  57
    Vollkommene Syllogismen und reine Vernunftschlüsse: Aristoteles und Kant. Eine Stellungnahme zu Theodor Eberts Gegeneinwänden. Teil 2.Michael Wolff - 2010 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 41 (2):359 - 371.
    In an earlier article (see J Gen Philos Sei (2010) 41: 341-355) I have compared Aristotle's syllogistic with Kant's theory of "pure ratiocination". "Ratiocinia pura" („reine Vernunftschlüsse") is Kant's designation for assertoric syllogisms Aristotle has called 'perfect'. In Kant's view they differ from non-pure ratiocinia precisely in that their validity rests only on the validity of the Dictum de omni et nullo (which, however, in Kant's view can be further reduced to more fundamental principles) whereas the validity of non-pure ratiocinia (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  9
    The contingency of prophetic semantics in Walter Chatton’s Lectura.Jon Bornholdt - 2022 - Bochumer Philosophisches Jahrbuch Fur Antike Und Mittelalter 25 (1):78-97.
    This paper examines Walter Chatton’s discussion of the problem of prophesied future contingents in his Lectura super Sententias. Faced with the challenge of reconciling the supposedly veridical character of divine prophecy with human freedom to do otherwise, Chatton casts the relation of prophecy to event in the form of a logical consequentia and formulates two rules which depend on the character of the antecedent in question. In the case of antecedents involving divine knowledge and related phenomena, the freedom of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  6
    Das Problem der apagogischen Beweise in Bolzanos Beyträgen_ und seiner _Wissenschaftslehre.Stefania Centrone - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (2):127-157.
    This paper analyzes and evaluates Bolzano's remarks on the apagogic method of proof with reference to his juvenile booklet ‘Contributions to a better founded presentation of mathematics’ of 1810 and to his ‘Theory of science’ (1837). I shall try to defend the following contentions: (1) Bolzanos’ vain attempt to transform all indirect proofs into direct proofs becomes comprehensible as soon as one recognizes the following facts: (1.1) his attitude towards indirect proofs with an affirmative conclusion differs from his stance to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  22
    Zur Pariser Philosophie des Spätmittelalters und ihrer zeitgenössischen Rezeption.Harald Berger - 2015 - Bulletin de Philosophie Medievale 57:265-325.
    This study based on manuscripts uncovers a network of Parisian Masters of Arts of the late fourteenth and early fifteenth centuries, especially in the period covered by the missing fifth Register of the English Nation of the Parisian Arts Faculty. Outstanding masters are Henry of Oy, Christian of Paris, John of Hokelem, James of Yvia, John of Paris and others. The life and work of John of Hokelem are critically studied here for the first time. The dominating figure is, however, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Three Conceptions of Formal Logic.Thom Paul - 2010 - Vivarium 48 (1-2):228-242.
    Aristotle's logical and metaphysical works contain elements of three distinct types of formal theory: an ontology, a theory of consequences, and a theory of reasoning. His formal ontology (unlike that of certain later thinkers) does not require all propositions of a given logical form to be true. His formal syllogistic (unlike medieval theories of consequences) was guided primarily by a conception of logic as a theory of reasoning; and his fragmentary theory of consequences exists merely as an adjunct to the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark