Results for 'Jeffrey Ketland'

(not author) ( search as author name )
1000+ found
Order:
  1. Empirical adequacy and ramsification.Jeffrey Ketland - 2004 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55 (2):287-300.
    Structural realism has been proposed as an epistemological position interpolating between realism and sceptical anti-realism about scientific theories. The structural realist who accepts a scientific theory thinks that is empirically correct, and furthermore is a realist about the ‘structural content’ of . But what exactly is ‘structural content’? One proposal is that the ‘structural content’ of a scientific theory may be associated with its Ramsey sentence (). However, Demopoulos and Friedman have argued, using ideas drawn from Newman's earlier criticism of (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  2. Deflationism and Tarski’s Paradise.Jeffrey Ketland - 1999 - Mind 108 (429):69-94.
    Deflationsism about truth is a pot-pourri, variously claiming that truth is redundant, or is constituted by the totality of 'T-sentences', or is a purely logical device (required solely for disquotational purposes or for re-expressing finitarily infinite conjunctions and/or disjunctions). In 1980, Hartry Field proposed what might be called a 'deflationary theory of mathematics', in which it is alleged that all uses of mathematics within science are dispensable. Field's criterion for the dispensability of mathematics turns on a property of theories, called (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  3. Structuralism and the identity of indiscernibles.Jeffrey Ketland - 2006 - Analysis 66 (4):303-315.
  4. Yablo’s Paradox and ω-Inconsistency.Jeffrey Ketland - 2005 - Synthese 145 (3):295-302.
    It is argued that Yablo’s Paradox is not strictly paradoxical, but rather ‘ω-paradoxical’. Under a natural formalization, the list of Yablo sentences may be constructed using a diagonalization argument and can be shown to be ω-inconsistent, but nonetheless consistent. The derivation of an inconsistency requires a uniform fixed-point construction. Moreover, the truth-theoretic disquotational principle required is also uniform, rather than the local disquotational T-scheme. The theory with the local disquotation T-scheme applied to individual sentences from the Yablo list is also (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  5. Deflationism and the gödel phenomena: Reply to Tennant.Jeffrey Ketland - 2005 - Mind 114 (453):75-88.
    Any (1-)consistent and sufficiently strong system of first-order formal arithmetic fails to decide some independent Gödel sentence. We examine consistent first-order extensions of such systems. Our purpose is to discover what is minimally required by way of such extension in order to be able to prove the Gödel sentence in a nontrivial fashion. The extended methods of formal proof must capture the essentials of the so-called 'semantical argument' for the truth of the Gödel sentence. We are concerned to show that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  6. Identity and indiscernibility.Jeffrey Ketland - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (2):171-185.
    The notion of strict identity is sometimes given an explicit second-order definition: objects with all the same properties are identical. Here, a somewhat different problem is raised: Under what conditions is the identity relation on the domain of a structure first-order definable? A structure may have objects that are distinct, but indiscernible by the strongest means of discerning them given the language (the indiscernibility formula). Here a number of results concerning the indiscernibility formula, and the definability of identity, are collected (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  7.  33
    Foundations of applied mathematics I.Jeffrey Ketland - 2021 - Synthese 199 (1-2):4151-4193.
    This paper aims to study the foundations of applied mathematics, using a formalized base theory for applied mathematics: ZFCAσ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$ \mathsf {ZFCA}_{\sigma }$$\end{document} with atoms, where the subscript used refers to a signature specific to the application. Examples are given, illustrating the following five features of applied mathematics: comprehension principles, application conditionals, representation hypotheses, transfer principles and abstract equivalents.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  62
    Empirical adequacy and ramsification, II.Jeffrey Ketland - 2009 - In Hieke Alexander & Leitgeb Hannes (eds.), Reduction, Abstraction, Analysis. Ontos Verlag. pp. 29--45.
  9. Bueno and Colyvan on Yablo’s Paradox.Jeffrey Ketland - 2004 - Analysis 64 (2):165–172.
    This is a response to a paper “Paradox without satisfaction”, Analysis 63, 152-6 (2003) by Otavio Bueno and Mark Colyvan on Yablo’s paradox. I argue that this paper makes several substantial mathematical errors which vitiate the paper. (For the technical details, see [12] below.).
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  10. Can a many-valued language functionally represent its own semantics?Jeffrey Ketland - 2003 - Analysis 63 (4):292–297.
    Tarski’s Indefinability Theorem can be generalized so that it applies to many-valued languages. We introduce a notion of strong semantic self-representation applicable to any (sufficiently rich) interpreted many-valued language L. A sufficiently rich interpreted many-valued language L is SSSR just in case it has a function symbol n(x) such that, for any f Sent(L), the denotation of the term n(“f”) in L is precisely ||f||L, the semantic value of f in L. By a simple diagonal construction (finding a sentence l (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11. Some more curious inferences.Jeffrey Ketland - 2005 - Analysis 65 (1):18–24.
    The following inference is valid: There are exactly 101 dalmatians, There are exactly 100 food bowls, Each dalmatian uses exactly one food bowl Hence, at least two dalmatians use the same food bowl. Here, “there are at least 101 dalmatians” is nominalized as, "x1"x2…."x100$y(Dy & y ¹ x1 & y ¹ x2 & … & y ¹ x100) and “there are exactly 101 dalmatians” is nominalized as, "x1"x2…."x100$y(Dy & y ¹ x1 & y ¹ x2 & … & y ¹ (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  12.  13
    Bases for Structures and Theories I.Jeffrey Ketland - 2020 - Logica Universalis 14 (3):357-381.
    Sometimes structures or theories are formulated with different sets of primitives and yet are definitionally equivalent. In a sense, the transformations between such equivalent formulations are rather like basis transformations in linear algebra or co-ordinate transformations in geometry. Here an analogous idea is investigated. Let a relational signature \ be given. For a set \ of \-formulas, we introduce a corresponding set \ of new relation symbols and a set of explicit definitions of the \ in terms of the \. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  58
    There's Glory for You!Jeffrey Ketland - 2014 - Philosophy 89 (1):3-29.
    This dialogue concerns metasemantics and language cognition. It defends a Lewisian conception of languages as abstract entities (Lewis 1975), arguing that semantic facts are necessities (Soames 1984), and therefore not naturalistically reducible. It identifies spoken languages as idiolects, in line roughly with Chomskyan I-languages. It relocates traditional metasemantic indeterminacy arguments as indeterminacies of what language an agent speaks or cognizes. Finally, it aims to provide a theoretical analysis of the cognizing relation in terms of the agent's assigning certain meanings to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  79
    VI—Nominalistic Adequacy.Jeffrey Ketland - 2011 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111 (2pt2):201-217.
    Instrumentalist nominalism responds to the indispensability arguments by rejecting the demand that successful mathematicized scientific theories be nominalized, and instead claiming merely that such theories are nominalistically adequate: the concreta behave ‘as if’ the theory is true. This article examines some definitions of the concept of nominalistic adequacy and concludes with some considerations against instrumentalist nominalism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  21
    Geoffrey Stokes: Popper: Philosophy, Politics and Scientific Method. [REVIEW]Jeffrey Ketland - 2000 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (2):363-369.
  16. Truth and provability again.Jeffrey Ketland & Panu Raatikainen - manuscript
    Lucas and Redhead ([2007]) announce that they will defend the views of Redhead ([2004]) against the argument by Panu Raatikainen ([2005]). They certainly re-state the main claims of Redhead ([2004]), but they do not give any real arguments in their favour, and do not provide anything that would save Redhead’s argument from the serious problems pointed out in (Raatikainen [2005]). Instead, Lucas and Redhead make a number of seemingly irrelevant points, perhaps indicating a failure to understand the logico-mathematical points at (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  5
    Empirical Adequacy and Ramsification, II.Jeffrey Ketland - 2009 - In Alexander Hieke & Hannes Leitgeb (eds.), Reduction, abstraction, analysis: proceedings of the 31th International Ludwig Wittgenstein-Symposium in Kirchberg, 2008. Frankfurt: de Gruyter. pp. 29-46.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18. On Wright’s Inductive Definition of Coherence Truth for Arithmetic.Jeffrey Ketland - 2003 - Analysis 63 (1):6-15.
    In “Truth – A Traditional Debate Reviewed”, Crispin Wright proposed an inductive definition of “coherence truth” for arithmetic relative to an arithmetic base theory B. Wright’s definition is in fact a notational variant of the usual Tarskian inductive definition, except for the basis clause for atomic sentences. This paper provides a model-theoretic characterization of the resulting sets of sentences "cohering" with a given base theory B. These sets are denoted WB. Roughly, if B satisfies a certain minimal condition, then WB (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. A proof of the (strengthened) liar formula in a semantical extension of peano arithmetic.Jeffrey Ketland - 2000 - Analysis 60 (1):1–4.
    In the Tarskian theory of truth, the strengthened liar sentence is a theorem. More generally, any formalized truth theory which proves the full, self-applicative scheme True(“f”) f will prove the strengthened liar sentence. (This scheme is sometimes called (T-Out).).
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  35
    A Proof of the (Strengthened) Liar Formula in a Semantical Extension of Peano Arithmetic.Jeffrey Ketland - 2000 - Analysis 60 (1):1-4.
    In the Tarskian theory of truth, the strengthened liar sentence is a theorem. More generally, any formalized truth theory which proves the full, self-applicative scheme True f will prove the strengthened liar sentence..).
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  31
    Conservativeness and translation-dependent T-schemes.Jeffrey Ketland - 2000 - Analysis 60 (4):319-328.
    Certain translational T-schemes of the form True « f, where f can be almost any translation you like of f, will be a conservative extension of Peano arithmetic. I have an inkling that this means something philosophically, but I don’t understand my own inkling.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22. How weak is the t-scheme?Jeffrey Ketland - manuscript
    Theorem 1 of Ketland 1999 is not quite correct as stated. The theorem would imply that the disquotational T-scheme – suitably restricted to avoid the liar paradox – is conservative over pure logic. But it has been pointed out (e.g. Halbach 2001, “How Innocent is Deflationism?”, Synthese 126, pp. 179-181) that this is not the case, for one can prove ∃x∃y(x ≠ y) from the T-scheme (lemma 2 below).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  74
    Beth's theorem and deflationism — reply to Bays.Jeffrey Ketland - 2009 - Mind 118 (472):1075-1079.
    Is the restricted, consistent, version of the T-scheme sufficient for an ‘implicit definition’ of truth? In a sense, the answer is yes (Haack 1978 , Quine 1953 ). Section 4 of Ketland 1999 mentions this but gives a result saying that the T-scheme does not implicitly define truth in the stronger sense relevant for Beth’s Definability Theorem. This insinuates that the T-scheme fares worse than the compositional truth theory as an implicit definition. However, the insinuation is mistaken. For, as (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Hume = small Hume.Jeffrey Ketland - 2002 - Analysis 62 (1):92–93.
    We can modify Hume’s Principle in the same manner that George Boolos suggested for modifying Frege’s Basic Law V. This leads to the principle Small Hume. Then, we can show that Small Hume is interderivable with Hume’s Principle.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  25
    Standard Formalization.Jeffrey Ketland - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (3):711-748.
    A standard formalization of a scientific theory is a system of axioms for that theory in a first-order language (possibly many-sorted; possibly with the membership primitive $$\in$$ ). Suppes (in: Carvallo M (ed) Nature, cognition and system II. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1992) expressed skepticism about whether there is a “simple or elegant method” for presenting mathematicized scientific theories in such a standard formalization, because they “assume a great deal of mathematics as part of their substructure”. The major difficulties amount to these. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  94
    A comment on bermúdez concerning the definability of identity.Jeffrey Ketland - 2007 - Analysis 67 (4):315–318.
    No categories
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  9
    Bases for Structures and Theories II.Jeffrey Ketland - 2020 - Logica Universalis 14 (4):461-479.
    In Part I of this paper, I assumed we begin with a signature $$P = \{P_i\}$$ P = { P i } and the corresponding language $$L_P$$ L P, and introduced the following notions: a definition system$$d_{\Phi }$$ d Φ for a set of new predicate symbols $$Q_i$$ Q i, given by a set $$\Phi = \{\phi _i\}$$ Φ = { ϕ i } of defining $$L_P$$ L P -formulas \leftrightarrow \phi _i)$$ ∀ x ¯ ↔ ϕ i ) ); (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  32
    Computation and Indispensability.Jeffrey Ketland - forthcoming - Logic and Logical Philosophy:1.
    This article provides a computational example of a mathematical explanation within science, concerning computational equivalence of programs. In addition, it outlines the logical structure of the reasoning involved in explanations in applied mathematics. It concludes with a challenge that the nominalist provide a nominalistic explanation for the computational equivalence of certain programs.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  86
    Conservativeness and translation-dependent t-schemes.Jeffrey Ketland - 2000 - Analysis 60 (4):319–328.
    Certain translational T-schemes of the form True(“f”) « f(f), where f(f) can be almost any translation you like of f, will be a conservative extension of Peano arithmetic. I have an inkling that this means something philosophically, but I don’t understand my own inkling.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  84
    Craig’s Theorem.Jeffrey Ketland - unknown
    In mathematical logic, Craig’s Theorem states that any recursively enumerable theory is recursively axiomatizable. Its epistemological interest concerns its possible use as a method of eliminating “theoretical content” from scientific theories.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Jacquette on Grelling’s Paradox.Jeffrey Ketland - 2005 - Analysis 65 (3):258–260.
    This discusses a mistake (concerning what a definition is) in “Grelling’s revenge”, Analysis 64, 251-6 (2004), by Dale Jacquette, who claims that the simple theory of types is inconsistent.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  84
    Stephen G. Simpson subsystems of second-order arithmetic.Jeffrey Ketland - 2001 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52 (1):191-195.
  33. Second-Order Logic.Jeffrey Ketland - unknown
    Second-order logic is the extension of first-order logic obtaining by introducing quantification of predicate and function variables.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Truth.Jeffrey Ketland - 2009 - In John Shand (ed.), Central Issues of Philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. The model theoretic conception of scientific theories.Jeffrey Ketland - unknown
    Ordinarily, in mathematical and scientific practice, the notion of a “theory” is understood as follows: (SCT) Standard Conception of Theories : A theory T is a collection of statements, propositions, conjectures, etc. A theory claims that things are thus and so. The theory may be true, and may be false. A theory T is true if things are as T says they are, and T is false if things are not as T says they are. One can make this Aristotelian (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  49
    Review of Paul Horwich, From a Deflationary Point of View[REVIEW]Jeffrey Ketland - 2005 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2005 (12).
  37. The nature and structure of content.Jeffrey C. King - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Belief in propositions has had a long and distinguished history in analytic philosophy. Three of the founding fathers of analytic philosophy, Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, and G. E. Moore, believed in propositions. Many philosophers since then have shared this belief; and the belief is widely, though certainly not universally, accepted among philosophers today. Among contemporary philosophers who believe in propositions, many, and perhaps even most, take them to be structured entities with individuals, properties, and relations as constituents. For example, the (...)
  38. Formal logic: its scope and limits.Richard C. Jeffrey - 1990 - Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
    This brief paperback is designed for symbolic/formal logic courses. It features the tree method proof system developed by Jeffrey. The new edition contains many more examples and exercises and is reorganized for greater accessibility.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  39. Driving to the panopticon: A philosophical exploration of the risks to privacy posed by the information technology of the future.Jeffrey Reiman - 2004 - In Beate Rössler (ed.), Privacies: philosophical evaluations. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. pp. 194--214.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40.  52
    Epicurus and the Epicurean tradition.Jeffrey Fish & Kirk R. Sanders (eds.) - 2011 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Epicureanism after the generation of its founders has been characterised as dogmatic, uncreative and static. But this volume brings together work from leading classicists and philosophers that demonstrates the persistent interplay in the school between historical and contemporary influences from outside the school and a commitment to the founders' authority. The interplay begins with Epicurus himself, who made arresting claims of intellectual independence, yet also admitted to taking over important ideas from predecessors, and displayed more receptivity than is usually thought (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  41. Anti-Luck Epistemologies and Necessary Truths.Jeffrey Roland & Jon Cogburn - 2011 - Philosophia 39 (3):547-561.
    That believing truly as a matter of luck does not generally constitute knowing has become epistemic commonplace. Accounts of knowledge incorporating this anti-luck idea frequently rely on one or another of a safety or sensitivity condition. Sensitivity-based accounts of knowledge have a well-known problem with necessary truths, to wit, that any believed necessary truth trivially counts as knowledge on such accounts. In this paper, we argue that safety-based accounts similarly trivialize knowledge of necessary truths and that two ways of responding (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  42. Semantics, pragmatics, and the role of semantic content.Jeffrey C. King & Jason Stanley - 2005 - In Zoltan Gendler Szabo (ed.), Semantics Versus Pragmatics. Oxford University Press. pp. 111--164.
    Followers of Wittgenstein allegedly once held that a meaningful claim to know that p could only be made if there was some doubt about the truth of p. The correct response to this thesis involved appealing to the distinction between the semantic content of a sentence and features attaching to its use. It is inappropriate to assert a knowledge-claim unless someone in the audience has doubt about what the speaker claims to know. But this fact has nothing to do with (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  43.  59
    Scientific inference.Harold Jeffreys - 1931 - Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press.
    Thats logic. LEWIS CARROLL, Through the Looking Glass 1-1. The fundamental problem of this work is the question of the nature of scientific inference.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  44. Data science ethical considerations: a systematic literature review and proposed project framework.Jeffrey S. Saltz & Neil Dewar - 2019 - Ethics and Information Technology 21 (3):197-208.
    Data science, and the related field of big data, is an emerging discipline involving the analysis of data to solve problems and develop insights. This rapidly growing domain promises many benefits to both consumers and businesses. However, the use of big data analytics can also introduce many ethical concerns, stemming from, for example, the possible loss of privacy or the harming of a sub-category of the population via a classification algorithm. To help address these potential ethical challenges, this paper maps (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  45.  18
    Consciousness, schizophrenia and scientific theory.Jeffrey A. Gray - 1993 - In Gregory R. Bock & Joan Marsh (eds.), Experimental and Theoretical Studies of Consciousness (CIBA Foundation Symposia Series, No. 174). Wiley. pp. 174--263.
  46. Fictional Universal Realism.Jeffrey Goodman - 2022 - Metaphysica 23 (2):177-192.
    Certain realists about properties and relations identify them with universals. Furthermore, some hold that for a wide range of meaningful predicates, the semantic contribution to the propositions expressed by the sentences in which those predicates figure is the universal expressed by the predicate. I here address ontological issues raised by predicates first introduced to us via works of fiction and whether the universal realist should accept that any such predicates express universals. After assessing arguments by Braun, D. and Sawyer, S. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. The Structure of Gunk: Adventures in the Ontology of Space.Jeffrey Sanford Russell - 2008 - In Dean Zimmerman (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics: Volume 4. Oxford University Press. pp. 248.
    Could space consist entirely of extended regions, without any regions shaped like points, lines, or surfaces? Peter Forrest and Frank Arntzenius have independently raised a paradox of size for space like this, drawing on a construction of Cantor’s. I present a new version of this argument and explore possible lines of response.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  48. From Biological to Synthetic Neurorobotics Approaches to Understanding the Structure Essential to Consciousness, Part 1.Jeffrey White & Jun Tani - 2016 - APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers 1 (16):13-23.
    Direct neurological and especially imaging-driven investigations into the structures essential to naturally occurring cognitive systems in their development and operation have motivated broadening interest in the potential for artificial consciousness modeled on these systems. This first paper in a series of three begins with a brief review of Boltuc’s (2009) “brain-based” thesis on the prospect of artificial consciousness, focusing on his formulation of h-consciousness. We then explore some of the implications of brain research on the structure of consciousness, finding limitations (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Probability and the Art of Judgment.Richard C. Jeffrey - 1992 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Richard Jeffrey is beyond dispute one of the most distinguished and influential philosophers working in the field of decision theory and the theory of knowledge. His work is distinctive in showing the interplay of epistemological concerns with probability and utility theory. Not only has he made use of standard probabilistic and decision theoretic tools to clarify concepts of evidential support and informed choice, he has also proposed significant modifications of the standard Bayesian position in order that it provide a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  50. From Biological to Synthetic Neurorobotics Approaches to Understanding the Structure Essential to Consciousness (Part 3).Jeffrey White & Jun Tani - 2017 - APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers 17 (1):11-22.
    This third paper locates the synthetic neurorobotics research reviewed in the second paper in terms of themes introduced in the first paper. It begins with biological non-reductionism as understood by Searle. It emphasizes the role of synthetic neurorobotics studies in accessing the dynamic structure essential to consciousness with a focus on system criticality and self, develops a distinction between simulated and formal consciousness based on this emphasis, reviews Tani and colleagues' work in light of this distinction, and ends by forecasting (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000