Results for 'Aristotle’s doctrine of virtue'

999 found
Order:
  1.  41
    When organizations are too good: Applying Aristotle's doctrine of the mean to the corporate ethical virtues model.Muel Kaptein - 2017 - Business Ethics: A European Review 26 (3):300-311.
    Aristotle's doctrine of the mean states that a virtue is the mean state between two vices: a deficient and an excessive one. The Corporate Ethical Virtues Model defines the mean and the corresponding deficient vice for each of its seven virtues. This paper defines for each of these virtues the corresponding excessive vice and explores why organizations characterized by these excessive vices increase the likelihood that their employees will behave unethically. The excessive vices are patronization, pompousness, lavishness, zealotry, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  2.  37
    X—Aristotle's Doctrine that Virtue is a “Mean”.W. F. R. Hardie - 1965 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 65 (1):183-204.
    W. F. R. Hardie; X—Aristotle's Doctrine that Virtue is a “Mean”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 65, Issue 1, 1 June 1965, Pages 183–204, https.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  3.  65
    A Defense of Aristotle’s Doctrine that Virtue Is a Mean.Howard J. Curzer - 1996 - Ancient Philosophy 16 (1):129-138.
  4.  30
    The Archer and Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean.Glen Koehn - 2012 - Peitho 3 (1):155-168.
    It is sometimes claimed that Aristotle’s doctrine of the Mean is false or unhelpful: moral virtues are not typically flanked by two opposing vices as he claimed. However, an explicit restatement of Aristotle’s view in terms of sufficiency for an objective reveals that the Mean is more widely applicable than has sometimes been alleged. Understood as a special case of sufficiency, it is essential to many judgments of right and wrong. I consider some objections by Rosalind Hursthouse (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  57
    Aristotle’s Conception of Ethical and Natural Virtue: How the Unity Thesis sheds light on the Doctrine of the Mean.Anselm Winfried Müller - 2004 - In Matthias Lutz-Bachmann & Jan Szaif (eds.), Was Ist Das Für den Menschen Gute? / What is Good for a Human Being?: Menschliche Natur Und Güterlehre / Human Nature and Values. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 18-53.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6. Aristotle's Account of the Virtue of Temperance in Nicomachean Ethics III.10-11.Howard J. Curzer - 1997 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (1):5-25.
    Aristotle's Account of the Virtue of Temperance in Nicomachean Ethics III. 1 o- 11 HOWARD J. CURZER 1. INTRODUCTION maNY ?ONTEMPOX~RY SOCIAL eROBL~S arise from inappropriate indulgence in food, drink, and/or sex. Temperance is the Aristotelian virtue which governs these three things, and Aristotle's account of temperance contains important insights and useful distinctions. Yet Aristotle's account of temperance has been surprisingly neglected, despite the resurgence of virtue ethics. I shall remedy this neglect by providing a passage- by-passage (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  6
    The Virtues of Aristotle.D. S. Hutchinson - 1986 - New York: Routledge.
    Originally published in 1986. Both moral philosophers and philosophical psychologists need to answer the question ‘what is a virtue?’ and the best answer so far give is that of Aristotle. This book is a rigorous exposition of that answer. The elements of Aristotle’s doctrine of virtue are scattered throughout his writings; this book reconstructs his complex and comprehensive doctrine in one place. It also covers Aristotle’s views about choice, character, emotions and the role of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  8.  58
    The Virtues of Aristotle’s Ethics.Paula Gottlieb - 2009 - Cambridge University Press.
    While Aristotle's account of the happy life continues to receive attention, many of his claims about virtue of character seem so puzzling that modern philosophers have often discarded them, or have reworked them to fit more familiar theories that do not make virtue of character central. In this book, Paula Gottlieb takes a fresh look at Aristotle's claims, particularly the much-maligned doctrine of the mean. She shows how they form a thought-provoking ethic of virtue, one that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  9. Kant's Theory of Virtue: The Importance of Autocracy.Anne Margaret Baxley - 2000 - Dissertation, University of California, San Diego
    Focusing on the Groundwork and the Critique of Practical Reason, historical and contemporary critics of Kant's rationalist ethical theory accuse him of holding an impoverished moral psychology and an inadequate account of character and virtue. Kant's sharp contrast between duty and inclination and his claim that only action from duty possesses moral worth appear to imply that pro-moral inclination is unnecessary for, if perhaps compatible with, a good will. On traditional accounts of virtue, however, having a good will (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. The Virtue of Aristotle's Ethics.Paula Gottlieb - 2009 - Cambridge University Press.
    While Aristotle's account of the happy life continues to receive attention, many of his claims about virtue of character seem so puzzling that modern philosophers have often discarded them, or have reworked them to fit more familiar theories that do not make virtue of character central. In this book, Paula Gottlieb takes a fresh look at Aristotle's claims, particularly the much-maligned doctrine of the mean. She shows how they form a thought-provoking ethic of virtue, one that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11. Mediality and Rationality in Aristotle's Account of Excellence of Character.Mark McCullagh - 1995 - Apeiron 28 (4):155 - 174.
    I offer a reading of Aristotle’sdoctrine of the mean” that avoids two pitfalls: taking it as truistic, and taking it as involving the bizarre thesis that whenever one acts as reason directs, one’s action is mid-way between some extremes. The crucial point is that while Aristotle denies the existence of useful general ethical truths, he himself offers truths about the likelihoods with which rationality will require actions of certain types; and it is with such truths that the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  21
    Aristotle's Theory of ΤΟΠΟΣ.H. R. King - 1950 - Classical Quarterly 44 (1-2):76-.
    Diogenes Laertius relates the tale that Aristotle, upon being reproached for giving alms to a debased fellow, replied, ‘It was not his character, but the man, that I pitied.’ Some such reply is equally apt in apology for a paper paying homage to an idea long discredited in the philosophical world, Aristotle's theory of Place. I have been moved, not indeed by the apparent character of Aristotle's theory, for that is easily reproached, but by what has proved for the philosophical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  11
    Kant's Theory of Virtue: The Value of Autocracy (review).Robert B. Louden - 2012 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 50 (1):142-143.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Kant's Theory of Virtue: The Value of AutocracyRobert B. LoudenAnne Margaret Baxley. Kant's Theory of Virtue: The Value of Autocracy. Cambridge-New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010. Pp. xvi + 189. Cloth, $85.00.Back in the early 1980s, Anglophone philosophers began to seriously explore the nature and role of virtue in Kant's ethics. This development itself was the result of a confluence of three other phenomena: (1) (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  13
    Interpreting Aristotle’s Concept of the Common Good.Anthony J. Celano - 2024 - In Heikki Haara & Juhana Toivanen (eds.), Common Good and Self-Interest in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy. Springer Verlag. pp. 31-49.
    Providing a definitive interpretation of many ideas in Aristotle’s moral and political works has proved to be a difficult task for his commentators, both ancient and modern. The relation between the individual human good and the communal good is a particularly complex problem, especially because of its association with complicated notions of human happiness, practical wisdom, and contemplative and political virtue. This chapter considers the question of the superiority of the common good over individual happiness in light of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  31
    Aristotle's Conception of Moral Weakness (review). [REVIEW]Josiah Gould - 1965 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 3 (2):262-264.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:262 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Aristotle's Coneeplion of Moral Weakness. By James J. Walsh. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1963. Pp. viii ~- 199. $6.00.) The section of the Nicomachean Ethics in which Aristotle discusses at length the notion of akrasia or moral weakness (vii. 1-10) is one which as much as any other has evoked from philosophers a host of varying interpretations. One of the difficulties posed by Aristotle's (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.J. O. Urmson - 1973 - American Philosophical Quarterly 10 (3):223 - 230.
    Aristotle's doctrine of the mean is not a counsel to perform mean or moderate actions. It states that excellence of character is a mean state with regard to the having and displaying of emotions. All emotions are morally neutral; character is shown by displaying emotions on the right occasions, Not too often or too rarely, Not too strongly or too weakly, For sufficient and only sufficient reasons, Etc. The difficulties for such a view presented by justice and such bad (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  17.  38
    Aristotle on the Intellectual Virtues: On the Meaning of the Notions of Consideration and Consideration for Others in Nicomachean Ethics.A. Solopova Maria - 2016 - Russian Studies in Philosophy 54 (6):519-534.
    This article discusses Aristotle’s doctrine of intellectual virtues in Nicomachean Ethics. The author describes all the intellectual virtues that Aristotle indicates, but mainly focuses on some “secondary” virtues that clarify the concept of reasonableness, with a detailed unpacking of the concepts of “consideration” and “consideration for others”. In addition to commenting on the interrelation of the moral and intellectual virtues, the article also shows why Aristotle must recognize “natural virtues” along with the virtues in the substantive sense of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Defending the Doctrine of the Mean Against Counterexamples: A General Strategy.Nicholas Colgrove - 2024 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly (Online First):1-24.
    Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean states that each moral virtue stands opposed to two types of vice: one of excess and one of deficiency, respectively. Critics claim that some virtues—like honesty, fair-mindedness, and patience—are counterexamples to Aristotle’s doctrine. Here, I develop a generalizable strategy to defend the doctrine of the mean against such counterexamples. I argue that not only is the doctrine of the mean defensible, but taking it seriously also allows us to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Mediality and Rationality in Aristotle's Account of Excellence of Character.Mark Mccullagh - 1992 - Apeiron 25 (4):155-174.
    I offer a reading of Aristotle’sdoctrine of the mean” that avoids two pitfalls: taking it as truistic, and taking it as involving the bizarre thesis that whenever one acts as reason directs, one’s action is mid-way between some extremes. The crucial point is that while Aristotle denies the existence of useful general ethical truths, he himself offers truths about the *likelihoods* with which rationality will require actions of certain types; and it is with such truths that the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics: An Introduction.Michael Pakaluk - 2005 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This is an engaging and accessible introduction to the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle's great masterpiece of moral philosophy. Michael Pakaluk offers a thorough and lucid examination of the entire work, uncovering Aristotle's motivations and basic views while paying careful attention to his arguments. The chapter on friendship captures Aristotle's doctrine with clarity and insight, and Pakaluk gives original and compelling interpretations of the Function Argument, the Doctrine of the Mean, courage and other character virtues, Akrasia, and the two treatments (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  21.  63
    The virtue of Aristotle's ethics (review). [REVIEW]Matthew Walker - 2010 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (3):397-398.
    In this work, Paula Gottlieb offers a wide-ranging overview of Aristotle's virtue ethics that puts Aristotle's doctrine of the mean at the center of discussion. She distinguishes this doctrine from a doctrine of moderation, and identifies the doctrine as one of equilibrium: just as a well-calibrated scale registers the right weight, the well-calibrated, virtuous agent responds appropriately in his circumstances. The virtues, then, are balanced dispositions . Further, they are in a mean "relative to us," (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Review of Gottlieb, The Virtue of Aristotle’s Ethics. [REVIEW]Thornton C. Lockwood Jr - 2011 - International Philosophical Quarterly 51 (3):418-420.
    In his Metaphysics of Morals, Kant famously wrote “The distinction between virtue and vice can never be sought in the degree to which one follows certain maxims…In other words, the well-known principle (Aristotle’s) that locates virtue in the mean between two vices is false.” Kant is not the first (or the last) thinker to take to task Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean, but he is representative of a line of criticism of Aristotle’s doctrine (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  16
    The Relativity of Moral Virtue in Aristotle’s Ethics - Focusing on His Doctrine of the Mean. 김도형 - 2018 - Journal of Ethics: The Korean Association of Ethics 1 (122):27-49.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  90
    The Relativity of Volition: Aristotle’s Teleological Agent Causalism.Robert Allen - manuscript
    Nicomachean Ethics/NE, Book III, Chapters 1-5, provides Aristotle’s account of “Voluntary Movement.” It, thus, draws the Passion-Action distinction, only posited earlier in Categories, while also serving as the linchpin of NE’ discussion of Virtue, in explicitly connecting it to Right Reason. My explication of this text renders its terminology consistent with the Law of Excluded Middle and rebuts two criticisms of the Eudaimonistic Axiology on which it is based. These results are shown to be entailments of Aristotle’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  16
    Aristotle's Ethics: Nicomachean and Eudemian Themes.Paula Gottlieb - 2022 - Cambridge University Press.
    This Element is an examination of the philosophical themes presented in Aristotle's Nicomachean and Eudemian Ethics. Topics include happiness, the voluntary and choice, the doctrine of the mean, particular virtues of character and temperamental means, virtues of thought, akrasia, pleasure, friendship, and luck. Special attention has been paid to Aristotle's treatment of virtues of character and thought and their relation to happiness, the reason why Aristotle is the quintessential virtue ethicist. The virtues of character have not received the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  24
    Aristotle on Virtue as Mean State.Steven C. Skultety - 2022 - Ancient Philosophy 42 (2):493-508.
    Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean is often interpreted as a map of how character virtues are constituted. Taken in this way, critics argue that the Doctrine fails to describe accurately the specific virtues analyzed in books 3 to 5 of the Nicomachean Ethics. I argue that Aristotle does not offer the Doctrine as a map, but rather as a legend in terms of which any explication of a character virtue should be given. This interpretation resolves (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  36
    Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction (review).Roderick T. Long - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):411-412.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.3 (2003) 411-412 [Access article in PDF] Deborah Achtenberg. Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction. Albany: The State University of New York Press, 2002. Pp. xiii + 218. Paper, $20.95.Deborah Achtenberg argues that, for Aristotle, virtue is a disposition to respond to situations with the appropriate emotions, where emotions are understood as perceptions of the value (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Courage, the Doctrine of the Mean, and the Possibility of Evaluative and Emotional Coherence.Michael Stocker - 1989 - In Plural and conflicting values. New York: Oxford University Press.
    According to Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean, virtue and a good life involve a mean of feeling and action. This chapter focuses on David Pear's claim that the Doctrine is conceptually incoherent. It argues that there are serious difficulties in understanding what it could be for courage and its feelings to be in a mean. Courage involves plural and incommensurable values, victory and danger, and the respective emotions, confidence and fear––it is difficult to see how these can (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Aquinas's interpretation of the Aristotelian virtue of justice and his doctrine of natural law.Matthias Perkams - 2007 - In István Bejczy (ed.), Virtue ethics in the Middle Ages: commentaries on Aristotle's Nicomachean ethics, 1200 -1500. Boston: Brill.
  30.  48
    Aristotle’s Contrary Psychology: The Mean in Ethics and Beyond.Louis Groarke - 2015 - Review of Metaphysics 69 (1):47-71.
    Contemporary commentators such as Rosalind Hursthouse misconstrue Aristotle’s doctrine of the ethical mean. They propose a monist account of his moral psychology, explaining each virtue in terms of the presence or absence of a single psychological trait. In contrast, the author argues that Aristotle depicts virtue as a balancing of two opposed psychological inclinations that push and pull in different directions. Each inclination is a positive force in its own right; neither is mere privation. This dualistic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  40
    Reading Aristotle’s Ethics. Virtue, Rhetoric, and Political Philosophy. [REVIEW]Leo J. Elders - 1998 - Review of Metaphysics 52 (2):493-494.
    The author sees his scholarly book as a contribution to the “remarkable resurgence of interest in Aristotle’s moral and political philosophy.” Despite the difficulty of integrating the various parts of the Nicomachean Ethics into a harmonious doctrine, Tessitore defends the cogency of the text. In five chapters he deals with several of the main topics studied by Aristotle. The Ethics is addressed to morally serious persons. The second chapter discusses the virtues treated in books 2–7. Special attention is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.J. O. Urmson - 1973 - [Department of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh].
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  33.  35
    Aristotle's dialogue with Socrates: on the Nicomachean ethics.Ronna Burger - 2008 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    What is the good life for a human being? Aristotle’s exploration of this question in the Nicomachean Ethics has established it as a founding work of Western philosophy, though its teachings have long puzzled readers and provoked spirited discussion. Adopting a radically new point of view, Ronna Burger deciphers some of the most perplexing conundrums of this influential treatise by approaching it as Aristotle’s dialogue with the Platonic Socrates. This dialogue initially takes the shape of a debate Aristotle (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34. Islamic Ethics and the Doctrine of the Mean.Hossein Atrak - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations at University of Tabriz 8 (14):131-147.
    Originally introduced by Plato and Aristotle, the doctrine of the mean is the most prevalent theory of ethics among Islamic scholars. According to this doctrine, every virtue or excellence of character lies in the observance of the mean, whereas vices are the excess or deficiency of the soul in his functions. Islamic scholars have been influenced by the doctrine, but they have also developed and re-conceptualized it in innovative ways. Kindi, Miskawayh, Avicenna, Raghib Isfahani, Nasir al-Din (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Aristotle's doctrine of the instrumental body of the soul.Abraham Bos - 1999 - Philosophia Reformata 64 (1):37-51.
    Hippolytus of Rome on Aristotle’s definition of the soul. His work Concerning the Soul is obscure. For in the entire three books [where he treats of his subject] it is not possible to say clearly what is Aristotle’s opinion concerning the soul. For, as regards the definition which he furnishes of soul, it is easy [enough] to declare this; but what it is that is signified by the definition is difficult to discover. For soul, he says, is an (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  64
    Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean.Peter Losin - 1987 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 4 (3):329 - 341.
  37. Aristotle's doctrine of the material substrate.Sheldon Cohen - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (2):171-194.
    Commentators have often held that aristotle's general doctrine of change commits him to a persisting material substrate for every change, And to an indeterminate material substrate (prime matter) for elemental transformation. I argue that though aristotle accepts a common matter for the four elements, Both these claims are false.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  38.  11
    Aristotle’s Doctrine of Causes and the Manipulative Theory of Causality.Gaetano Licata - 2019 - Axiomathes 29 (6):653-666.
    I will argue for the similarity between some aspects of Aristotle’s doctrine of causes and a particular kind of interventionist theory of causality. The interventionist account hypothesizes that there is a connection between causation and human intervention: the idea of a causal relation between two events is generated by the reflection of human beings on their own operating. This view is remindful of the Aristotelian concept of αἴτιον, which is linked to the figure of the αἴτιος, the person (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  18
    Aristotle’s Doctrine of Causes and the Manipulative Theory of Causality.Gaetano Licata - 2019 - Axiomathes 29 (6):653-666.
    I will argue for the similarity between some aspects of Aristotle’s doctrine of causes and a particular kind of interventionist theory of causality. The interventionist account hypothesizes that there is a connection between causation and human intervention: the idea of a causal relation between two events is generated by the reflection of human beings on their own operating. This view is remindful of the Aristotelian concept of αἴτιον, which is linked to the figure of the αἴτιος, the person (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  41
    Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature.Nahum Brown - 2016 - Kritike 10 (2):122-131.
    Aristotle's famous claim that human beings are animals with rationality has a subtle and complicated articulation in his doctrine of the mean. This paper offers textual analysis of Aristotle's discussion of the mean as a resource for coming to terms with the thesis that humans naturally deliberate over the essence of their nature. Unlike other animals who tend to act without deliberation and without mediation, human beings are the animals who are capable of giving an account of themselves. However, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Nature in Aristotle's ethics and politics.Richard Kraut - 2007 - Social Philosophy and Policy 24 (2):199-219.
    Aristotle's doctrine that human beings are political animals is, in part, an empirical thesis, and posits an inclination to enter into cooperative relationships, even apart from the instrumental benefits of doing so. Aristotle's insight is that human cooperation rests on a non-rational propensity to trust even strangers, when conditions are favorable. Turning to broader questions about the role of nature in human development, I situate Aristotle's attitude towards our natural propensities between two extremes: he rejects both the view that (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  35
    Kant's Doctrine of Virtue.Mark Timmons - 2021 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    Immanuel Kant's final publication in ethics was The Doctrine of Virtue, Part II of the 1797 The Metaphysics of Morals. This text presents Kant's normative ethical theory. This guide is meant to be read alongside Kant's text, combining accessible explanations and novel interpretations of this difficult text. It is the first book in English devoted to The Doctrine of Virtue, one of Kant's most significant works. -/- Timmons divides the guide into five parts. Part I reviews (...)
  43.  17
    Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Uncreatedness and Indestructibility of the Universe.Anton-Hermann Chroust - 1978 - New Scholasticism 52 (2):268-279.
  44.  7
    Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction (review).Roderick T. Long - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):411-412.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.3 (2003) 411-412 [Access article in PDF] Deborah Achtenberg. Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction. Albany: The State University of New York Press, 2002. Pp. xiii + 218. Paper, $20.95.Deborah Achtenberg argues that, for Aristotle, virtue is a disposition to respond to situations with the appropriate emotions, where emotions are understood as perceptions of the value (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  21
    Aristotle's doctrine of "universalia in rebus".Darrel D. Colson - 1983 - Apeiron 17 (2):113 - 124.
  46.  18
    Aristotle’s Doctrine of ‘The Underlying Matter’.Dermot O’Donoghue - 1953 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 3:16-39.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  12
    Aristotle’s Doctrine of ‘The Underlying Matter’.Dermot O’Donoghue - 1953 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 3:16-39.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  44
    Aristotle's Doctrine Of Predicables And Porphyry's Isagoge.Christos Evangeliou - 1985 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 23 (1):15-34.
  49. Aristotle's Doctrine of the Unmoved Mover.David Stewart - 1973 - The Thomist 37 (3):522-547.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction (review). [REVIEW]Roderick T. Long - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):411-412.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.3 (2003) 411-412 [Access article in PDF] Deborah Achtenberg. Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction. Albany: The State University of New York Press, 2002. Pp. xiii + 218. Paper, $20.95.Deborah Achtenberg argues that, for Aristotle, virtue is a disposition to respond to situations with the appropriate emotions, where emotions are understood as perceptions of the value (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 999