Results for 'Mark-Nelson Youngerman'

(not author) ( search as author name )
997 found
Order:
  1.  12
    The Postmodern Turn. [REVIEW]Mark-Nelson Youngerman - 2003 - International Studies in Philosophy 35 (4):159-162.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  10
    Hermeneutics of Poetic Sense. [REVIEW]Mark-Nelson Youngerman - 2004 - International Studies in Philosophy 36 (1):331-332.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  3
    Hermeneutics of Poetic Sense. [REVIEW]Mark-Nelson Youngerman - 2004 - International Studies in Philosophy 36 (1):331-332.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  19
    The Postmodern Turn. [REVIEW]Mark-Nelson Youngerman - 2003 - International Studies in Philosophy 35 (4):159-162.
  5.  7
    The Postmodern Turn. [REVIEW]Mark-Nelson Youngerman - 2003 - International Studies in Philosophy 35 (4):159-162.
  6.  8
    [Book review] the priority of prudence, virtue and natural law in Thomas Aquinas and the implications for modern ethics. [REVIEW]Mark Nelson Daniel - 1994 - In Peter Singer (ed.), Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 401-402.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  4
    Paul Crowther., Critical Aesthetics and Postmodernity.Mark Youngerman - 1996 - International Studies in Philosophy 28 (2):122-124.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  27
    More Bad News For The Logical Autonomy of Ethics.Mark T. Nelson - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):203-216.
    Since the time of Hume, many philosophers have thought it impossible to deduce an ‘Ought’ from an ‘Is,’ or in general to deduce ‘ethical sentences’ from purely ‘factual sentences.’ This is the thesis of the logical autonomy of ethics. I consider a more recent argument by Toomas Karmo in support of the autonomism, but show its limitations in the context of justification skepticism about ethics.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  5
    Kant's Metaphysics of Morals.Nelson T. Potter & Mark Timmons - 1998 - University of Memphis, Dept. Of Philosophy.
  10.  64
    Intuitionism and conservatism.Mark T. Nelson - 1990 - Metaphilosophy 21 (3):282-293.
    I define ethical intuitionism as the view that it is appropriate to appeal to inferentially unsupported moral beliefs in the course of moral reasoning. I mention four common objections to this view, including the view that all such appeals to intuition make ethical theory politically and noetically conservative. I defend intuitionism from versions of this criticism expressed by R.B. Brandt, R.M. Hare and Richard Miller.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  12
    Knowledge and Evidence. [REVIEW]Mark T. Nelson - 1993 - Philosophical Quarterly 43 (171):242-244.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  12.  43
    Andrew J. McKenna., Violence and Difference: Girard, Derrida, and Deconstruction.Andrew J. Mckenna & Mark Youngerman - 1994 - International Studies in Philosophy 26 (4):149-150.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  12
    An Aristotelian Business Ethics?Mark T. Nelson - 1998 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 15 (1):89-104.
    Elaine Sternberg’s Just Business is one of the first book‐length Aristotelian treatments of business ethics. It is Aristotelian in the sense that Sternberg begins by defining the nature of business in order to identify its end, and, thence, normative principles to regulate it. According to Sternberg, the nature of business is ‘the selling of goods or services in order to maximise long‐term owner value’, therefore all business behaviour must be evaluated with reference to the maximisation of long‐term owner value, constrained (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14. We Have No Positive Epistemic Duties.Mark T. Nelson - 2010 - Mind 119 (473):83-102.
    In ethics, it is commonly supposed that we have both positive duties and negative duties, things we ought to do and things we ought not to do. Given the many parallels between ethics and epistemology, we might suppose that the same is true in epistemology, and that we have both positive epistemic duties and negative epistemic duties. I argue that this is false; that is, that we have negative epistemic duties, but no positive ones. There are things that we ought (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  15.  21
    Conjoined Twins of Malta.Mark S. Latkovic & M. D. Nelson - 2001 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 1 (4):585-614.
  16.  16
    Conjoined Twins of Malta.Mark S. Latkovic & Timothy A. Nelson - 2001 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 1 (4):585-614.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  29
    Absolutism, Utilitarianism and Agent-Relative Constraints.Mark T. Nelson - 2022 - International Philosophical Quarterly 62 (2):243-252.
    Absolutism—the idea that some kinds of acts are absolutely wrong and must never be done—plays an important role in medical ethics. Nicholas Denyer has defended it from some influential consequentialist critics who have alleged that absolutism is committed to “agent-relative constraints” and therefore intolerably complex and messy. Denyer ingeniously argues that, if there are problems with agent-relative constraints, then they are problems for consequentialism, since it contains agent-relative constraints, too. I show that, despite its ingenuity, Denyer’s argument does not succeed. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  57
    The Possibility of Inductive Moral Arguments.Mark T. Nelson - 2006 - Philosophical Papers 35 (2):231-246.
    Is it possible to have moral knowledge? ‘Moral justification skeptics’ hold it is not, because moral beliefs cannot have the sort of epistemic justification necessary for knowledge. This skeptical stance can be summed up in a single, neat argument, which includes the premise that ‘Inductive arguments from non-moral premises to moral conclusions are not possible.’ Other premises in the argument may rejected, but only at some cost. It would be noteworthy, therefore, if ‘inductive inferentialism’ about morals were shown to be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  18
    Morality and Universality.Nelson T. Potter & Mark Timmons - 1989 - Noûs 23 (4):555-557.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  25
    Divergent Effects of Metaphoric Company Logos: Do They Convey What the Company Does or What I Need?Mark J. Landau, Noelle M. Nelson & Lucas A. Keefer - 2015 - Metaphor and Symbol 30 (4):314-338.
    Many corporate logos use pictorial metaphors to influence consumer attitudes. Priming concrete concepts—by means of logo exposure or other procedures—changes attitudes toward dissimilar abstract targets in metaphor-consistent ways. It is assumed, however, that observers apply a logo’s metaphor externally to interpret the company and its service. This research examined the possibility that observers may instead apply that metaphor internally to interpret their current condition and hence their need for the company’s service. We hypothesized that the same logo can have divergent (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  8
    Bald Lies.Mark Nelson - 1996 - Cogito 10 (3):235-237.
    It is wrong to deceive people, to get them to believe falsehoods. At least some times, when I wear a wig, I attempt to deceive people about how much hair I have. Why is this not deception? Why is this not wrong? These are the questions I explore.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  26
    Sinnott–Armstrong's Moral Scepticism.Mark T. Nelson - 2003 - Ratio 16 (1):63-82.
    Walter Sinnott-Armstrong’s recent defence of moral scepticism raises the debate to a new level, but I argue that it is unsatisfactory because of problems with its assumption of global scepticism, with its use of the Sceptical Hypothesis Argument, and with its use of the idea of contrast classes and the correlative distinction between ‘everyday’ justification and ‘philosophical’ justification. I draw on Chisholm’s treatment of the Problem of the Criterion to show that my claim that I know that, e.g., baby-torture is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  20
    Lunar Voices. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 2000 - International Studies in Philosophy 32 (2):148-149.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  2
    Lunar Voices. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 2000 - International Studies in Philosophy 32 (2):148-149.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  17
    Prefaces to the Diaphora. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1993 - International Studies in Philosophy 25 (3):106-107.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  3
    Prefaces to the Diaphora. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1993 - International Studies in Philosophy 25 (3):106-107.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  9
    Reading the Postmodern Polity. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1994 - International Studies in Philosophy 26 (1):134-135.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  20
    The Hermeneutics of Postmodernity. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1991 - International Studies in Philosophy 23 (3):131-131.
  29.  9
    The Institution of Theory. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1996 - International Studies in Philosophy 28 (4):119-121.
  30.  19
    Editors' Introduction.Nelson Potter & Mark Timmons - 1998 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 36 (S1):i-i.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  72
    Is it Always Fallacious to Derive Values From Facts?Mark T. Nelson - 1995 - Argumentation 9 (4):553-562.
    Charles Pigden has argued for a logical Is/Ought gap on the grounds of the conservativeness of logic. I offer a counter-example which shows that Pigden’s argument is unsound and that there need be no logical gap between Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion. My counter-example is an argument which is logically valid, has only Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion, does not purport to violate the conservativeness of logic, and does not rely on controversial assumptions about Aristotelian biology or 'institutional facts.'.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  32.  24
    Discoveries of the Other. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1998 - International Studies in Philosophy 30 (4):147-148.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  5
    Discoveries of the Other. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1998 - International Studies in Philosophy 30 (4):147-148.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  21
    The Persistence of Modernity. [REVIEW]Mark Youngerman - 1995 - International Studies in Philosophy 27 (4):149-150.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  91
    Utilitarian Eschatology.Mark T. Nelson - 1991 - American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (4):339-47.
    Traditional utilitarianism, when applied, implies a surprising prediction about the future, viz., that all experience of pleasure and pain must end once and for all, or infinitely dwindle. Not only is this implication surprising, it should render utilitarianism unacceptable to persons who hold any of the following theses: that evaluative propositions may not imply descriptive, factual propositions; that evaluative propositions may not imply contingent factual propositions about the future; that there will always exist beings who experience pleasure or pain.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  36. Moral realism and program explanation.Mark T. Nelson - 2006 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (3):417 – 428.
    Alexander Miller has recently considered an ingenious extension of Frank Jackson and Philip Pettit's account of 'program explanation' as a way of defending non-reductive naturalist versions of moral realism against Harman's explanatory criticism. Despite the ingenuity of this extension, Miller concludes that program explanation cannot help such moral realists in their attempt to defend moral properties. Specifically, he argues that such moral program explanations are dispensable from an epistemically unlimited point of view. I show that Miller's argument for this negative (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  37.  42
    Just Business.Mark Nelson & Elaine Sternberg - 1996 - Philosophical Quarterly 46 (185):554.
  38. More bad news for the logical autonomy of ethics.Mark T. Nelson - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):203-216.
    Are there good arguments from Is to Ought? Toomas Karmo has claimed that there are trivially valid arguments from Is to Ought, but no sound ones. I call into question some key elements of Karmo’s argument for the “logical autonomy of ethics”, and show that attempts to use it as part of an overall case for moral skepticism would be self-defeating.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  39. The Priority of Prudence: Virtue and Natural Law in Thomas Aquinas and the Implications for Modern Ethics.Daniel Mark Nelson - 1992 - Pennsylvania State University Press.
    In _The Priority of Prudence_, Daniel Mark Nelson proposes a reappropriation of a moral perspective that focuses on the cardinal virtues of courage, temperance, justice, and prudence. The study aims to recover and rehabilitate the virtue of prudence as a way of resuming a moral conversation that has been stalemated for too long. Nelson's main source for reviving the virtue of prudence is St. Thomas Aquinas's account of the cardinal virtues in the _Summa Theologica_. A primary problem (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40.  19
    Introduction.Mark T. Nelson - 2011 - Philosophical Papers 40 (3):279-283.
    Philosophical Papers, Volume 40, Issue 3, Page 279-283, November 2011.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  58
    An aristotelian business ethics?Mark T. Nelson - 1998 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 15 (1):89–104.
    Elaine Sternberg's Just Business is one of the first book-length Aristotelian treatments of business ethics. It is Aristotelian in the sense that Sternberg begins by defining the nature of business in order to identify its end, and, thence, normative principles to regulate it. According to Sternberg, the nature of business is 'the selling of goods or services in order to maximise long-term owner value', therefore all business behaviour must be evaluated with reference to the maximisation of long-term owner value, constrained (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  67
    The Principle of Sufficient Reason: a Moral Argument: MARK T. NELSON.Mark T. Nelson - 1996 - Religious Studies 32 (1):15-26.
    The Clarke/Rowe version of the Cosmological Argument is sound only if the Principle of Sufficient Reason is true, but many philosophers, including Rowe, think that there is not adequate evidence for the principle of sufficient reason. I argue that there may be indirect evidence for PSR on the grounds that if we do not accept it, we lose our best justification for an important principle of metaethics, namely, the Principle of Universalizability. To show this, I argue that all the other (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  46
    Temporal Wholes and the Problem of Evil: MARK T. NELSON.Mark T. Nelson - 1993 - Religious Studies 29 (3):313-324.
    This article is not intended to state what I positively believe to be true, but to make a suggestion which I think it well-worth working out. The suggestion is not altogether unfamiliar, but it has certain implications that seem to have been so far overlooked, or at any rate have never been developed. I do not think that it is the duty of a philosopher to confine himself in his publications to working out theories of the truth of which he (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  75
    Who Needs Valid Moral Arguments?Mark T. Nelson - 2003 - Argumentation 17 (1):35-42.
    Why have so many philosophers agonised over the possibility of valid arguments from factual premises to moral conclusions? I suggest that they have done so, because of worries over a sceptical argument that has as one of its premises, `All moral knowledge must be non-inferential, or, if inferential, based on valid arguments or strong inductive arguments from factual premises'. I argue that this premise is false.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45.  22
    Is/Ought Fallacy.Mark T. Nelson - 2018-05-09 - In Robert Arp, Steven Barbone & Michael Bruce (eds.), Bad Arguments. Wiley. pp. 360–363.
    This chapter focuses on one of the common fallacies in Western philosophy called the 'is/ought fallacy (IOF)'. Some philosophers conclude that the IOF is not a logical problem but an epistemological one, meaning that even if inferences like this one are logically valid, they cannot be used epistemologically to warrant anyone's real‐life moral beliefs. Arguments do not warrant their conclusions unless the premises of those arguments are themselves warranted, and in the real world, they say, no one would ever be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  63
    What justification could not be.Mark T. Nelson - 2002 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 10 (3):265 – 281.
    I begin by asking the meta-epistemological question, 'What is justification?', analogous to the meta-ethical question, 'What is rightness?' I introduce the possibility of non-cognitivist, naturalist, non-naturalist, and eliminativist answers in meta-epistemology,corresponding to those in meta-ethics. I devote special attention to the naturalistic hypothesis that epistemic justification is identical to probability, showing its antecedent plausibility. I argue that despite this plausibility, justification cannot be identical with probability, under the standard interpretation of the probability calculus, for the simple reason that justification can (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  47. The Morality of a Free Market for Transplant Organs.Mark T. Nelson - 1991 - Public Affairs Quarterly 5 (1):63-79.
    There is a world-wide shortage of kidneys for transplantation. Many people will have to endure lengthy and unpleasant dialysis treatments, or die before an organ becomes available. Given this chronic shortage, some doctors and health economists have proposed offering financial incentives to potential donors to increase the supply of transplantable organs. In this paper, I explore objections to the practice of buying and selling organs from the point of view 1) justice, 2) beneficence and 3) Commodification. Regarding objection to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  48. A problem for conservatism.Mark T. Nelson - 2009 - Analysis 69 (4):620-630.
    I present a problem for a prominent kind of conservatism, viz., the combination of traditional moral & religious values, patriotic nationalism, and libertarian capitalism. The problem is that these elements sometimes conflict. In particular, I show how libertarian capitalism and patriotic nationalism conflict via a scenario in which the thing that libertarian capitalists love – unregulated market activity – threatens what American patriots love – a strong, independent America. Unrestricted libertarian rights to buy and sell land would permit the sale (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  41
    Bald Lies.Mark Nelson - 1996 - Cogito 10 (3):235-237.
    I present a short, informal vignette that poses the question of whether altering one's appearance by wearing a wig counts as deception, since in both cases one (apparently) tries to bring about false beliefs in others. The bald-headed wig-wearer tries to get others to believe falsely that he has a thick head of hair. If deception is generally wrong, why isn't wig-wearing wrong also?
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  27
    Commentary: Practical Wisdom and Theory.Mark T. Nelson - 2012 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 21 (3):404-408.
    This paper is an ethical reflection on the real-life case of "Angela", a highly intelligent but severely anorexic young woman who wishes to refuse all but palliative treatment. It is part of CQHE's "Ethics Committees and Consultants at Work" series, in response to the essay, "Starving for Perfection.".
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 997