Results for ' common name'

990 found
Order:
  1. “∊” and Common Names.Vito F. Sinisi - 1965 - Philosophy of Science 32 (3/4):281 - 286.
    In [6] I tried to show how an objection to “the nominalist's” analysis of “This is red” and “That is red” on the basis of “the doctrine of common names” might be overcome. The objection is that “the nominalist,” attempting to analyze and by construing the pronouns in these sentences as two different proper names and “red” as a common name, is forced thereby to construe the copula in both sentences as the “is” of identity, and hence (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  8
    “∊” and Common Names.Vito F. Sinisi - 1965 - Philosophy of Science 32 (3):281-286.
    In [6] I tried to show how an objection to “the nominalist's” analysis of (a) “This is red” and (b) “That is red” on the basis of “the doctrine of common names” might be overcome. The objection is that “the nominalist,” attempting to analyze (a) and (b) by construing the pronouns in these sentences as two different proper names and “red” as a common name, is forced thereby to construe the copula in both sentences as the “is” (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  20
    “∊” and Common Names.Vito F. Sinisi - 1965 - Philosophy of Science 32 (3/4):281-.
    In [6] I tried to show how an objection to “the nominalist's” analysis of “This is red” and “That is red” on the basis of “the doctrine of common names” might be overcome. The objection is that “the nominalist,” attempting to analyze and by construing the pronouns in these sentences as two different proper names and “red” as a common name, is forced thereby to construe the copula in both sentences as the “is” of identity, and hence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  61
    Are common names becoming less common? The rise in uniqueness and individualism in Japan.Yuji Ogihara, Hiroyo Fujita, Hitoshi Tominaga, Sho Ishigaki, Takuya Kashimoto, Ayano Takahashi, Kyoko Toyohara & Yukiko Uchida - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
  5.  66
    An Observation on Common Names and Proper Names.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (2):73 - 76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name. This contrast is misleading. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Pragmatics in Peter John Olivi’s Account of Signification of Common Names.Ana María Mora-Márquez - 2011 - Vivarium 49 (1-3):150-164.
    The aim of this paper is to present a reconstruction of Olivi's account of signification of common names and to highlight certain intrusion of pragmatics into this account. The paper deals with the question of how certain facts, other than original imposition, may be relevant to determine the semantical content of an utterance, and not with the question of how we perform actions by means of utterances. The intrusion of pragmatics into Olivi's semantics we intend to point out may (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  28
    Nominalism and common names.Vito F. Sinisi - 1962 - Philosophical Review 71 (2):230-235.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8.  55
    Common names and "family resemblances".Haig Khatchadourian - 1957 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 18 (3):341-358.
  9.  13
    An observation on common names and proper.John Tienson - 1986 - Analysis 46 (1):73-76.
    Common names, for Mill, have both connotation and denotation. Thus ‘horse’ connotes certain properties, and the name ‘horse’ denotes the things that have those properties. By contrast, proper names have no connotations; they do not denote in virtue of the possession of certain properties by their denotations, but so to speak, directly. Thus Socrates received his name by being dubbed ‘Socrates’; and he might just as well have been given any other name.This contrast is misleading. After (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. The common name's problem of meaning in John duns scotus.Héctor Hernando Salinas Leal - 2011 - Universitas Philosophica 28 (56):201-240.
  11.  19
    Neaera as a Common Name.J. P. Postgate - 1914 - Classical Quarterly 8 (02):121-.
    There are two undoubted instances of this use of Neaera in Prudentius which are cited by Mr. Ullman in support of his contention that in Horace another proper name may be similarly employed. I imagine however that to an unprejudiced sense of Latin usage these instances will themselves seem to be strange and in need of explanation.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  17
    Common decency for common names.P. T. Sagal - 1974 - Philosophical Studies 26 (1):63 - 67.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. A new Python in Captivity from New Guinea, The New Guinea Carpet Python and the Sawu Python–a correct common name.D. G. Barker & T. M. Barker - 1995 - Vivarium 6 (6):30-33.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  33
    On the nominalistic semiotics of common names.R. M. Martin - 1978 - Philosophia 8 (2-3):277-293.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. The commonalities between proper names and natural kind terms : a Fregean perspective.Harold Noonan - 2010 - In Helen Beebee & Nigel Sabbarton-Leary (eds.), The Semantics and Metaphysics of Natural Kinds. New York: Routledge. pp. 84-103.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Proper Names and their Fictional Uses.Heidi Tiedke - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (4):707 - 726.
    Fictional names present unique challenges for semantic theories of proper names, challenges strong enough to warrant an account of names different from the standard treatment. The theory developed in this paper is motivated by a puzzle that depends on four assumptions: our intuitive assessment of the truth values of certain sentences, the most straightforward treatment of their syntactic structure, semantic compositionality, and metaphysical scruples strong enough to rule out fictional entities, at least. It is shown that these four assumptions, taken (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  17. To Name or to Describe: Shared Knowledge Affects Referential Form.Daphna Heller, Kristen S. Gorman & Michael K. Tanenhaus - 2012 - Topics in Cognitive Science 4 (2):290-305.
    The notion of common ground is important for the production of referring expressions: In order for a referring expression to be felicitous, it has to be based on shared information. But determining what information is shared and what information is privileged may require gathering information from multiple sources, and constantly coordinating and updating them, which might be computationally too intensive to affect the earliest moments of production. Previous work has found that speakers produce overinformative referring expressions, which include privileged (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  18.  2
    The Common Being: An Outline.Thomas Telios - 2024 - Symposium 28 (1):53-78.
    In this article, I revisit Karl Marx’s claim in his Economic and Phil-osophic Manuscripts of 1844, that the subject in its “individual existence is at the same time a social being.” I redefine what has been translated as “social being” as “common being” in order to extrapolate an understanding of subjectivity that is a socio-ontological and collectively structured collectivity. In doing so, I demonstrate (1) that this common being is a collection of different socio-ontological traits; (2) that in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. How Children Learn Common Nouns and Proper Names.Geoffrey Hall - 1994 - In John Macnamara & Gonzalo E. Reyes (eds.), The Logical Foundations of Cognition. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 212-240.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  15
    In the name of Husserl: nursing in pursuit of the things‐in‐themselves.Tania Yegdich - 2000 - Nursing Inquiry 7 (1):29-40.
    In the name of Husserl: nursing in pursuit of the things‐in‐themselves A perceived contradiction between the tenets of humanism and positivism secures phenomenology’s endorsement in nursing as an alternative methodology to the natural sciences. Nursing’s humanistic doctrine of valuing the individual is aligned with phenomenology in the belief that both projects investigate the subjective experiences of others. However, the belief that phenomenology opposes objectifying methods does not account for the different understandings of subjectivity that underpin various philosophic positions, such (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  25
    Proper Names: A Millian Account.Stefano Predelli - 2017 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Stefano Predelli defends a semantics of proper names which has simplicity and common sense in its favour: proper names are non-indexical devices of rigid and direct reference. He grounds this view in accounts of the shape and form of names, and of their introduction within language use, and he responds to widespread misconceptions and objections.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  22. The neuropsychology of proper names.Carlo Semenza - 2009 - Mind and Language 24 (4):347-369.
    The difference between common and proper names seems to derive from specific semantic characteristics of proper names. In particular, proper names refer to specific individual entities or events, and unlike common names, rarely map onto more general semantic characteristics (attributes, concepts, categories). This fact makes the link proper names have with their reference particularly fragile. Processing proper names seems, as a consequence, to require special cognitive and neural resources. Neuropsychological findings show that proper names and common names (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23.  53
    Names as Predicates.Sarah Sawyer - 2021 - In Heimir Geirsson & Stephen Biggs (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Linguistic Reference. New York: Routledge. pp. 198-212.
    This contribution to the volume explains predicativism, including reasons that favour it and different versions of it. What all predicativist theories have in common is the claim that a proper name is a general, predicative term, with a hidden determiner in its single use.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  26
    Art-Names and Aesthetic Judgments.Haig Khatchadourian - 1961 - Philosophy 36 (136):30 - 48.
    In an earlier paper I have attempted to show, among other things; that the names of human artifacts and man-devised activities and processes involve in their uses the notion of some end-in-view, function, or use , which partially regulates these uses. In this paper I shall limit myself to a somewhat detailed discussion of one very important class of such common names which requires a separate treatment. I mean art-names.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  25.  58
    The Common Cause Principle. Explanation via Screening off.Leszek Wronski - 2010 - Dissertation, Jagiellonian University
    My Ph.D. dissertation written under the supervision of Prof. Tomasz Placek at the Institute of Philosophy of the Jagiellonian University in Kraków. In one of its most basic and informal shapes, the principle of the common cause states that any surprising correlation between two factors which are believed not to directly influence one another is due to their common cause. Here we will be concerned with a version od this idea which possesses a purely probabilistic formulation. It was (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26. Russell-Names: An Introduction to Millian Descriptivism.Stefano Predelli - 2016 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 45 (5):603-622.
    This essay studies the semantic properties of what I call Russell-names. Russell-names bear intimate semantic relations with descriptive conditions, in consonance with the main tenets of descriptivism. Yet, they are endowed with the semantic properties attributed to ordinary proper names by Millianism: they are rigid and non-indexical devices of direct reference. This is not an essay in natural language semantics, and remains deliberately neutral with respect to the question whether any among the expressions we ordinarily classify as proper names behave (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  11
    Young children’s knowledge of names and uses of common tableware.Paul Ngo & Albert E. Goss - 1989 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 27 (2):127-130.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  21
    Poetry as the Naming of the Gods.Phyllis Zagano - 1989 - Philosophy and Literature 13 (2):340-349.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:POETRY AS THE NAMING OF THE GODS by Phyllis Zagano There have been many attempts to define poetry, and there is copious advice to would-be poets. Horace writes somewhere "Sit quod vis, simplex dumtaxat et unum" which can be comfortably rendered as "make anything at all, so long as it hangs together." The hanging together is the quality most writers point to as evidence of success: simply, it works. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  73
    Names vs nouns.Laura Delgado - 2022 - Philosophical Studies 179 (11):3233-3258.
    This paper takes issue with the predicativist’s identification of proper names and common count nouns. Although Predicativism emerges precisely to account for certain syntactic facts about proper names, namely, that they behave like common count nouns on occasions, it seems clear that proper names and common count nouns have different properties, and this undermines the thesis that proper names are in fact just common count nouns. The predicativist’s strategy to bridge these differences is to postulate an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Common Subject for Ethics.Mark Schroeder - 2021 - Mind 130 (517):85-110.
    The purpose of this paper is to conceptualize and explore what I shall call the Common Subject Problem for ethics. The problem is that there seems to be no good answer to what property everyone who makes moral claims could be talking and thinking about. The Common Subject Problem is not a new problem; on the contrary, I will argue that it is one of the central animating concerns in the history of both metaethics and normative theory. But (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  23
    Naming animals in Chinese writing.Han-Liang Chang - 2001 - Sign Systems Studies 29 (2):647-656.
    Naming, according to Sebeok, constihttes the first stage of zoosemiotics. This special but common use of language acrually inaugurates more complicated procedures of human discourse on non-human kingdom, including classification of its members. Because of language's double articulation in sound and sense, as well as the grapheme's pleremic (meaning-full) rather than cenemic (meaning-empty) characteristic (according to Hjelmslev). Chinese script is capable of naming and grouping animals randomly but effectively. This paper attempts to describe the said scriptorial "necessity of naming" (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Names, identity, and predication.Eros Corazza - 2018 - Philosophical Studies 175 (10):2631-2647.
    It is commonly accepted, after Frege, that identity statements like “Tully is Cicero” differ from statements like “Tully is Tully”. For the former, unlike the latter, are informative. One way to deal with the information problem is to postulate that the terms ‘Tully’ and ‘Cicero’ come equipped with different informative values. Another approach is to claim that statements like these are of the subject/predicate form. As such, they should be analyzed along the way we treat “Tully walks”. Since proper names (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Naming God: Moses Maimonides and Thomas Aquinas.Neil A. Stubbens - 1990 - The Thomist 54 (2):229-267.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:NAMING GOD: MOSES MAIMONIDES AND THOMAS AQUINAS NEIL A. 8TUBBENS The Methodist Ohurch Barnsley Oircuit, South Yorkshire MOSES MAIMONIDES (1135-U04) and Thomas Aquinas (c. U~5-1274), two of the greatest theologians of the Jewish and Christian faiths, had much in oommon.1 Like other Ohristian.writers, Aquinas made several criticisms of Maimonides' views on divine predication. In this article l will discuss these criticisms and evaluate them by means of a detailed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  55
    The naked ‘duchess’: names are titles.Roberta Ballarin - 2019 - Linguistics and Philosophy 42 (4):349-379.
    In her recent defense of predicativism for proper names, Delia Graff Fara proposes the following non-metalinguistic being-called condition for the applicability of names as predicates: A name ‘N’ is true of a thing if and only if it is called N. The BCC is supposed to hold for names only. In this essay I criticize Fara’s BCC by arguing that the word ‘called’ is ambiguous, and that the BCC holds only for the particular sense of ‘calling’ as naming. I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  32
    Bioethics Common Market: An International Exchange.Maggie Hall - 1994 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 3 (2):302.
    Bioethics Common Market is an international bulletin board to post notices regarding such things as networking contacts among people interested in a specific area of concern, hospitality, research underway for which collaboration is desired or possible, sources of scarce or hard-to-find materials, reports or papers available in sufficient numbers to share, textbooks or study materials desired, and, for travelers to any state or country, names of local people with possible common interests.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Survey-based naming conventions for use in OBO Foundry ontology development.Schober Daniel, Barry Smith, Lewis Suzanna, E. Kusnierczyk, Waclaw Lomax, Jane Mungall, Chris Taylor, F. Chris, Rocca-Serra Philippe & Sansone Susanna-Assunta - 2009 - BMC Bioinformatics 10 (1):125.
    A wide variety of ontologies relevant to the biological and medical domains are available through the OBO Foundry portal, and their number is growing rapidly. Integration of these ontologies, while requiring considerable effort, is extremely desirable. However, heterogeneities in format and style pose serious obstacles to such integration. In particular, inconsistencies in naming conventions can impair the readability and navigability of ontology class hierarchies, and hinder their alignment and integration. While other sources of diversity are tremendously complex and challenging, agreeing (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  80
    Kant on Common-sense and the Unity of Judgments of Taste.Samuel A. Stoner - 2019 - Kant Yearbook 11 (1):81-99.
    Though the notion of common-sense plays an important role in Kant’s aesthetic theory, it is not immediately clear what Kant means by this term. This essay works to clarify the role that common-sense plays in the logic of Kant’s argument. My interpretive hypothesis is that a careful examination of the way common-sense functions in Kant’s account of judgments of taste can help explain what this notion means. I argue that common-sense names the capacity to discern the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  38.  2
    Naming God: Moses Maimonides and Thomas Aquinas.Neil A. Stubbens - 1990 - The Thomist 54 (2):229-267.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:NAMING GOD: MOSES MAIMONIDES AND THOMAS AQUINAS NEIL A. 8TUBBENS The Methodist Ohurch Barnsley Oircuit, South Yorkshire MOSES MAIMONIDES (1135-U04) and Thomas Aquinas (c. U~5-1274), two of the greatest theologians of the Jewish and Christian faiths, had much in oommon.1 Like other Ohristian.writers, Aquinas made several criticisms of Maimonides' views on divine predication. In this article l will discuss these criticisms and evaluate them by means of a detailed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  19
    Proper Names in Early Word Learning: Rethinking a Theoretical Account of Lexical Development.D. Geoffrey Hall - 2009 - Mind and Language 24 (4):404-432.
    Abstract:There is evidence that children learn both proper names and count nouns from the outset of lexical development. Furthermore, children's first proper names are typically words for people, whereas their first count nouns are commonly terms for other objects, including artifacts. I argue that these facts represent a challenge for two well‐known theoretical accounts of object word learning. I defend an alternative account, which credits young children with conceptual resources to acquire words for both individual objects and object categories, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40.  13
    Enlightened common sense I: clarifying and developing the concepts of depth, emergence, and transfactuality.Dominic Holland - 2019 - Journal of Critical Realism 18 (1):56-82.
    This article is the first in a series of four articles that engage critically with the arguments of two recent and significant additions to the literature on critical realism, namely Bhaskar’s ‘Enlightened Common Sense: The Philosophy of Critical Realism’, and Bhaskar et al.’s ‘Interdisciplinarity and Wellbeing: A Critical Realist General Theory of Interdisciplinarity’. Using the method of immanent critique and focusing mainly, but not exclusively, on the arguments of Enlightened Common Sense, I identify, and propose solutions to, a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  35
    Recognition, Naming and Bare Particulars.John Trentman - 1966 - Dialogue 5 (1):19-30.
    In a recent discussion of the notion of substance Miss Anscombe points out that the following three doctrines are very closely associated: the doctrine that proper names lack all connotation, are mere labels, the view that there is nothing essential to the individual, and the doctrine that individuals are bare particulars with no properties in and of themselves. In this article as well as in other writings she rejects all three of these doctrines. And, along with P. T. Geach, whose (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  13
    Naming the Unnamable: A Comparison between W ANG Bi’s Commentary on the Laozi and Derrida’s Khōra.Gabriella Stanchina - 2020 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 19 (3):409-426.
    In this article, I compare WANG Bi’s 王弼 rendition of Dao 道 as the nameless, unfathomable root of language and the totality of beings, with Derrida’s analysis of the term khōra. Both cases include a text that presents itself as a commentary on another text, namely the Laozi 老子 for Wang Bi and Plato’s Timaeus for Derrida, whose matter is declared as elusive and ungraspable. I analyze the analogies between these two attempts to convey the unsayable, as well as the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Kripke: names, necessity, and identity.Christopher Hughes - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Saul Kripke, in a series of classic writings of the 1960s and 1970s, changed the face of metaphysics and philosophy of language. Christopher Hughes offers a careful exposition and critical analysis of Kripke's central ideas about names, necessity, and identity. He clears up some common misunderstandings of Kripke's views on rigid designation, causality and reference, and the necessary a posteriori and contingent a priori. Through his engagement with Kripke's ideas Hughes makes a significant contribution to ongoing debates on, inter (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  44.  15
    Some Type-Names in the Odes of Horace.B. L. Ullman - 1915 - Classical Quarterly 9 (01):27-.
    In a recent number of the CLASSICAL QUARTERLY , under the title ‘Neaera as a Common Name,’ Mr. Postgate writes: ‘There are two undoubted instances of this use of Neaera in Prudentius which are cited by Mr. Ullman.’ This is indeed a very welcome admission, for, unless I am greatly mistaken, Mr. Postgate was formerly of the opinion that such a usage or anything approaching it was unthinkable in Latin.1 But Mr. Postgate still feels uneasy about it, for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  98
    Land as a Global Commons?Megan Blomfield - 2023 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 40 (4):577-592.
    Land is becoming increasingly scarce relative to the demands of the global economy; a problem significantly exacerbated by climate change. In response, some have suggested that land should be conceptualised as a global commons. This framing might seem like an appealing way to promote sustainable and equitable land use. However, it is a poor fit for the worldʼs land because global commons are generally understood as resources located beyond state borders. I argue that land can be seen to fit the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  75
    Aquinas on Common Nature and Universals.G. Galluzzo - 2004 - Recherches de Theologie Et Philosophie Medievales 71 (1):131-171.
    Throughout his career Aquinas held to the Avicennian doctrine that the nature or essence of sensible substances is somehow indifferent. According to Aquinas's version of this well-known doctrine an essence as such posssesses only those characteristics which are specified in its definition. The essence of a human being, for instance, possesses as such animality and rationality and nothing else. On this view, all the other characteristics and in particular general properties like being one or many, universal or particular, do not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47. A common structure for concepts of individuals, stuffs, and real kinds: More Mama, more milk, and more mouse.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (1):55-65.
    Concepts are highly theoretical entities. One cannot study them empirically without committing oneself to substantial preliminary assumptions. Among the competing theories of concepts and categorization developed by psychologists in the last thirty years, the implicit theoretical assumption that what falls under a concept is determined by description () has never been seriously challenged. I present a nondescriptionist theory of our most basic concepts, which include (1) stuffs (gold, milk), (2) real kinds (cat, chair), and (3) individuals (Mama, Bill Clinton, the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  48.  44
    Common Possession of the Earth and Cosmopolitan Right.Alice Pinheiro Walla - 2016 - Kant Studien 107 (1):160-178.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Kant-Studien Jahrgang: 107 Heft: 1 Seiten: 160-178.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  49.  46
    Bringing Plurality Together: Common Sense, Thinking and Philosophy in Arendt.Itay Snir - 2015 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 53 (3):362-384.
    Arendt's concept of common sense has generally been misunderstood. It is almost exclusively interpreted in light of Kant's common sense, either as an espousal of the latter or as a distortion of it. This narrow reading of Arendtian common sense has led to a problem, as her uses of the concept do not always fit its Kantian understanding. This has led to accusing her of being inconsistent, or as holding on to several, incompatible concepts of common (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50.  63
    Reichenbach’s Common Cause Principle in Algebraic Quantum Field Theory with Locally Finite Degrees of Freedom.Gábor Hofer-Szabó & Péter Vecsernyés - 2012 - Foundations of Physics 42 (2):241-255.
    In the paper it will be shown that Reichenbach’s Weak Common Cause Principle is not valid in algebraic quantum field theory with locally finite degrees of freedom in general. Namely, for any pair of projections A, B supported in spacelike separated double cones ${\mathcal{O}}_{a}$ and ${\mathcal{O}}_{b}$ , respectively, a correlating state can be given for which there is no nontrivial common cause (system) located in the union of the backward light cones of ${\mathcal{O}}_{a}$ and ${\mathcal{O}}_{b}$ and commuting with (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
1 — 50 / 990