Results for 'Legal moralism'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. New Legal Moralism: Some Strengths and Challenges.Thomas Søbirk Petersen - 2010 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 4 (2):215-232.
    The aim of this paper is to critically discuss the plausibility of legal moralism with an emphasis on some central and recent versions. First, this paper puts forward and defends the thesis that recently developed varieties of legal moralism promoted by Robert P. George, John Kekes and Michael Moore are more plausible than Lord Devlin's traditional account. The main argument for this thesis is that in its more modern versions legal moralism is immune to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  2. Legal moralism and retribution revisited.Jeffrie G. Murphy - 2007 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 1 (1):5-20.
    This is a slightly revised text of Jeffrie G. Murphy’s Presidential Address delivered to the American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division, in March 2006. In the essay the author reconsiders two positions he had previously defended—the liberal attack on legal moralism and robust versions of the retributive theory of punishment—and now finds these positions much more vulnerable to legitimate attack than he had previously realized. In the first part of the essay, he argues that the use of Mill’s liberal (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  3.  16
    Legal Moralism, Interests and Preferences: Alexander on Aesthetic Regulation.Jonathan Peterson - 2015 - Philosophia 43 (2):485-498.
    Legal moralists hold that the immorality of an action is a sufficient reason for the state to prevent it. Liberals in the tradition of Mill generally reject legal moralism. However, Larry Alexander has recently developed an argument that suggests that a class of legal restrictions on freedom that most liberals endorse is, and perhaps can only be, justified on moralistic grounds. According to Alexander, environmental restrictions designed to preserve nature or beauty are forms of legal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Towards a Modest Legal Moralism.R. A. Duff - 2014 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (1):217-235.
    After distinguishing different species of Legal Moralism I outline and defend a modest, positive Legal Moralism, according to which we have good reason to criminalize some type of conduct if it constitutes a public wrong. Some of the central elements of the argument will be: the need to remember that the criminal law is a political, not a moral practice, and therefore that in asking what kinds of conduct we have good reason to criminalize, we must (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  5.  74
    In Defense of “Pure” Legal Moralism.Danny Scoccia - 2013 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (3):513-530.
    In this paper I argue that Joel Feinberg was wrong to suppose that liberals must oppose any criminalization of “harmless immorality”. The problem with a theory that permits criminalization only on the basis of his harm and offense principles is that it is underinclusive, ruling out laws that most liberals believe are justified. One objection (Arthur Ripstein’s) is that Feinberg’s theory is unable to account for the criminalization of harmless personal grievances. Another (Larry Alexander’s and Robert George’s) is that it (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  91
    Liberalism, legal moralism and moral disagreement.Arthur Kuflik - 2005 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 (2):185–198.
    abstract According to “legal moralism” it is part of law's proper role to “enforce morality as such”. I explore the idea that legal moralism runs afoul of morality itself: there are good moral reasons not to require by law all that there is nevertheless good moral reason to do. I suggest that many such reasons have broad common‐sense appeal and could be appreciated even in a society in which everyone completely agreed about what morality requires. But (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  7.  15
    Legal Moralism, Overinclusive Offenses, and the Problem of Wrongfulness Conflation.Stuart P. Green - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (3):417-430.
    In the Realm of Criminal Law, Antony Duff seeks to defend the view that we should criminalize conduct only if it is wrongful. Skeptics of legal moralism argue that this occurs all the time in supposedly overinclusive offenses whose definitions capture not only the kind of conduct that constitutes the target wrong, but also a wider class of conduct that is not wrongful prior to prohibition. An example is statutory rape. Duff, in response, contends that such offenses need (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  48
    Legal moralism reconsidered.Carl F. Cranor - 1979 - Ethics 89 (2):147-164.
    In section i, I sketch the main arguments to date for legal moralism, And show the ways in which they are unpersuasive. In sections ii and iii, I sketch and evaluate a seemingly compelling argument, Dependent on the concept of wrongful conduct, For the weak thesis that the immorality of conduct is a reason, But not a sufficient reason for making it illegal. Despite the apparent persuasiveness of this argument, The particular conclusions of the legal moralist, That (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9.  10
    Liberalism, Legal Moralism and Moral Disagreement.Arthur Kuflik - 2005 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 (2):185-198.
    abstract According to “legal moralism” it is part of law's proper role to “enforce morality as such”. I explore the idea that legal moralism runs afoul of morality itself: there are good moral reasons not to require by law all that there is nevertheless good moral reason to do. I suggest that many such reasons have broad common‐sense appeal and could be appreciated even in a society in which everyone completely agreed about what morality requires. But (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. What is Legal Moralism?Thomas S.øøbirk Petersen - 2011 - SATS 12 (1):80-88.
    The aim of this critical commentary is to distinguish and analytically discuss some important variations in which legal moralism is defined in the literature. As such, the aim is not to evaluate the most plausible version of legal moralism, but to find the most plausible definition of legal moralism. As a theory of criminalization, i.e. a theory that aims to justify the criminal law we should retain, legal moralism can be, and has (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11. Legal Moralism and Retribution Revisited.Jeffrie G. Murphy - 2006 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 80 (2):45-62.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  60
    Legal Moralism and Freefloating Evils.Joel Feinberg - 1980 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61 (1/2):122.
    This article distinguishes and evaluates the various forms of legal moralism from a liberal vantage point. It devotes special attention to the most plausible form of the theory, That which is often called "the conservative thesis," and to that supporting argument which is based on the need to prevent "freefloating social-Change evils." freefloating evils are defined as evils that are imputable to human beings but which do not give rise to personal grievances as harms, Offenses, And "harmless exploitative (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  57
    Retributivism and Legal Moralism.David O. Brink - 2012 - Ratio Juris 25 (4):496-512.
    This article examines whether a retributivist conception of punishment implies legal moralism and asks what liberalism implies about retributivism and moralism. It makes a case for accepting the weak retributivist thesis that culpable wrongdoing creates a pro tanto case for blame and punishment and the weak moralist claim that moral wrongdoing creates a pro tanto case for legal regulation. This weak moralist claim is compatible with the liberal claim that the legal enforcement of morality is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  14.  40
    Defining Legal Moralism.Jens Damgaard Thaysen - 2015 - SATS 16 (2):179-201.
    Journal Name: SATS Issue: Ahead of print.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Legal moralism and the harm principle: A rejoinder.Arthur Ripstein - 2007 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 35 (2):195–201.
  16.  20
    Limited legal moralism.Richard Francis Galvin - 1988 - Criminal Justice Ethics 7 (2):23-36.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Legal Paternalism and Legal Moralism: Devlin, Hart and Ten.Heta Häyry - 1992 - Ratio Juris 5 (2):191-201.
    H. L. A. Hart in his Law, Liberty, and Morality (1963) defended the view that legal paternalism and legal moralism can be clearly distinguished from each other. Hart also stated that while legal moralism is always unacceptable, paternalistic laws are often justifiable. In this paper it is argued that Hart held the right view for the wrong reasons. Hart defended legal paternalism by claiming, against J. S. Mill, that for various psychological reasons individuals do (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  34
    Towards a Modest Legal Moralism: Concept, Open Questions, and Potential Extension. [REVIEW]F. Meyer - 2014 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (1):237-244.
    The article introduces and critiques Antony Duff’s Modest Legal Moralism from a strictly analytical angle. It seeks to illuminate its core tenets and modestly addresses a number of aspects that deserve further elaboration from the author’s point of view. Notwithstanding these points of contention the main thrust of the article is the exploration of the constructive potential of Duff’s concept. It will be shown that its core elements are well-equipped to come to grips with the lacuna of theorization (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Boxing, Paternalism, and Legal Moralism.Nicholas Dixon - 2001 - Social Theory and Practice 27 (2):323-344.
    324 "we should impose a single legal restriction that would effectively eliminate boxing's main medical risk: a complete ban on blows to the head" against Mill's harm principle, is not possible to justify paternalism requires other paternalistic arguments 325 "the entire paternalism v. respect for autonomy debate as it applied to boxing is cast in nonconsequentialist terms" do we have any reason to suppose that boxers' decisions to enter the profession are lacking in autonomy? many fail the first hurdle: (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  20.  38
    An Epistemic Case for Legal Moralism.Robert E. Goodin - 2010 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 30 (4):615-633.
    Ignorance of the law is no excuse, or so we are told. But why not? The statute books run to hundreds of volumes. How can an ordinary citizen know what is in them? The best way might be for law (at least in its wide-scope duty-conferring aspects) to track broad moral principles that ordinary citizens can know and apply for themselves. In contrast to more high-minded and deeply principled arguments, this epistemic argument for legal moralism is purely pragmatic—but (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  35
    Liberalism and Legal Moralism: The Hart‐Devlin Debate and Beyond.Heta Häyry - 1991 - Ratio Juris 4 (2):202-218.
    Abstract.The legitimate impact of common morality on legal restrictions has been continuously discussed within the Western philosophy of law since Lord Patrick Devlin in the late 1950s presented his moralistic arguments against some liberal conclusions drawn by the English Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution in their public report. Devlin's arguments were subsequently identified and refuted by Richard Wollheim, H. L. A. Hart and Ronald Dworkin, but in a way that later provoked further argument. In particular the attack against (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  31
    Boxing, Paternalism, and Legal Moralism.Nicholas Dixon - 2001 - Social Theory and Practice 27 (2):323-344.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  23.  18
    Requirement‐Sensitive Legal Moralism: A Critical Assessment.Morten Ebbe Juul Nielsen - 2012 - Ratio Juris 25 (4):527-554.
    Requirement‐sensitive legal moralism is a species of legal moralism in which the legitimacy of turning moral into legal demands depends on the existence of a legitimate moral requirement, producing a legitimate social requirement, which can then ground a legitimate legal requirement. Crucially, each step is defeasible by contingent or instrumental, but not intrinsic moral factors. There is no genuinely moral sphere (e.g., a private sphere) in which the law is not to interfere; only contingent, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  9
    The Justification of Legal Moralism.John Kultgen - 1985 - Philosophical Topics 13 (2):123-131.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  55
    Another look at legal moralism.Jeffrie G. Murphy - 1966 - Ethics 77 (1):50-56.
    The idea that immoral conduct ought to be criminalized is already often rejected, But not for precisely the right reasons. Victim-Less crimes ought to be decriminalized not (as h l a hart and j s mill argue) because it is immoral to make crimes of them, But because it is contrary to the nature of the criminal law itself. Acts of private immorality do not violate the rights of the participants; thus they cannot be crimes because there is no crime (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  26.  52
    Infidelity and the Possibility of a Liberal Legal Moralism.Jens Damgaard Thaysen - 2017 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 11 (2):273-294.
    This paper argues that according to the influential version of legal moralism presented by Moore infidelity should all-things-considered be criminalized. This is interesting because criminalizing infidelity is bound to be highly controversial and because Moore’s legal moralism is a prime example of a self-consciously liberal legal moralism, which aims to yield legislative implications that are quite similar to liberalism, while maintaining that morality as such should be legally enforced. Moore tries to make his theory (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  42
    The Justification of Legal Moralism.John Kultgen - 1985 - Philosophical Topics 13 (2):123-131.
  28. Mill and the Liberal Rejection of Legal Moralism.Piers Norris Turner - 2015 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 32 (1):79-99.
    This article examines John Stuart Mill's position as the principal historical opponent of legal moralism. I argue that inattention to the particular form of his opposition to legal moralism has muddied the interpretation of his liberty principle. Specifically, Mill does not endorse what I call the illegitimacy thesis, according to which appeals to harmless wrongdoings, whether or not they exist, are illegitimate in the justification of legal interference.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  27
    The Problem of Over-Inclusive Offenses: A Closer Look at Duff on Legal Moralism and Mala Prohibita.Stephen Bero & Alex Sarch - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (3):395-416.
    There are sometimes good reasons to define a criminal offense in a way that is over-inclusive, in the sense that the definition will encompass conduct that is not otherwise wrongful. But are these reasons ever sufficient? When, if ever, can such laws justifiably be made and enforced? When, if ever, can they permissibly be violated? In The Realm of Criminal Law, Antony Duff tackles this challenge head on. We find Duff’s strategy promising in many ways as an effort to reconcile (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  7
    Moralistic Fallacy.Galen Foresman - 2018-05-09 - In Robert Arp, Steven Barbone & Michael Bruce (eds.), Bad Arguments. Wiley. pp. 371–373.
    This chapter focuses on one of the common fallacies in Western philosophy: the moralistic fallacy. The moralistic fallacy occurs when one concludes that something is a particular way because it should or ought to be that way. Alternatively, this fallacy occurs when one concludes that something cannot be a particular way because it should not or ought not be that way. The moralistic fallacy is often described as the reverse of the is/ought fallacy, wherein one reasons fallaciously that because things (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  6
    Legal Morality and Moral Law in Kant. 김덕수 - 2021 - Journal of the Daedong Philosophical Association 97:15-36.
    시대적 진보에 의한 인간의 삶은 매우 많은 변화를 가져왔다. 그에 따라 우리 사회는 과거와 달리 보다 다원화되고 전문화되었으며, 그 과정에서 크고 작은 갈등과 충돌의 모습 을 보이고 있다. 이런 상황은 사회적이고 관계적 존재인 인간에게 끊임없이 갈등의 문제에 대한 해결을 요구해왔고, 그 해결은 대개 도덕이 아닌 법에 의해 이루어졌다. 하지만 우리 가 교육을 통해 배운 갈등과 충돌의 해결방법은 우선적으로 도덕적인 접근임에도 불구하 고, 도덕보다는 법이 우리의 삶을 더 많이 지배하고 있으며, 이 법을 통해 갈등과 충돌의 문제를 해결하고 있다. 또한 법의 논리가 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  25
    Legal punishment of immorality: once more into the breach.Kyle Swan - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (4):983-1000.
    Gerald Dworkin’s overlooked defense of legal moralism attempts to undermine the traditional liberal case for a principled distinction between behavior that is immoral and criminal and behavior that is immoral but not criminal. According to Dworkin, his argument for legal moralism “depends upon a plausible idea of what making moral judgments involves.” The idea Dworkin has in mind here is a metaethical principle that many have connected to morality/reasons internalism. I agree with Dworkin that this is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  8
    Ethics at the edges of law: Christian moralists and American legal thought.Cathleen Kaveny - 2018 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    Part I. Narratives and Norms -- 1 Tradition and development: Engaging John T. Noonan, Jr. -- 2 Creation and covenant: Engaging Stanley Hauerwas -- 3 Examples and rules-Engaging Jeffrey Stout -- Part II Love, Justice, and Law -- 4 Neighbor love and legal precedent: Engaging Gene Outka -- 5 Compassionate respect and victims' voices: Engaging Margaret Farley -- 6 Covenant fidelity and culture wars: Engaging Paul Ramsey -- Part III Legal Categories and Theological Problems -- 7 Juridical insights (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  10
    Legal imperfectionism.James Edwards - forthcoming - Jurisprudence:1-25.
    What role do moral norms play in the justification of legal norms? This is one of many questions about the relationship between law and morality. Let us call it the justificatory question for short...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  25
    Political Moralism and Constitutional Reasoning: A Reply to Bernard Williams.Roni Mann - 2020 - Res Publica 27 (2):235-253.
    Williams’s well-known critique of the ‘moralism’ of liberal political philosophy—its disconnect from political reality—holds special significance for the theory and practice of constitutional adjudication, where calls for ‘realism’ increasingly resound. Is constitutional discourse also guilty of moralism—as Williams himself thought—or might it succeed where political philosophy has failed? This paper reconstructs Williams’s critique of political moralism as one that decries the empty idealism of the philosophical project of abstraction: the quest for general, timeless, and universal principles drains (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  22
    Legal, Moral, and Metaphysical Truths: The Philosophy of Michael S. Moore.Kimberly Kessler Ferzan & Stephen J. Morse (eds.) - 2016 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press UK.
    Perhaps more than any other scholar, Michael Moore has argued that there are deep and necessary connections between metaphysics, morality, and law. Moore has developed every contour of a theory of criminal law, from philosophy of action to a theory of causation. Indeed, not only is he the central figure in retributive punishment but his moral realist position places him at the center of many jurisprudential debates. Comprised of essays by leading scholars, this volume discusses and challenges the work of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  28
    Drug Legalization: A Philosophical Analysis.Chris Meyers - 2023 - Springer Verlag.
    This textbook introduces students to the various arguments for and against the prohibition of recreational drugs. The arguments are carefully presented and analyzed, inviting students to consider the competing principles of liberty rights, paternalism, theories of punishment, legal moralism, and the social consequences of drug use and drug laws. Meyers extends this examination by presenting alternatives to the prohibition/legalization dichotomy, including harm reduction, decriminalization, and user licensing or on-premise use. The presentation invites readers to think clearly about the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  26
    James Seth on Natural Law and Legal Theory.Thom Brooks - 2012 - Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 18 (2):115-132.
    This article argues that James Seth provides illuminating contributions to our understanding of law and, more specifically, the natural law tradition. Seth defends a unique perspective through his emphasis on personalism that helps identify a distinctive and compelling account of natural law and legal moralism. The next section surveys standard positions in the natural law tradition. This is followed with an examination of Seth's approach and the article concludes with analysis of its wider importance for scholars of Seth's (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  35
    Ethics at the Edges of Law: Christian Moralists and American Legal Thought. By CathleenKaveny. Pp. xxi, 299, New York, Oxford University Press, 2018, $35.00/£22.99.Litigating Religions: An Essay on Human Rights, Courts, and Beliefs. By ChristopherMcCrudden. Pp. xv, 196, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2018, $65.00. [REVIEW]John R. Williams - 2019 - Heythrop Journal 60 (6):961-963.
  40.  22
    Ethics at the Edges of Law: Christian Moralists and American Legal Thought. By CathleenKaveny. Pp. xxi, 299, New York, Oxford University Press, 2018, $35.00/£22.99.Litigating Religions: An Essay on Human Rights, Courts, and Beliefs. By ChristopherMcCrudden. Pp. xv, 196, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2018, $65.00. [REVIEW]John R. Williams - 2019 - Heythrop Journal 60 (4):651-653.
  41.  44
    A Failed Refutation and an Insufficiently Developed Insight in Hart’s Law, Liberty, and Morality.Jeffrie G. Murphy - 2013 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (3):419-434.
    H. L. A. Hart, in his classic book Law, Liberty, and Morality, is unsuccessful in arguing that James Fitzjames Stephen’s observations about the role of vice in criminal sentencing have no relevance to a more general defense of legal moralism. He does, however, have a very important insight about the special significance of sexual liberty.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  9
    An “Ingenious Moralist”: Bernard Mandeville as a Precursor of Bentham.Ryu Susato - 2020 - Utilitas 32 (3):335-349.
    This article argues that Bernard Mandeville's ideas were more likely to have influenced Jeremy Bentham's writings than previously believed. The conventional interpretation of Mandeville as a forerunner of the Hayekian “theory of spontaneous order” has obscured Mandeville and Bentham's shared emphasis on legal and interventionist solutions for the issues of prostitution and prisoners. This influence is evinced by focusing on some of Mandeville's minor works, which anticipated some of Bentham's arguments. It is unlikely that Bentham directly knew of Mandeville's (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. MORAL STRUCTURE OF LEGAL OBLIGATION.Kuczynski John-Michael - 2006 - Dissertation, University of California, Santa Barbara
    What are laws, and do they necessarily have any basis in morality? The present work argues that laws are governmental assurances of protections of rights and that concepts of law and legal obligation must therefore be understood in moral terms. There are, of course, many immoral laws. But once certain basic truths are taken into account – in particular, that moral principles have a “dimension of weight”, to use an expression of Ronald Dworkin’s, and also that principled relations are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  14
    Building blocks of legal behaviour.Margaret Gruter & Monika Gruter Morhenn - 2000 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 1 (1-2):38.
    Flack and de Waal's exploration of basic building blocks of moral systems among non-human primates indicates that human legal systems and legal behaviour are not purely the product of the environment. An examination of some of the ways in which capacities for reciprocity, retributive behaviours, moralistic aggression, dispute resolution, sympathy, and empathy play roles in contemporary law and legal behaviour shows that these capacities are both ubiquitous and facilitative of legal systems. No attempt is made to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. France and the Ban on the Full-Face Veil.Sarah Roberts-Cady - 2014 - In Justin P. McBrayer (ed.), Introducing ethics: a critical thinking approach with readings. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 635-643.
    This article considers the appropriate limits of legal regulation through an analysis of the 2010 French law banning the wearing of full-face veils in public. The author examines the law from the perspective of John Stuart Mill's harm principle and Patrick Devlin's legal moralism. The author concludes that neither position provides a convincing justification for the French law.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  66
    Political Neutrality and Punishment.Matt Matravers - 2013 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (2):217-230.
    This paper is concerned with the tensions that arise when one juxtaposes one important liberal understanding of the nature and use of state power in circumstances of pluralism and (broadly) retributive accounts of punishment. The argument is that there are aspects of the liberal theory that seem to be in tension with aspects of retributive punishment, and that these tensions are difficult to avoid because of the attractiveness of precisely those features of each account. However, a proper understanding of both (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Theism and the Criminalization of Sin.Jeremy Koons - 2018 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10 (1):163-187.
    The free will theodicy places significant value on free will: free will is of such substantial value, that God’s gift of free will to humans was justified, even though this gift foreseeably results in the most monstrous of evils. I will argue that when a state criminalizes sin, it can restrict or eliminate citizens’ exercise of metaphysical free will with respect to choosing to partake in or refrain from these activities. Given the value placed on free will in the free (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Varied and Principled Understandings of Autonomy in English Law: Justifiable Inconsistency or Blinkered Moralism[REVIEW]John Coggon - 2007 - Health Care Analysis 15 (3):235-255.
    Autonomy is a concept that holds much appeal to social and legal philosophers. Within a medical context, it is often argued that it should be afforded supremacy over other concepts and interests. When respect for autonomy merely requires non-intervention, an adult’s right to refuse treatment is held at law to be absolute. This apparently simple statement of principle does not hold true in practice. This is in part because an individual must be found to be competent to make a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  49.  40
    The slippery slope argument against the legalization of voluntary euthanasia.W. H. Nielsen - 1987 - Journal of Social Philosophy 18 (1):12-27.
    In all great moral issues the moralist must choose and choosing has a price.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  79
    Unlocking Morality from Criminal Law.Thom Brooks - 2017 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 14 (3):339-352.
    This review article critically examines R. A. Duff and Stuart P. Green’s wide-ranging Philosophical Foundations of Criminal Law. The book captures well a crucial debate at the heart of its topic: is morality a key for understanding criminal law? I first consider legal moralism arguments answering this question in the affirmative and argue they should be rejected. I next consider alternatives to argue that philosophers of criminal law should look beyond legal moralism for more compelling theories (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000