Results for 'Common Sense Problem of Evil'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Defusing the Common Sense Problem of Evil.Chris Tweedt - 2015 - Faith and Philosophy 32 (4):391-403.
    The inductive argument from evil to the non-existence of God contains the premise that, probably, there is gratuitous evil. Some skeptical theists object: one's justification for the premise that, probably, there is gratuitous evil involves an inference from the proposition that we don't see a good reason for some evil to the proposition that it appears that there is no good reason for that evil, and they use a principle, "CORNEA," to block that inference. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  2.  52
    A Surviving Version of the Common Sense Problem of Evil.Jerome Gellman - 2017 - Faith and Philosophy 34 (1):82-92.
    Chris Tweedt has offered a solution to the “common sense problem of evil,” on which that there is gratuitous evil is justified non-inferentially as a trivial inference from non-inferentially justified premises by invoking versions of CORNEA. Tweedt claims his solution applies not only to the versions of the common sense problem of evil offered by Paul Draper and Trent Dougherty, but also to that offered by me in this journal in 1992. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  3.  63
    A Surviving Version of the Common Sense Problem of Evil.Jerome Gellman - 2017 - Faith and Philosophy 34 (1):82-92.
    Chris Tweedt has offered a solution to the “common sense problem of evil,” on which that there is gratuitous evil is justified non-inferentially as a trivial inference from non-inferentially justified premises by invoking versions of CORNEA. Tweedt claims his solution applies not only to the versions of the common sense problem of evil offered by Paul Draper and Trent Dougherty, but also to that offered by me in this journal in 1992. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  53
    The Perspectival Problem of Evil.Blake McAllister - 2020 - Faith and Philosophy 37 (4):421-450.
    Whether evil provides evidence against the existence of God, and to what degree, depends on how things seem to the subject—i.e., on one’s perspective. I explain three ways in which adopting an atheistic perspective can increase support for atheism via considerations of evil. The first is by intensifying the common sense problem of evil by making evil seem gratuitous or intrinsically wrong to allow. The second is by diminishing the apparent fit between theism (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5. The problem of evil.Paul Draper - 2008 - In Thomas P. Flint & Michael Rea (eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophical theology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This article focuses on questions about evil which are both theological and doxastic, and more specifically alethic – i.e., questions about whether what we know about evil can be used to establish the falsity or probable falsity of the belief or proposition that God exists. Such a focus is natural for agnostics. More generally, it is natural for anyone who is engaged in genuine inquiry about whether or not God exists. A specific concept of God is employed – (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  6.  65
    The Problem with the Problem of Evil.Shane Andre - 2021 - Open Journal of Philosophy 11 (2):336-354.
    The problem of evil has been around for centuries but as yet no consensus exists as to its significance for atheism or theism. After a brief historical review, I focus on the debate between two leading contemporary philosophers, Rowe and Plantinga, and argue that neither has succeeded in resolving the evidential version of the problem of evil. It is time to turn from the theological issue to practical issues about pointless suffering. Using a common (...) approach, I argue that there are countless cases of pointless suffering and that they deserve our undivided attention. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  6
    Dionysius on the Problem of Evil: Lessons One can Learn.Jijimon Alakkalam Joseph - 2015 - Tattva - Journal of Philosophy 7 (2):79-95.
    The problem of evil is a much-debated issue and is as old as human history itself. Evil is a universal and the most common experience of humans, in the sense it functions as a common denominator and no one escapes. Evil causes a sense of isolation. This is evident in the lives of theists. Evil isolates humans from God. Evil is also one such experience that is personal and existential. (...) brings along a lot of meaninglessness. Here it expresses itself as victimization. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Hume and the Problem of Evil.Michael Tooley - 2011 - In Jeffrey J. Jordan (ed.), Philosophy of Religion: The Key Thinkers. London and New York: Continuum. pp. 159-86.
    1.1 The Concept of Evil The problem of evil, in the sense relevant here, concerns the question of the reasonableness of believing in the existence of a deity with certain characteristics. In most discussions, the deity is God, understood as an omnipotent, omniscient, and morally perfect person. But the problem of evil also arises, as Hume saw very clearly, for deities that are less than all-powerful, less than all-knowing, and less than morally perfect. What (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Is mainstream economics against common sense? Problems of scale and transitivity too.Terence Rajivan Edward - manuscript
    Mainstream economics, with its rational actor models, appears to be against common sense. For example, it does not take into account how tribal people are. They have a group identity and they are largely concerned with perpetuating that identity. I propose that mainstream economics is not more opposed to common sense than alternative frameworks. The appendix introduces a counterexample to transitivity of preferences, which I assume is where the chief value of the paper is.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Agency and responsibility: a common-sense moral psychology.Jeanette Kennett - 2001 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Is it ever possible for people to act freely and intentionally against their better judgement? Is it ever possible to act in opposition to one's strongest desire? If either of these questions are answered in the negative, the common-sense distinctions between recklessness, weakness of will and compulsion collapse. This would threaten our ordinary notion of self-control and undermine our practice of holding each other responsible for moral failure. So a clear and plausible account of how weakness of will (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  11.  32
    Scottish common sense and nineteenth-century american law: A critical appraisal.John Mikhail - 2008
    In her insightful and stimulating article, The Mind of a Moral Agent, Professor Susanna Blumenthal traces the influence of Scottish Common Sense philosophy on early American law. Among other things, Blumenthal argues that the basic model of moral agency upon which early American jurists relied, which drew heavily from Common Sense philosophers like Thomas Reid, generated certain paradoxical conclusions about legal responsibility that later generations were forced to confront. "Having cast their lot with the Common (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  7
    Skeptical Theism, CORNEA, and Common Sense Epistemology.Thomas D. Senor - 2013 - In Justin P. McBrayer & Daniel Howard‐Snyder (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil. Oxford, UK: Wiley. pp. 426–443.
    The problem of evil is best understood as an instance of what I call “the problem of defeated expectations.” These problems arise for theism when the world we experience does not conform to what we would expect to find in a world created and sustained by a being who is omnipotent, omniscient, and omnibenevolent. In this chapter, I explore skeptical theism, which is an approach to the evidential problem of evil that argues that, at least (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  68
    Hutcheson's moral sense and the problem of innateness.Daniel Carey - 2000 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (1):103-110.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 38.1 (2000) 103-110 [Access article in PDF] Hutcheson's Moral Sense and the Problem of Innateness Daniel Carey National University of Ireland Francis Hutcheson's philosophy arguably represented a delicate, and at times precarious, synthesis of positions laid out by John Locke and the third Earl of Shaftesbury. From Shaftesbury, whose influence he acknowledged explicitly in the title page of the first edition (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  20
    The Problem of Evil from a Decolonial Viewpoint.Luís Cordeiro-Rodrigues & Jonathan O. Chimakonam - 2023 - Philosophia: International Journal of Philosophy (Philippine e-journal) 24 (1):51-72.
    In this article, we contest the idea that evil does not exist, or that it is a mistaken grasp of reality to contend that evil exists. We analyze two versions of this argument: the 'orchestra argument' and the 'mystical argument.' In common, these arguments contend that those who affirm the existence of evil in the world have a limited view of reality. We argue that these views are either over-abstract from reality or do not offer a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  50
    Explaining Evil Behavior: Using Kant and M. Scott Peck to Solve the Puzzle of Understanding the Moral Psychology of Evil People.David E. Ward - 2002 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 9 (1):1-12.
    I assume that we find it hard to understand, for example, how a person could harm another person in cold blood. I then set out Kant's reason's for thinking that, strictly speaking, evil behavior is impossible: people may act on wicked desires but deliberate wrong-doing is not a genuine phenomenon. However, Kant's view is at odds with our common sense intuitions about morally evil behavior, namely, that such behavior is possible, albeit difficult to understand. I then (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  10
    Worldviews & the problem of evil: a compartive approach.Ronnie P. Campbell - 2019 - Bellingham, WA: Lexham Press.
    How does the Christian response to the problem of evil contrast with that of other worldviews? Most attempts at answering the problem of evil either present a straightforward account of the truth claims of Christianity or defend a minimalist concept of God. This book is different. Inside, you'll examine four worldviews' responses to the problem of evil. Then, you'll hear the author's argument that Christian theism makes better sense of the phenomenon of (...) in the worldâe"equipping you to reach an informed conclusion. This book's unique approachâe"integrating worldviews with apologetics with theologyâe"will give you a better understanding of the debate surrounding the problem of evil, in both philosophy and theology. Learn to think cogently and theologically about the problem of evil and Christianity's ability to answer its challenges with Worldviews and the Problem of Evil as your guide. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. National Defence, Self Defence, and the Problem of Political Aggression.Seth Lazar - 2014 - In Cécile Fabre & Seth Lazar (eds.), The Morality of Defensive War. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 10-38.
    Wars are large-scale conflicts between organized groups of belligerents, which involve suffering, devastation, and brutality unlike almost anything else in human experience. Whatever one’s other beliefs about morality, all should agree that the horrors of war are all but unconscionable, and that warfare can be justified only if we have some compel- ling account of what is worth fighting for, which can justify contributing, as individu- als and as groups, to this calamitous endeavour. Although this question should obviously be central (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  18.  12
    Thankfulness: Kierkegaard’s First-Person Approach to the Problem of Evil.Heiko Schulz - 2024 - Philosophies 9 (2):32.
    The present paper argues that, despite appearance to the contrary, Kierkegaard’s writings offer promising argumentational resources for addressing the problem of evil. According to Kierkegaard, however, in order to make use of these resources at all, one must necessarily be willing to shift the battleground, so to speak: from a third- to a genuine first-person perspective, namely the perspective of what Climacus dubs Religiousness A. All (yet also only) those who seek deliberate self-annihilation before God—a God in relation (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  57
    Absolute idealism and the problem of evil.N. N. Trakakis - 2017 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 82 (1):47-69.
    The problem of evil is regularly regarded as posing a serious threat to theistic belief. However, contemporary philosophers of religion have overlooked the ways in which this problem has been, or could be, handled by theists committed to the metaphysics of idealism. In seeking to redress this lacuna, I turn to the systems of the British idealists, popular in the late nineteenth century though now out of favour, and in particular the work of F.H. Bradley, while also (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  40
    The problem of “god” in psychology of religion: Lonergan's “common sense” versus “theory”.Daniel A. Helminiak - 2017 - Zygon 52 (2):380-418.
    The emphasis on God in American psychology of religion generates the problem of explaining divine-versus-natural causality in “spiritual experiences.” Especially “theistic psychology” champions divine involvement. However, its argument exposes a methodological error: to pit popular religious opinions against technical scientific conclusions. Countering such homogenizing “postmodern agnosticism,” Bernard Lonergan explained these two as different modes of thinking: “common sense” and “theory”—which resolves the problem: When theoretical science is matched with theoretical theology, “the God-hypothesis” explains the existence of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  25
    Animal Suffering and the Darwinian Problem of Evil.John R. Schneider - 2020 - Cambridge University Press.
    John R. Schneider explores the problem that animal suffering, caused by the inherent nature of Darwinian evolution, poses to belief in theism. Examining the aesthetic aspects of this moral problem, Schneider focuses on the three prevailing approaches to it: that the Fall caused animal suffering in nature (Lapsarian Theodicy), that Darwinian evolution was the only way for God to create an acceptably good and valuable world (Only-Way Theodicy), and that evolution is the source of major, God-justifying beauty (Aesthetic (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  27
    Duhkha & Karma: the problem of evil and God’s Omnipotence. [REVIEW]Purushottama Bilimoria - 1995 - Sophia 34 (1):92-119.
    This paper arises from a symposium on philosophical reconstructions of religious doctrines within the 16th conference of the Australasian Association for the Study of Religions held in the Armidale, N.S.W., July, 1993. The convenor, Peter Forrest, read a paper on ‘Making sense of karma and original sin’, and I elected to discuss the doctrine of karma in the context of the problem of evil. Forrest's paper appeared in the previous issue ofSophia and I shall be making reference (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23. Silencing Theodicy with Enthusiasm: Aesthetic Experience as a Response to the Problem of Evil in Shaftesbury, Annie Dillard, and the Book of Job.John McAteer - 2016 - Heythrop Journal 57 (5):788-795.
    The problem of evil is not only a logical problem about God's goodness but also an existential problem about the sense of God's presence, which the Biblical book of Job conceives as a problem of aesthetic experience. Thus, just as theism can be grounded in religious experience, atheism can be grounded in experience of evil. This phenomenon is illustrated by two contrasting literary descriptions of aesthetic experience by Jean-Paul Sartre and Annie Dillard. I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  7
    A common-sense approach to the problem of the itinerary stadion.Irina Tupikova - 2022 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 76 (4):319-361.
    Estimating the length of the Greek stadion remains controversial. This paper highlights the pitfalls of a purely metrological approach to this problem and proposes a formal differentiation between metrologically defined ancient measuring units and other measures used to estimate long distances. The common-sense approach to the problem is strengthened by some cross-over documentary evidence for usage of the so-called itinerary stadion in antiquity. We discuss the possibility of using statistical analysis methods to estimate the length of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  11
    God and the Problem of Evil: Why Soul-Making Won't Suffice.Brian D. Earp - 2024 - Think 23 (66):11-15.
    If you believe in the existence of an infinitely good, all-knowing, and all-powerful deity (‘God’), how do you explain the reality of evil – including the inexpressible suffering and death of innocents? Wouldn't God be forced to vanquish such suffering due to God's very nature? Alvin Plantinga has argued, convincingly, that if the possibility of ultimate goodness somehow necessarily required that evil be allowed to exist, God, being omnibenevolent, would have to allow it. But as John Hick has (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  34
    The Image of God: The Problem of Evil and the Problem of Mourning.Eleonore Stump - 2022 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    The problem of evil has generated varying attempts at theodicy. To show that suffering is defeated for a sufferer, a theodicy argues that there is an outweighing benefit which could not have been gotten without the suffering. Typically, this condition has the tacit presupposition given that this is a post-Fall world. Consequently, there is a sense in which human suffering would not be shown to be defeated even if there were a successful theodicy because a theodicy typically (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  21
    God’s Existence and the Problem of Evil in African Philosophy of Religion.Ada Agada - 2023 - In Björn Freter, Elvis Imafidon & Mpho Tshivhase (eds.), Handbook of African Philosophy. Dordrecht, New York: Springer Verlag. pp. 555-574.
    Traditional African societies tend to favor a theocentric and anthropocentric conception of the universe, with God at the top of the hierarchy of being, in which the human sphere is a major center of influence and meaning. God is sometimes conceived in the traditional theistic sense and attributed with superlative qualities of omnipotence, omniscience, and benevolence. On the other hand, a more critical study of oral sources of African traditional religious thought constrains the traditional theistic interpretation and presents the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  43
    Vedanta Solution of the Problem of Evil.Kali Prasad - 1930 - Philosophy 5 (17):62-.
    Vedānta endeavours to base itself essentially on the facts of experience—in the fullest sense of the term. It recognizes the occurrence of everyday experience and the so-called fact of evil, but it refuses to view them as real. The real, it says, like Hegel, does not exist, and that which exists is not real. Evil is only an “existent"—as all this Samsara is—but not the ultimate Real. But it will be at once objected that if evil (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. How Divine Hiddenness Sheds Light on the Problem of Evil.Travis Dumsday - 2015 - International Philosophical Quarterly 55 (3):315-323.
    The problems of evil and of divine hiddenness are the two most prominent arguments for atheism in the contemporary literature on the philosophy of religion. But relatively little has been written on the possible relations between these two problems, and especially on whether a solution to one could shed light on a solution to the other. I explore this question here by arguing that a resolution to the hiddenness problem could help address the problem of evil, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  3
    Common Sense, Space, and The Problem of Troubled Consciousness.Kevin McGinley - 1997 - Method 15 (2):169-189.
  31. Thomas Reid and the problem of induction: from common experience to common sense.Benjamin W. Redekop - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33 (1):35-57.
    By the middle of the eighteenth century the new science had challenged the intellectual primacy of common experience in favor of recondite, expert and even counter-intuitive knowledge increasingly mediated by specialized instruments. Meanwhile modern philosophy had also problematized the perceptions of common experience — in the case of David Hume this included our perception of causal relations in nature, a fundamental precondition of scientific endeavor.In this article I argue that, in responding to the ‘problem of induction’ as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  25
    Free Will and the Problem of Evil.C. Mason Myers - 1987 - Religious Studies 23 (2):289 - 294.
    Hume after arguing for the compatibility of liberty and necessity, a view now known as soft determinism or compatibilism , noted that it is not ‘possible to explain distinctly, how the Deity can be the mediate cause of the actions of sin and moral turpitude’. It seems that Hume is correct if the explanation must show specifically why an omnipotent and omnibenevolent deity must permit certain actions that to human reason seem to be unnecessary evils. On the other hand if (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. The Hiddenness Problem and the Problem of Evil.J. L. Schellenberg - 2010 - Faith and Philosophy 27 (1):45-60.
    The problem of Divine hiddenness, or the hiddenness problem, is more and more commonly being treated as independent of the problem of evil, and as rivalling the latter in significance. Are we in error if we acquiesce in these tendencies? Only a careful investigation into relations between the hiddenness problem and the problem of evil can help us see. Such an investigation is undertaken here. What we will find is that when certain knots (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34.  40
    Schelling’s pantheism and the problem of evil.Olli Pitkänen - 2017 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 78 (4-5):361-372.
    Any religious worldview, understood in the sense that ‘life has a purpose’, has to face the problem of evil. The problem of evil has been particularly intensively discussed in the Aristotelian–Scholastic–Christian tradition. The most popular solution has been to deny that anything truly evil actually exists. It is hard to conceive why an omnipotent and perfectly good God would allow evil to appear. Yet, Western culture has been and still is full of imagery (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  15
    "London" and the Fundamental Problem of Hermeneutics.Joel Weinsheimer - 1982 - Critical Inquiry 9 (2):303-322.
    In the preface to the Yale edition of Samuel Johnson’s poems, the editors remark that “for a modern reader who can recreate the situation in which [“London”] was written, it may still be exciting enough. But to one with less imaginative capacity or historical knowledge, its appeal lies in Johnson’s skillful handling of the couplet.”2 To assist us in re-creating the milieu of 1738, the editors supply the usual notes identifying various historical personages and events which are no longer in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  30
    Does “Divine Hiddenness” Neutralize the Problem of Evil? Is Process Theodicy More Adequate?Ruslan Elistratov - 2020 - Process Studies 49 (1):36-53.
    This article critically engages Paul Moser’s “Divine Hiddenness Response” to the problem of evil—an approach to have recently come out of traditional free-will theism. I begin with identifying the initial common ground between Mosers thought and process theology that arguably coincides with what can be called the "Four Noble Truths of Christianity. ” Howevery when confronted with the problem of evil that threatens the credibility of these truths. Moser offers an epistemic strategy to address this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  45
    Possible-Worlds Metaphysics and the Logical Problem of Evil.Joseph L. Lombardi - 2018 - International Philosophical Quarterly 58 (1):19-29.
    Alvin Plantinga’s solution to J. L. Mackie’s logical problem of evil invokes possible-worlds metaphysics. There are reasons for thinking that the solution is, at least, problematic. Difficulties emerge in the attempts to answer four related questions. Can God’s necessary existence, understood in terms of possible-world metaphysics, make God’s actual existence impossible to explain? Can an omniscient being with knowledge of the contents of every possible world prove ignorant of the consequences of his creative acts? Can an immoral action (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  85
    Reflections on the Deep Connection Between Problems of Evil and Problems of Divine Hiddenness.Trent Dougherty - 2016 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 8 (4):65--84.
    In the literature on the subject, it is common to understand the problem of divine hiddenness and the problem of evil as distinct problems. Schellenberg and van Inwagen are representative. Such a sharp distinction is not so obvious to me. In this essay, I explore the relationship between the problem of evil and the problem of divine hiddenness.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. God and possible worlds: The modal problem of evil.Theodore Guleserian - 1983 - Noûs 17 (2):221-238.
    Using four principles common to several theories about possible worlds, It is argued that the necessary existence of a divine being that is essentially omnipotent, Omniscient, And morally perfect is impossible. The central argument employs the premise that there are possible worlds that any divine being ought not to actualize (because of their evil contents). This premise is then defended on the grounds that the same sort of justification that we give for other modal statements that we accept (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  40.  89
    Formalizing common sense: an operator-based approach to the Tibbles–Tib problem.Ingvar Johansson - 2008 - Synthese 163 (2):217-225.
    The paper argues, that a direct formalization of the way common sense thinks about the numerical identity of enduring entities, requires that traditional predicate logic is developed. If everyday language mirrors the world, then persons, organisms, organs, cells, and ordinary material things can lose some parts but nonetheless remain numerically exactly the same entity. In order to formalize this view, two new logical operators are introduced; and they bring with them some non-standard syntax. One of the operators is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  30
    Possible-Worlds Metaphysics and the Logical Problem of Evil.Joseph L. Lombardi - 2018 - International Philosophical Quarterly 58 (1):19-29.
    Alvin Plantinga’s solution to J. L. Mackie’s logical problem of evil invokes possible-worlds metaphysics. There are reasons for thinking that the solution is, at least, problematic. Difficulties emerge in the attempts to answer four related questions. (1) Can God’s necessary existence, understood in terms of possible-world metaphysics, make God’s actual existence impossible to explain? (2) Can an omniscient being with knowledge of the contents of every possible world (a being endowed with “middle knowledge”) prove ignorant of the consequences (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  40
    A Common Sense Approach to the Mind-Body Problem.Russell A. Lascola - 1992 - Journal of Philosophical Research 17:279-286.
    In a popular book and a widely anthologized article, Richard Taylor argues for a materialistic account of human nature based on considerations of common sense. While I do not argue against materialism, per se, I offer an extended critique of Taylor’s position that common sense unambiguously supports his version of materialism. I also argue that his account of the nature of psychological processes is of dubious philosophical value.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  19
    A Common Sense Approach to the Mind-Body Problem.Russell A. Lascola - 1992 - Journal of Philosophical Research 17:279-286.
    In a popular book and a widely anthologized article, Richard Taylor argues for a materialistic account of human nature based on considerations of common sense. While I do not argue against materialism, per se, I offer an extended critique of Taylor’s position that common sense unambiguously supports his version of materialism. I also argue that his account of the nature of psychological processes is of dubious philosophical value.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Scottish Common Sense in Germany, 1768--1800: A Contribution to the History of Critical Philosophy.Manfred Kuehn - 1980 - Dissertation, Mcgill University (Canada)
    This work attempts to show that the Scottish common sense philosophers Thomas Reid, James Oswald and James Beattie, had a substantial influence upon the development of German thought during the period of the late enlightenment. Their works were thoroughly reviewed in German philosophical journals and translated into German soon after they had appeared in English. Whether it was Mendelssohn, a rationalist, Lossius, a materialist, Feder, a sensationalist, Tetens, a critical empiricist, or Hamann and Jacobi, irrationalist philosophers of faith, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  45. Does hard determinism render the problem of evil even harder?Nick Trakakis - 2006 - Ars Disputandi: The Online Journal for Philosophy of Religion 6 (6):1-1.
    Hard determinism, in theological dress, holds that there is no human free will since God is the sufficient active cause of everything that happens in creation. It is surprising that, in the ever-growing literature on the problem of evil, very little attention has been paid to theodicies that adopt a hard determinist outlook. It is commonly assumed that without free will the theodical project is a non-starter. I challenge this long-held assumption by, firstly, developing a cumulative-style theodicy from (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  13
    Enlightened common sense I: clarifying and developing the concepts of depth, emergence, and transfactuality.Dominic Holland - 2019 - Journal of Critical Realism 18 (1):56-82.
    This article is the first in a series of four articles that engage critically with the arguments of two recent and significant additions to the literature on critical realism, namely Bhaskar’s ‘Enlightened Common Sense: The Philosophy of Critical Realism’, and Bhaskar et al.’s ‘Interdisciplinarity and Wellbeing: A Critical Realist General Theory of Interdisciplinarity’. Using the method of immanent critique and focusing mainly, but not exclusively, on the arguments of Enlightened Common Sense, I identify, and propose solutions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47. Review: Murray Shanahan, Solving the Frame Problem. A Mathematical Investigation of the Common Sense Law of Inertia. [REVIEW]Michael Gelfond - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (3):1186-1188.
  48.  25
    Shanahan Murray. Solving the frame problem. A mathematical investigation of the common sense law of inertia. Artificial intelligence series. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., and London, 1997, xxxiv + 407 pp. [REVIEW]Michael Gelfond - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (3):1186-1188.
  49. Common-sense Realism and the Unimaginable Otherness of Science.Bradley Monton - 2007 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 11 (2):117-126.
    Bas van Fraassen endorses both common-sense realism — the view, roughly, that the ordinary macroscopic objects that we take to exist actually do exist — and constructive empiricism — the view, roughly, that the aim of science is truth about the observable world. But what happens if common-sense realism and science come into conflict? I argue that it is reasonable to think that they could come into conflict, by giving some motivation for a mental monist solution (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. Humor, Common Sense and the Future of Metaphysics in the Prolegomena.Melissa Merritt - 2021 - In Peter Thielke (ed.), Kant's Prolegomena: A Critical Guide. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. pp. 9-26.
    Kant’s Prolegomena is a piece of philosophical advertising: it exists to convince the open-minded “future teacher” of metaphysics that the true critical philosophy — i.e., the Critique — provides the only viable solution to the problem of metaphysics (i.e. its failure to make any genuine progress). To be effective, a piece of advertising needs to know its audience. This chapter argues that Kant takes his reader to have some default sympathies for the common-sense challenge to metaphysics originating (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000