Results for 'Henri Aristotle'

(not author) ( search as author name )
1000+ found
Order:
  1.  2
    Aristotle Meteorologica.Henry Desmond Pritchard Aristotle & Lee - 1952 - Heinemann Harvard University Press.
  2. The fifth book of the Nicomachean ethics of Aristotle.Henry Aristotle & Jackson - 1879 - New York,: Arno Press. Edited by Henry Jackson.
  3. A Paraphrase of the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle.Henry W. Chandler & Aristotle - 1859 - H. Hammans ..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Miscellaneous Emendations & Suggestions.Henry W. Chandler & Aristotle - 1866 - Rivingtons.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Aristotle on pleasure and the worst form of akrasia.Devin Henry - 2002 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5 (3):255-270.
    The focus of this paper is Aristotle's solution to the problem inherited from Socrates: How could a man fail to restrain himself when he believes that what he desires is wrong? In NE 7 Aristotle attempts to reconcile the Socratic denial of akrasia with the commonly held opinion that people act in ways they know to be bad, even when it is in their power to act otherwise. This project turns out to be largely successful, for what (...) shows us is that if we distinguish between two ways of having knowledge (potentially and actually), the Socratic thesis can effectively account for a wide range of cases (collectively referred to here as drunk-akrasia) in which an agent acts contrary to his general knowledge of the Good, yet can still be said to know in the qualified sense that his actions are wrong. However, Book 7 also shows that the Socratic account of akrasia cannot take us any farther than drunk-akrasia, for unlike drunk-akrasia, genuine akrasia cannot be reduced to a failure of knowledge. This agent knows in the unqualified sense that his actions are wrong. The starting-point of my argument is that Aristotle's explanation of genuine akrasia requires a different solution than the one found in NE 7 which relies on the distinction between qualified and unqualified knowing: genuinely akratic behaviour is due to the absence of an internal conflict that a desire for the proper pleasures of temperance would create if he could experience them. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  6. Aristotle’s Pluralistic Realism.Devin Henry - 2011 - The Monist 94 (2):197-220.
    In this paper I explore Aristotle’s views on natural kinds and the compatibility of pluralism and realism, a topic that has generated considerable interest among contemporary philosophers. I argue that, when it came to zoology, Aristotle denied that there is only one way of organizing the diversity of the living world into natural kinds that will yield a single, unified system of classification. Instead, living things can be grouped and regrouped into various cross-cutting kinds on the basis of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  7. Aristotle on the Mechanisms of Inheritance.Devin Henry - 2006 - Journal of the History of Biology 39 (3):425-455.
    In this paper I address an important question in Aristotle’s biology, What are the causal mechanisms behind the transmission of biological form? Aristotle’s answer to this question, I argue, is found in Generation of Animals Book 4 in connection with his investigation into the phenomenon of inheritance. There we are told that an organism’s reproductive material contains a set of "movements" which are derived from the various "potentials" of its nature (the internal principle of change that initiates and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  8. How sexist is Aristotle's developmantal biology?Devin Henry - 2007 - Phronesis 52 (3):251-69.
    The aim of this paper is to evaluate the level of gender bias in Aristotle’s Generation of Animals while exercising due care in the analysis of its arguments. I argue that while the GA theory is clearly sexist, the traditional interpretation fails to diagnose the problem correctly. The traditional interpretation focuses on three main sources of evidence: (1) Aristotle’s claim that the female is, as it were, a “disabled” (πεπηρωμένον) male; (2) the claim at GA IV.3, 767b6-8 that (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  9. Aristotle on Epigenesis.Devin Henry - 2018
    It has become somewhat of a platitude to call Aristotle the first epigenesist insofar as he thought form and structure emerged gradually from an unorganized, amorphous embryo. But modern biology now recognizes two senses of “epigenesis”. The first is this more familiar idea about the gradual emergence of form and structure, which is traditionally opposed to the idea of preformationism. But modern biologists also use “epigenesis” to emphasize the context-dependency of the process itself. Used in this sense development is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  67
    Aristotle and mathematics.Henry Mendell - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  11. Bridging the Gap Between Aristotle's Science and Ethics.Devin Henry & Karen Margrethe Nielsen (eds.) - 2015 - Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
    This book consolidates emerging research on Aristotle's science and ethics in order to explore the extent to which the concepts, methods, and practices he developed for scientific inquiry and explanation are used to investigate moral phenomena. Each chapter shows, in a different way, that Aristotle's ethics is much more like a science than it is typically represented. The upshot of this is twofold. First, uncovering the links between Aristotle's science and ethics promises to open up new and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  32
    Aristotle on Matter, Form, and Moving Causes: The Hylomorphic Theory of Substantial Generation.Devin Henry - 2019 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book examines an important area of Aristotle's philosophy: the generation of substances. While other changes presuppose the existence of a substance (Socrates grows taller), substantial generation results in something genuinely new that did not exist before (Socrates himself). The central argument of this book is that Aristotle defends a 'hylomorphic' model of substantial generation. In its most complete formulation, this model says that substantial generation involves three principles: (1) matter, which is the subject from which the change (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  52
    Aristotle: a contemporary appreciation.Henry Babcock Veatch - 1974 - Bloomington,: Indiana University Press.
    Under the guidance of Professor Veatch, Aristotle stands forth again as the philosopher who, above all, speaks simply and directly to the common sense of all ...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14. Optimality and Teleology in Aristotle's Natural Science.Devin Henry - manuscript
    In this paper I examine the role of optimality reasoning in Aristotle’s natural science. By “optimality reasoning” I mean reasoning that appeals to some conception of “what is best” in order to explain why things are the way they are. We are first introduced to this pattern of reasoning in the famous passage at Phaedo 97b8-98a2, where (Plato’s) Socrates invokes “what is best” as a cause (aitia) of things in nature. This passage can be seen as the intellectual ancestor (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Aristotle’s Generation of Animals.Devin Henry - 2008 - In Georgios Anagnostopoulos (ed.), A Companion to Aristotle. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    A general article discussing philosophical issues arising in connection with Aristotle's "Generation of Animals" (Chapter from Blackwell's Companion to Aristotle).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  80
    Aristotle on definition (review).Devin Henry - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (3):pp. 478-480.
    Aristotle on Definition is an exceptional piece of scholarship. Its arguments are carefully justified, sophisticated, and far-reaching. Those interested in Aristotle's theory of definition will find this book a nice compliment to David Charles' Meaning and Essence. Whereas Charles examines Aristotle's theory of syllogistic definitions, Deslauriers focuses mainly on the concept of immediate definitions .It is impossible to do justice to the entire book. In what follows I shall attempt to isolate one of its main lines of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  47
    Aristotle's Metaphysics Z 13.Henry Teloh - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (1):77 - 89.
    Aristotle states in Metaphysics Z13 that nothing said universally τῶν ϰαϑόλου λεγομένων is substance, rather the substance of each thing is particular to it. The natural interpretation of this statement is that being said universally is a sufficient condition for not being substance. But this claim is very perplexing since it is the key premiss in the following apparently inconsistent set:Form is substance.Form is universal.Nothing universal or said universally is substance, rather the substance of something is particular ἴδιος to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  99
    Understanding Aristotle's Reproductive Hylomorphism.Devin Henry - 2006 - Apeiron 39 (3):257 - 287.
  19. Aristotle and the Later Tradition: Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 1991.Henry Blumenthal & Julia Annas (eds.) - 1991 - Clarendon Press.
    This volume contains papers by a group of leading experts on Aristotle and the later Aristotelian tradition of Neoplatonism. The discussion ranges from Aristotle's treatment of Parmenides, the most important pre-Socratic Greek philosopher, to Neoplatonic and medieval use of Aristotle, for which Aristotle himself set guidelines in his discussions of his predecessors. Traces of these guidelines can be seen in the work of Plotinus, and that of the later Greek commentators on Aristotle. The study of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  82
    Degrees of finality and the highest good in Aristotle.Henry S. Richardson - 1992 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (3):327-352.
    This article develops a uniform interpretation of "pursuit for the sake of an end", explaining what an "unqualified final" end (sought solely for its own sake) offers that a (merely) final one does not and providing an improved account of what Aristotle means by an "ultimate end". This interpretation sheds light on (1) the regress argument at the outset of "N.E." I.2, (2) the way Aristotle argues for the existence of a highest good, (3) the special contribution of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  21.  28
    Two Geometrical Examples From Aristotle's Metaphysics.Henry Mendell - 1984 - Classical Quarterly 34 (02):359-.
    The discussion of mathematical knowledge and its relation to the construction of an appropriate diagram in Aristotle's Metaphysics Θ 9. 1051 a21—33 is an important, if compressed, account of Aristotle's most mature thoughts on mathematical knowledge. The discussion of what sort of previous knowledge one must have for understanding a theorem recalls the discussion at An. Post. A 1. 71 a 17–21, where the epistemological point is similar and the examples the same. The first example, that the interior (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22. Does Aristotle have a Mechanics?Henri Carteron - 1975 - In Jonathan Barnes, Malcolm Schofield & Richard Sorabji (eds.), Articles on Aristotle. London: Duckworth. pp. 1--161.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23. Putting Aristotle's Physics in its Place: A Discussion of B. Morison, On Location.Henry Mendell - 2005 - In David Sedley (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Xxviii: Summer 2005. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  62
    Topoi on Topos: The Development o f Aristotle's Concept of Place.Henry Mendell - 1987 - Phronesis 32 (1):206-231.
  25.  20
    What Aristotle Should Have Said in Metaphysics Z.Henry Teloh - 1982 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):241-255.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  38
    Aristotle, the Nicomachean ethics: a commentary.Harold Henry Joachim - 1951 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press. Edited by D. A. Rees.
    An edited collection of lectures delivered by the late H. H. Joachim on the subject of Aristotle's Nichomachean Ethics.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  27. Aristotle and the Later Tradition: Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 1991.Henry Blumenthal & Howard Robinson (eds.) - 1991 - Oxford University Press UK.
    This volume contains papers by a group of leading experts on Aristotle and the later Aristotelian tradition of Neoplatonism. The discussion ranges from Aristotle's treatment of Parmenides, the most important pre-Socratic Greek philosopher, to Neoplatonic and medieval use of Aristotle, for which Aristotle himself set guidelines in his discussions of his predecessors. Traces of these guidelines can be seen in the work of Plotinus, and that of the later Greek commentators on Aristotle. The study of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. The Fifth Book of the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle.Henry Jackson - 1879 - Mind 4 (14):284-286.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  29.  5
    Aristotle's Metaphysics Z 13.Henry Teloh - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (1):77-89.
    Aristotle states inMetaphysicsZ13 (1038b9-11) that nothing said universally τῶν ϰαϑόλου λεγομένων is substance (οὐαία), rather the substance of each thing is particular to it (οὐαία ἐϰάστου ὴ ίδιος ἐϰάστῳ). The natural interpretation of this statement is that being said universally is a sufficient condition for not being substance. But this claim is very perplexing since it is the key premiss in the following apparently inconsistent set:(1)Form is substance.(2)Form is universal.(3)Nothing universal or said universally is substance, rather the substance of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  42
    Essence and definition in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals.Devin Henry - 2021 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 29 (5):763-783.
    In this paper, I argue that the Parts of Animals [PA] should be seen as continuing in the tradition of those earlier natural scientists who “investigated the material principle of things and that s...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Aristotle.Harold Henry Joachim - 1951 - Oxford,: Clarendon Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  32. Desire and the Good in De Anima.Henry S. Richardson - 1992 - In Martha C. Nussbaum & Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's de Anima. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    This essay presents an interpretation of the theory of animal movement that emphasizes the place Aristotle accords the good as the object of desire and the coordinate importance he assigns to desire and discernment. This interpretation is based on two competing models: the desire-based model, where the shape of the account of any action is based on some one occurrent desire; and the good-based model, where the account starts from some object aimed at as good. It is argued that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  16
    Aristotle's theory of the syllogism: a logico-philosophical study of Book A of the prior analytics.Henry Veatch - 1972 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 2 (4):369-378.
  34.  34
    Studies in Aristotle: Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy vol. 9.Henry Mendell - 1989 - Ancient Philosophy 9 (2):340-350.
  35.  43
    Practical Reasoning About Final Ends.Henry S. Richardson - 1994 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    Henry Richardson argues that we can determine our ends rationally. He constructs a rich and original theory of how we can reason about our final goals. Richardson defuses the counter-arguments for the limits of rational deliberation, and develops interesting ideas about how his model might be extended to interpersonal deliberation of ends, taking him to the borders of political theory. Along the way Richardson offers illuminating discussions of, inter alia, Aristotle, Aquinas, Sidgwick, and Dewey, as well as the work (...)
  36. Aristotle and Neoplatonism in Late Antiquity. Interpretations of the De anima.Henry J. Blumenthal - 1996 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 60 (2):379-380.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  7
    Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy: Aristotle and the Later Tradition. 1991. Supplemantary volume.Henry Blumenthal (ed.) - 1991 - Oxford University Press on Demand.
    This volume contains papers by a group of leading experts on Aristotle and the later Aristotelian tradition of Neoplatonism. The discussion ranges from Aristotle's treatment of Parmenides, the most important pre-Socratic Greek philosopher, to Neoplatonic and medieval use of Aristotle, forwhich Aristotle himself set guidelines in his discussions of his predecessors. Traces of these guidelines can be seen in the work of Plotinus, and that of the later Greek commentators on Aristotle. The study of these (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38. Optimality Reasoning in Aristotle's Natural Teleology.Devin Henry - 2013 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 45:225-263.
  39. Putting Aristotle's Physics in its Place: A Discussion of Benjamin Morison, On Location.Henry Mendell - 2005 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 28:327-366.
  40.  31
    Commentary on Aristotle's On Interpretation.Henry Babcock Veatch - 1965 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 3 (1):121-125.
  41.  22
    Copernicus and Aristotle's Cosmos.Henry Guerlac - 1968 - Journal of the History of Ideas 29 (1):109.
  42.  8
    What Aristotle Should Have Said in Metaphysics Z.Henry Teloh - 1982 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):241-255.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Aîtres de la Langue Et Demeures de la Pensée Henri Maldiney.Henri Maldiney - 1975 - Éditions L'âge D'Homme.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  25
    Practical Reasoning About Final Ends.Henry S. Richardson - 1994 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    Henry Richardson argues that we can determine our ends rationally. He constructs a rich and original theory of how we can reason about our final goals. Richardson defuses the counter-arguments for the limits of rational deliberation, and develops interesting ideas about how his model might be extended to interpersonal deliberation of ends, taking him to the borders of political theory. Along the way Richardson offers illuminating discussions of, inter alia, Aristotle, Aquinas, Sidgwick, and Dewey, as well as the work (...)
  45.  27
    A Modest Word in Defense of Aristotle’s Logic.Henry Veatch - 1968 - The Monist 52 (2):210-228.
    It is fashionable now-a-days to regard Aristotle’s logic as being the skeleton in the closet of Aristotelian philosophy. As Miss Anscombe has acidly remarked, “Aristotle himself … misconceived the importance of the categorical syllogism, supposing that the theory of it gave him the key to the nature of scientific knowledge. He expresses this view in what I find his worst book: Book I of the Posterior Analytics.”.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  75
    The Birds and the Bees: Aristotle on the Biological Concept of Analogy.Devin Henry - 2014 - In Gary M. Gurtler S. J. & William Wians (eds.), Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy. Brill. pp. 145-169.
  47.  10
    Degrees of Finality and the Highest Good in Aristotle.Henry R. Richardson - 1992 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (3):327.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  48. Texts to illustrate a course of elementary lectures on the history of Greek philosophy from Thales to Aristotle..Henry Jackson - 1930 - London,: Macmillan & Co..
  49.  4
    Two Traces of Two-Step Eudoxan Proportion Theory in Aristotle: a Tale of Definitions in Aristotle, with a Moral.Henry Mendell - 2007 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 61 (1):3-37.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  24
    The Universal in Aristotle.Henry Teloh - 1979 - Apeiron 13 (2):70 - 78.
1 — 50 / 1000