Results for 'John L. Tienson'

(not author) ( search as author name )
1000+ found
Order:
  1.  20
    About competence.John L. Tienson - 1990 - Philosophical Papers 19 (1):19-36.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  45
    An introduction to connectionism.John L. Tienson - 1988 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (S1):1-16.
  3. Introduction to connectionism.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy (Suppl.) 1:1-16.
  4.  22
    A Conception of Metaphysics.John L. Tienson - 1989 - American Philosophical Quarterly 26 (1):63 - 71.
  5.  24
    An argument concerning quantification and propositional attitudes.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 51 (2):145 - 168.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  81
    Brains are not conscious.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Philosophical Papers 16 (November):187-93.
  7.  33
    Entia successiva and ordinary things.John L. Tienson - 1985 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (4):475-479.
  8.  8
    Entia Successiva and Ordinary Things.John L. Tienson - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (4):475-479.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  19
    Is this any way to be a realist?John L. Tienson - 1990 - Philosophical Psychology 3 (1):155-164.
    Andy Clark argues that the reality and causal efficacy of the folk psychological attitudes do not require in‐the‐head correlates of the that‐clauses by which they are attributed. The facts for which Fodor invokes a language of thought as empirical explanation—systemati‐city, for example—are, Clark argues, an a priori conceptual demand upon propositional attitude ascription, and hence not in need of empirical explanation. However, no such strategy can work. A priori demands imposed by our practices do not eliminate the need for empirical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  84
    Resemblance and general terms.John L. Tienson - 1988 - Philosophical Studies 54 (1):87 - 108.
    Any successful account of general terms must explain our ability to apply terms correctly to new instances. Many philosophers have thought resemblance offers an ontologically sparse basis for such an account. However, Any natural and plausible account of general terms on the basis of resemblance requires quite a rich ontology, Including at least second order properties and relations. Given a sufficiently rich structure of resemblances, We can surely account for the application of many general terms. I argue, However, That our (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  60
    Synonyms and the objects of belief.John L. Tienson - 1982 - Philosophical Studies 42 (3):297 - 313.
  12. Phenomenal intentionality and the brain in a vat.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2004 - In Richard Schantz (ed.), The Externalist Challenge. De Gruyter.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  13.  52
    Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.) - 1991 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    "A third of the papers in this volume originated at the 1987 Spindel Conference ... at Memphis State University"--Pref.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  14. The phenomenology of first-person agency.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2003 - In Sven Walter & Heinz-Dieter Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and Mental Causation. Imprint Academic. pp. 323.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  15. Deconstructing new wave materialism.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2001 - In Carl Gillett & Barry M. Loewer (eds.), Physicalism and its Discontents. Cambridge University Press. pp. 307--318.
    In the first post World War II identity theories (e.g., Place 1956, Smart 1962), mind brain identities were held to be contingent. However, in work beginning in the late 1960's, Saul Kripke (1971, 1980) convinced the philosophical community that true identity statements involving names and natural kind terms are necessarily true and furthermore, that many such necessary identities can only be known a posteriori. Kripke also offered an explanation of the a posteriori nature of ordinary theoretical identities such as that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  16. A nonclassical framework for cognitive science.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1994 - Synthese 101 (3):305-45.
    David Marr provided a useful framework for theorizing about cognition within classical, AI-style cognitive science, in terms of three levels of description: the levels of (i) cognitive function, (ii) algorithm and (iii) physical implementation. We generalize this framework: (i) cognitive state transitions, (ii) mathematical/functional design and (iii) physical implementation or realization. Specifying the middle, design level to be the theory of dynamical systems yields a nonclassical, alternative framework that suits (but is not committed to) connectionism. We consider how a brain's (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  17. Structured representations in connectionist systems?Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1991 - In S. Davis (ed.), Connectionism: Theorye and Practice. Oxford University Press.
  18. Internal-world skepticism and mental self-presentation.Terence E. Horgan, John L. Tienson & George Graham - 2006 - In Uriah Kriegel & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. MIT Press. pp. 41-61.
  19. Authors' replies.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1999 - Acta Analytica 144:275-287.
  20. Cognition needs syntax but not rules.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2006 - In Robert J. Stainton (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Cognitive Science. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 147--158.
    Human cognition is rich, varied, and complex. In this Chapter we argue that because of the richness of human cognition (and human mental life generally), there must be a syntax of cognitive states, but because of this very richness, cognitive processes cannot be describable by exceptionless rules. The argument for syntax, in Section 1, has to do with being able to get around in any number of possible environments in a complex world. Since nature did not know where in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Consciousness and intentionality.George Graham, Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 2007 - In Max Velmans & Susan Schneider (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness. Blackwell. pp. 468--484.
  22. Aristotle on action.John L. Ackrill - 1976 - Mind 87 (348):595-601.
  23.  22
    Set Theory: Boolean-Valued Models and Independence Proofs.John L. Bell - 2011 - Oxford University Press.
    This third edition, now available in paperback, is a follow up to the author's classic Boolean-Valued Models and Independence Proofs in Set Theory. It provides an exposition of some of the most important results in set theory obtained in the 20th century: the independence of the continuum hypothesis and the axiom of choice.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  24. Contemporary theories of knowledge.John L. Pollock - 1986 - London: Hutchinson.
    This new edition of the classic Contemporary Theories of Knowledge has been significantly updated to include analyses of the recent literature in epistemology.
  25.  37
    The Continuous, the Discrete and the Infinitesimal in Philosophy and Mathematics.John L. Bell - 2019 - Springer Verlag.
    This book explores and articulates the concepts of the continuous and the infinitesimal from two points of view: the philosophical and the mathematical. The first section covers the history of these ideas in philosophy. Chapter one, entitled ‘The continuous and the discrete in Ancient Greece, the Orient and the European Middle Ages,’ reviews the work of Plato, Aristotle, Epicurus, and other Ancient Greeks; the elements of early Chinese, Indian and Islamic thought; and early Europeans including Henry of Harclay, Nicholas of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  88
    Continuity and Infinitesimals.John L. Bell - unknown
    The usual meaning of the word continuous is “unbroken” or “uninterrupted”: thus a continuous entity —a continuum—has no “gaps.” We commonly suppose that space and time are continuous, and certain philosophers have maintained that all natural processes occur continuously: witness, for example, Leibniz's famous apothegm natura non facit saltus—“nature makes no jump.” In mathematics the word is used in the same general sense, but has had to be furnished with increasingly precise definitions. So, for instance, in the later 18th century (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  27. The Continuous and the Infinitesimal in Mathematics and Philosophy.John L. Bell - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 13 (3):361-363.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  28.  52
    Philosophical foundations of adult education.John L. Elias - 1995 - Malabar, Fla.: Krieger. Edited by Sharan B. Merriam.
    "The Third Edition of Philosophical Foundations of Adult Education presents seven theoretical approaches to adult education: liberal, progressive, behaviorist, humanist, radical/critical, analytic, and postmodem. The book gives the historical grounding as well as the basic principles for each approach. In this edition each chapter has been revised and brought up to date. The chapter on radical adult education incorporates recent developments in radical education, phenomenology, feminist educational theory, and critical social theory. The book contains an entirely new chapter on postmodem (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  64
    Cognitive Carpentry: A Blueprint for how to Build a Person.John L. Pollock - 1995 - MIT Press.
    "A sequel to Pollock's How to Build a Person, this volume builds upon that theoretical groundwork for the implementation of rationality through artificial ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   209 citations  
  30.  15
    Peripherally presented and unreported words may bias the perceived meaning of a centrally fixated homograph.John L. Bradshaw - 1974 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 103 (6):1200.
  31. Higher-Order Logic and Type Theory.John L. Bell - 2022 - Cambridge University Press.
    This Element is an exposition of second- and higher-order logic and type theory. It begins with a presentation of the syntax and semantics of classical second-order logic, pointing up the contrasts with first-order logic. This leads to a discussion of higher-order logic based on the concept of a type. The second Section contains an account of the origins and nature of type theory, and its relationship to set theory. Section 3 introduces Local Set Theory, an important form of type theory (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  27
    Meaning and the Moral Sciences.John L. Koethe - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (3):460.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  33.  39
    Hermann Weyl.John L. Bell - 2010 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger.
  34.  33
    Ear asymmetry and delayed auditory feedback: Effects of task requirements and competitive stimulation.John L. Bradshaw, Norman C. Nettleton & Gina Geffen - 1972 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 94 (3):269.
  35. The axiom of choice.John L. Bell - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    The principle of set theory known as the Axiom of Choice has been hailed as “probably the most interesting and, in spite of its late appearance, the most discussed axiom of mathematics, second only to Euclid's axiom of parallels which was introduced more than two thousand years ago” (Fraenkel, Bar-Hillel & Levy 1973, §II.4). The fulsomeness of this description might lead those unfamiliar with the axiom to expect it to be as startling as, say, the Principle of the Constancy of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  36. Hermann Weyl on intuition and the continuum.John L. Bell - 2000 - Philosophia Mathematica 8 (3):259-273.
    Hermann Weyl, one of the twentieth century's greatest mathematicians, was unusual in possessing acute literary and philosophical sensibilities—sensibilities to which he gave full expression in his writings. In this paper I use quotations from these writings to provide a sketch of Weyl's philosophical orientation, following which I attempt to elucidate his views on the mathematical continuum, bringing out the central role he assigned to intuition.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  37. Knowledge and Justification.John L. Pollock - 1974 - Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Edited by John Pollock.
    Princeton University Press, 1974. This book is out of print, but can be downloaded as a pdf file (5 MB).
  38. The meaning of a word.John L. Austin - 1961 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (4):23--43.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  39. The Development of Categorical Logic.John L. Bell - unknown
    5.5. Every topos is linguistic: the equivalence theorem.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  40.  35
    Frustration effect with a long delay.John L. Allen - 1976 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 7 (2):185-186.
  41.  63
    Logical Options: An Introduction to Classical and Alternative Logics.John L. Bell, David DeVidi & Graham Solomon - 2001 - Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press.
    Logical Options introduces the extensions and alternatives to classical logic which are most discussed in the philosophical literature: many-sorted logic, second-order logic, modal logics, intuitionistic logic, three-valued logic, fuzzy logic, and free logic. Each logic is introduced with a brief description of some aspect of its philosophical significance, and wherever possible semantic and proof methods are employed to facilitate comparison of the various systems. The book is designed to be useful for philosophy students and professional philosophers who have learned some (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42.  18
    Weather foreasting and the development of meteorological theory at the Paris Observatory, 1853–1878.John L. Davis - 1984 - Annals of Science 41 (4):359-382.
    (1984). Weather foreasting and the development of meteorological theory at the Paris Observatory, 1853–1878. Annals of Science: Vol. 41, No. 4, pp. 359-382.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43. Logical Reflections On the Kochen-Specker Theorem.John L. Bell - unknown
    IN THEIR WELL-KNOWN PAPER, Kochen and Specker (1967) introduce the concept of partial Boolean algebra (pBa) and show that certain (finitely generated) partial Boolean algebras arising in quantum theory fail to possess morphisms to any Boolean algebra (we call such pBa's intractable in the sequel). In this note we begin by discussing partial..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44. Infinitary logic.John L. Bell - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Traditionally, expressions in formal systems have been regarded as signifying finite inscriptions which are—at least in principle—capable of actually being written out in primitive notation. However, the fact that (first-order) formulas may be identified with natural numbers (via "Gödel numbering") and hence with finite sets makes it no longer necessary to regard formulas as inscriptions, and suggests the possibility of fashioning "languages" some of whose formulas would be naturally identified as infinite sets . A "language" of this kind is called (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45. Defeasible Reasoning.John L. Pollock - 1987 - Cognitive Science 11 (4):481-518.
    There was a long tradition in philosophy according to which good reasoning had to be deductively valid. However, that tradition began to be questioned in the 1960’s, and is now thoroughly discredited. What caused its downfall was the recognition that many familiar kinds of reasoning are not deductively valid, but clearly confer justification on their conclusions. Here are some simple examples.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   336 citations  
  46. Types, Sets and Categories.John L. Bell - unknown
    This essay is an attempt to sketch the evolution of type theory from its beginnings early in the last century to the present day. Central to the development of the type concept has been its close relationship with set theory to begin with and later its even more intimate relationship with category theory. Since it is effectively impossible to describe these relationships (especially in regard to the latter) with any pretensions to completeness within the space of a comparatively short article, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47. Ethnography And The Historical Imagination.John L. Comaroff & John & Jean Comaroff - 1992 - Westview Press.
    In their writings on Africa and colonialism, John and Jean Comaroff have explored some of the fundamental questions of social science, delving into the nature of history and human agency, culture and consciousness, ritual and representation. How are human differences constructed and institutionalized, transformed and (sometimes) resisted? How do local cultures articulate with global forms? How is the power of some people over others built, sustained, eroded, and negated?These essays work toward an "imaginative sociology," demonstrating the techniques by which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  48.  12
    Trust and Exchange: Expressive and Instrumental Dimensions of Reciprocity in a Peasant Community.John L. Aguilar - 1984 - Ethos: Journal of the Society for Psychological Anthropology 12 (1):3-29.
  49.  33
    ‘Women’s will to fail’ in a disjunctive reaction time competitive task.John L. Allen & Michael R. Boivin - 1976 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 8 (5):401-402.
  50.  45
    Hilbert’s varepsilon -operator in intuitionistic type theories.John L. Bell - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):323--337.
    We investigate Hilbert’s varepsilon -calculus in the context of intuitionistic type theories, that is, within certain systems of intuitionistic higher-order logic. We determine the additional deductive strength conferred on an intuitionistic type theory by the adjunction of closed varepsilon -terms. We extend the usual topos semantics for type theories to the varepsilon -operator and prove a completeness theorem. The paper also contains a discussion of the concept of “partially defined‘ varepsilon -term. MSC: 03B15, 03B20, 03G30.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000