Results for ' pain‐behaviour'

991 found
Order:
  1.  38
    Signs of Anger: Representation of Agonistic Behaviour in Invertebrate Cognition.Stephen Philip Pain - 2009 - Biosemiotics 2 (2):181-191.
    In this essay I shall examine the representation of aggression and its issues in the model animal, the Fruit Fly, Drosophila melanogaster. The Fruit Fly is the model animal for genetics and more recently neuroscience. On the basis of its behaviour conclusions are being drawn that will help in the development of new treatments for clinical entities like aggression and anxiety disorders—the author questions those findings and asks whether more should be done to focus on the actual biology and behaviour—the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. How WEIRD is Cognitive Archaeology? Engaging with the Challenge of Cultural Variation and Sample Diversity.Anton Killin & Ross Pain - 2023 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 14 (2):539-563.
    In their landmark 2010 paper, “The weirdest people in the world?”, Henrich, Heine, and Norenzayan outlined a serious methodological problem for the psychological and behavioural sciences. Most of the studies produced in the field use people from Western, Educated, Industrialised, Rich and Democratic (WEIRD) societies, yet inferences are often drawn to the species as a whole. In drawing such inferences, researchers implicitly assume that either there is little variation across human populations, or that WEIRD populations are generally representative of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  21
    Pain behavior and the pretence of knowledge.Kenneth M. Prkachin - 2002 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (4):470-470.
    A monolithic model that ignores functional and topographic distinctions among its components has dominated clinical accounts of pain behavior. This model contributes to a pretence of knowledge that affects the treatment of sufferers. This commentary addresses the role of the target article in correcting knowledge-pretence and introduces a complementary caveat about evolutionary psychology concepts.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  18
    Pain behavior: How to define the operant.Hugh Lacey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):64-65.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  21
    Pain behaviour is not unitary.Kenneth M. Prkachin - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):754-755.
  6.  27
    Pain and Pain Behaviour.Colin Radford - 1972 - Philosophy 47 (181):189 - 205.
    What is the connection between pain and pain behaviour? Is it logically necessary, or is it contingent? Or is it too complex to be classified in terms of this Humean dichotomy? Surely it is too complex, for if we say the relationship is a necessary one, we should, apparently, have to deny that there could be pain without pain behaviour, or pain behaviour without pain; yet stoicism and shamming pain occur. If we say that the relationship is not necessary and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  54
    Is it Intelligible that an Organism with no Pain-Behaviour should be in Pain?Natalie Waights Hickman - 2011 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 18 (9-10):9-10.
  8. Pain and behavior.Howard Rachlin - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):43-83.
    There seem to be two kinds of pain: fundamental pain, the intensity of which is a direct function of the intensity of various pain stimuli, and pain, the intensity of which is highly modifiable by such factors as hypnotism, placebos, and the sociocultural setting in which the stimulus occurs.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   209 citations  
  9. Reconceptualizing Pain-related Behavior: Introducing the Concept of Bodily Doubt.Anthony Vincent Fernandez, Jan Hartvigsen, Susanne Ravn, Peter Stilwell & Alice Kongsted - 2023 - European Journal of Pain 1.
    The aim of the article is to introduce a new concept of “pain-related bodily doubt,” which complements current concepts currently in use, such as pain-related fear, pain catastrophizing, and pain self-efficacy. This new concept, adapted from recent philosophical work on illness experience, has the potential to positively contribute to pain research and clinical practice by providing a vocabulary for clinicians and patients to discuss implicit or tacit dimensions of pain-related experiences.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  30
    Not “pain and behavior” but pain in behavior.Patrick D. Wall - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):73-73.
  11.  26
    Do pains make a difference to our behavior?William S. Robinson - 1979 - American Philosophical Quarterly 16 (4):327-34.
  12.  31
    Pain without behavior: Inhibition of reactions to sensation.Kelly G. Shaver & Jana J. Herrman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):71-71.
  13.  11
    Chronic Pain and Aberrant Drug-Related Behavior in the Emergency Department.Knox H. Todd - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (4):761-769.
    Pain is the single most common reason patients seek care in the emergency department. Given the prevalence of pain as a presenting complaint, one might expect emergency physicians to assign its treatment a high priority; however, pain is often seemingly invisible to the emergency physician. Multiple research studies have documented that the undertreatment of pain, or oligoanalgesia, is a frequent occurrence. Pain that is not acknowledged and managed appropriately causes dissatisfaction with medical care, hostility toward the physician, unscheduled returns to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  5
    Chronic Pain and Aberrant Drug-Related Behavior in the Emergency Department.Knox H. Todd - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (4):761-769.
    Pain is the single most common reason patients seek care in the emergency department. Given the prevalence of pain as a presenting complaint, one might expect emergency physicians to assign its treatment a high priority; however, pain is often seemingly invisible to the emergency physician. Multiple research studies have documented that the undertreatment of pain, or oligoanalgesia, is a frequent occurrence. Pain that is not acknowledged and managed appropriately causes dissatisfaction with medical care, hostility toward the physician, unscheduled returns to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  32
    Is pain overt behavior?Gilbert Harman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):61-61.
  16.  44
    Semicovert behavior and the concept of pain.Ullin T. Place - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):70-71.
  17.  19
    When Pain Brings Gain: Soccer Players Behavior and Admissions Suggest Feigning Injury to Maintain a Favorable Scoreline.Stuart W. G. Derbyshire, Ilana Angel & Richard Bushell - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  8
    Physical Activity, Sedentary Behavior, Anxiety, and Pain Among Musicians in the United Kingdom.Raluca Matei & Jane Ginsborg - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Context and AimsAlthough some exercise-based interventions have been associated with lower levels of pain and performance-related musculoskeletal disorders among musicians, the evidence is still mixed. Furthermore, little is known about musicians’ general engagement in physical activity, their knowledge of PA guidelines, or the relevant training they receive on pain prevention and the sources of such training. Similarly, little is known about the relationship between PA and PRMDs and other risk factors for PRMDs.MethodsFollowing a cross-sectional correlational study design, both standardized andad (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. The Problem of Fetal Pain and Abortion: Toward an Ethical Consensus for Appropriate Behavior.E. Christian Brugger - 2012 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 22 (3):263-287.
    This essay concerns what people should do in conflict situations when a doubt of fact bears on settling whether an alternative under consideration is legitimate or not. Its principal audience are those who believe that abortion can be legitimate when not having an abortion gives rise to serious harms that can be avoided by having one, but who are concerned that fetuses might feel pain when being aborted, and who believe that causing unnecessary pain should be avoided when doing so (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  20
    A mentalistic view of “Pain and behavior”.H. Merskey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):68-68.
  21.  16
    Response-specific effects of pain observation on motor behavior.India Morrison, Ellen Poliakoff, Lucy Gordon & Paul Downing - 2007 - Cognition 104 (2):407-416.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  22.  26
    On Rachlin's “Pain and behavior”: A lightening of the burden.Wilbert E. Fordyce - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):58-59.
  23.  6
    Does item overlap render measured relationships between pain and challenging behaviour trivial? Results from a multicentre cross‐sectional study in 13 German nursing homes.Patrick Kutschar, Zsuzsa Bauer, Irmela Gnass & Jürgen Osterbrink - 2017 - Nursing Inquiry 24 (3):e12182.
    Several studies suggest that pain is a trigger for challenging behaviour in older adults with cognitive impairment. However, such measured relationships might be confounded due to item overlap as instruments share similar or identical items. The purpose of this study was to examine whether the frequently observed association between pain and challenging behaviour might be traced back to item overlap. This multicentre cross‐sectional study was conducted in 13 nursing homes and examined pain (measure: Pain Assessment in Advanced Dementia Scale) and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  76
    Pain and Action.David Bain - manuscript
    While many agree that unpleasant pains motivate, little attention has been paid to this idea’s action-theoretic significance, to what kind of motivation pains are, or to the status of the behaviour they motivate. I claim that some pain behaviour belongs to a neglected category. For it is not brute behaviour, but action; yet it is not motivated by desires or intentions, nor like other behaviour that philosophers construe as neither brute nor desire-motivated, such as habitual action. Rather it is what (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Robot Pain.Simon van Rysewyk - 2014 - International Journal of Synthetic Emotions 4 (2):22-33.
    Functionalism of robot pain claims that what is definitive of robot pain is functional role, defined as the causal relations pain has to noxious stimuli, behavior and other subjective states. Here, I propose that the only way to theorize role-functionalism of robot pain is in terms of type-identity theory. I argue that what makes a state pain for a neuro-robot at a time is the functional role it has in the robot at the time, and this state is type identical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26. Pains and reasons: Why it is rational to kill the Messenger.Brian Cutter & Michael Tye - 2014 - Philosophical Quarterly 64 (256):423-433.
    In this paper, we defend the representationalist theory of phenomenal consciousness against a recent objection due to Hilla Jacobson, who charges representationalism with a failure to explain the role of pain in rationalizing certain forms of behavior. In rough outline, her objection is that the representationalist is unable to account for the rationality of certain acts, such as the act of taking pain killers, which are aimed at getting rid of the experience of pain rather than its intentional object. If (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  27.  90
    Pain Perception in Disorders of Consciousness: Neuroscience, Clinical Care, and Ethics in Dialogue.Athina Demertzi, Eric Racine, Marie-Aurélie Bruno, Didier Ledoux, Olivia Gosseries, Audrey Vanhaudenhuyse, Marie Thonnard, Andrea Soddu, Gustave Moonen & Steven Laureys - 2013 - Neuroethics 6 (1):37-50.
    Pain, suffering and positive emotions in patients in vegetative state/unresponsive wakefulness syndrome (VS/uws) and minimally conscious states (MCS) pose clinical and ethical challenges. Clinically, we evaluate behavioural responses after painful stimulation and also emotionally-contingent behaviours (e.g., smiling). Using stimuli with emotional valence, neuroimaging and electrophysiology technologies can detect subclinical remnants of preserved capacities for pain which might influence decisions about treatment limitation. To date, no data exist as to how healthcare providers think about end-of-life options (e.g., withdrawal of artificial nutrition (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28. Painful Reasons: Representationalism as a Theory of Pain.Brendan O'Sullivan & Robert Schroer - 2012 - Philosophical Quarterly 62 (249):737-758.
    It is widely thought that functionalism and the qualia theory are better positioned to accommodate the ‘affective’ aspect of pain phenomenology than representationalism. In this paper, we attempt to overturn this opinion by raising problems for both functionalism and the qualia theory on this score. With regard to functionalism, we argue that it gets the order of explanation wrong: pain experience gives rise to the effects it does because it hurts, and not the other way around. With regard to the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  29.  78
    Reconsidering pain.Norton Nelkin - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (3):325-43.
    In 1986, I argued that pains are essentially not phenomenal states. Using a Wittgen-steinian son of argument, I showed that the same sort of phenomena can be had on different occasions, and on one occasion persons be in pain, while on another occasion persons not be in pain. I also showed that very different phenomena could be experienced and, yet, organisms have the same sort of pain. I supported my arguments with empirical data from both laboratory and clinical studies. There (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  30. Pain Perception in Disorders of Consciousness: Neuroscience, Clinical Care, and Ethics in Dialogue. [REVIEW]A. Demertzi, E. Racine, M.-A. Bruno, D. Ledoux, O. Gosseries, A. Vanhaudenhuyse, M. Thonnard, A. Soddu, G. Moonen & S. Laureys - 2012 - Neuroethics 6 (1):37-50.
    Pain, suffering and positive emotions in patients in vegetative state/unresponsive wakefulness syndrome (VS/UWS) and minimally conscious states (MCS) pose clinical and ethical challenges. Clinically, we evaluate behavioural responses after painful stimulation and also emotionally-contingent behaviours (e.g., smiling). Using stimuli with emotional valence, neuroimaging and electrophysiology technologies can detect subclinical remnants of preserved capacities for pain which might influence decisions about treatment limitation. To date, no data exist as to how healthcare providers think about end-of-life options (e.g., withdrawal of artificial nutrition (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  31.  37
    Exercising for the Pleasure and for the Pain of It: The Implications of Different Forms of Hedonistic Thinking in Theories of Physical Activity Behavior.Stephen L. Murphy & Daniel L. Eaves - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Pain, suffering, and anxiety in animals and humans.David DeGrazia & Andrew Rowan - 1991 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 12 (3).
    We attempt to bring the concepts of pain, suffering, and anxiety into sufficient focus to make them serviceable for empirical investigation. The common-sense view that many animals experience these phenomena is supported by empirical and philosophical arguments. We conclude, first, that pain, suffering, and anxiety are different conceptually and as phenomena, and should not be conflated. Second, suffering can be the result — or perhaps take the form — of a variety of states including pain, anxiety, fear, and boredom. Third, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  33.  37
    Pain And Emotion.R. TRIGG - 1970 - Clarendon Press.
  34.  56
    Facial expression of pain: An evolutionary account.Amanda C. De C. Williams - 2002 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (4):439-455.
    This paper proposes that human expression of pain in the presence or absence of caregivers, and the detection of pain by observers, arises from evolved propensities. The function of pain is to demand attention and prioritise escape, recovery, and healing; where others can help achieve these goals, effective communication of pain is required. Evidence is reviewed of a distinct and specific facial expression of pain from infancy to old age, consistent across stimuli, and recognizable as pain by observers. Voluntary control (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  35.  8
    Pain and the collision of expertise in primary care physical exams.Amanda McArthur - 2019 - Discourse Studies 21 (5):522-539.
    Using conversation analysis and a collection of naturally occurring US primary care consultations, this article explores the search for pain during primary care physical exams. Inhabiting this activity is a ‘collision’ of expertise between physicians’ clinical knowledge about bodies and patients’ knowledge about their bodies. I show how patients responding to questions like does that hurt? tacitly guide physicians to their pain using pain displays, glottal cutoffs and response delays to observably react to the physician’s touch, delineating painful from non- (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  99
    Hypnotic behavior: A social-psychological interpretation of amnesia, analgesia, and “trance logic”.Nicholas P. Spanos - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):449-467.
    This paper examines research on three hypnotic phenomena: suggested amnesia, suggested analgesia, and “trance logic.” For each case a social-psychological interpretation of hypnotic behavior as a voluntary response strategy is compared with the traditional special-process view that “good” hypnotic subjects have lost conscious control over suggestion-induced behavior. I conclude that it is inaccurate to describe hypnotically amnesic subjects as unable to recall the material they have been instructed to forget. Although amnesics present themselves as unable to remember, they in fact (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  37.  99
    Animals, pain and morality.Alan Carter - 2005 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 (1):17–22.
    While it is widely agreed that the infliction upon innocents of needless pain is immoral, many have argued that, even though nonhuman animals act as if they feel pain, there is no reason to think that they actually suffer painful experiences. And if our actions only appear to cause nonhuman animals pain, then such actions are not immoral. On the basis of the claim that certain behavioural responses to organismic harm are maladaptive, whereas the ability to feel pain is itself (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  85
    Pains.Kurt Baier - 1962 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 40 (1):1-23.
  39.  46
    Pain and Consciousness in Humans. Or Why Pain Subserves the Identity and Self-representation.Irene Venturella & Michela Balconi - 2016 - Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 7 (2):166-179.
    : Traditional definitions of pain assume that an individual learns about pain through verbal usages related to the experience of injury in early life. This emphasis on the verbal correlates of pain restricts our understanding of pain to the context of adult human consciousness. In this paper we instead support the idea that our understanding of pain originates in neonatal experience and is not merely a verbally determined phenomenon. We also challenge the definition of pain as a merely sensory message (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  27
    The Complex Reality of Pain.Jennifer Corns - 2020 - New York, NY: Routledge.
    This book employs contemporary philosophy, scientific research, and clinical reports to argue that pain, though real, is not an appropriate object of scientific generalisations or an appropriate target for medical intervention. Each pain experience is instead complex and idiosyncratic in a way which undermines scientific utility. In addition to contributing novel arguments and developing a novel position on the nature of pain, the book provides an interdisciplinary overview of dominant models of pain. The author lays the needed groundwork for improved (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  41.  15
    Investigating How Parental Instructions and Protective Responses Mediate the Relationship Between Parental Psychological Flexibility and Pain-Related Behavior in Adolescents With Chronic Pain: A Daily Diary Study.Melanie Beeckman, Laura E. Simons, Sean Hughes, Tom Loeys & Liesbet Goubert - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
  42.  6
    Pain and temporality: a merleau-pontyian approach.Judith N. Wagner - forthcoming - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy:1-11.
    Chronic pain is a common disorder with enormous sociomedical importance. A major part of primary and secondary costs of illness is caused by the various pain syndromes. Nociception – the sensory perception of a painful stimulus – is a complex process relying on an intricate system of anatomical, neurophysiological and biochemical networks. This applies even more so to pain – the state of experiencing a nociceptive event, of interpreting it in terms of meaning for the affected individual and of suffering (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  25
    Is there always a neurochemical link between pain and behavior?G. Pepeu - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):69-70.
  44. Fish do not feel pain and its implications for understanding phenomenal consciousness.Brian Key - 2015 - Biology and Philosophy 30 (2):149-165.
    Phenomenal consciousness or the subjective experience of feeling sensory stimuli is fundamental to human existence. Because of the ubiquity of their subjective experiences, humans seem to readily accept the anthropomorphic extension of these mental states to other animals. Humans will typically extrapolate feelings of pain to animals if they respond physiologically and behaviourally to noxious stimuli. The alternative view that fish instead respond to noxious stimuli reflexly and with a limited behavioural repertoire is defended within the context of our current (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  45.  12
    Seeing pains.B. H. Slater - 2001 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 62 (1):65-81.
    P.M.S. Hacker, recounting some of Wittgenstein's views, says : [T]he pervasive conception of behaviour that has informed philosophical psychology for the last three centuries has misrepresented human behaviour as 'bare bodily movement', from which it is supposed we infer, by analogy or inference to best explanation, the inner state and so on from which the behaviour might be thought to arise … But we see the pain in a person's face hear the glee in his chortles, perceive the affection in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  48
    Neonatal Pain Relief and the Helsinki Declaration.Robert S. Van Howe & J. Steven Svoboda - 2008 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 36 (4):803-823.
    The Helsinki Declaration is the universally accepted standard for ethical behavior in research involving human subjects. The Declaration calls for research studies to compare new therapies to the best current therapies. Despite this standard, multiple studies of pain relief interventions in newborns have recruited placebo controls instead of active controls using the best current therapy. These studies are evaluated using the standards required by the Helsinki Declaration, and the reasons for the ethical shortcomings of these studies are explored.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  17
    Associative learning and pain? Why stop there?Marcus Munafo' - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (3):459-460.
    It is argued by berkley that there are theoretical reasons why sex differences in pain may result from specific learning processes. I argue that Berkley has not gone far enough in pursuing this suggestion, and that the evidence that learning is a major determinant of pain behaviour is substantial. Moreover, sex differences in pain may represent only a special case of individual differences in pain resulting from learning processes.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  81
    The Social Pain Posit.Jennifer Corns - 2015 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (3):561-582.
    Although discussion of social pain has become popular among researchers in psychology and behavioural neuroscience, the philosophical community has yet to pay it any direct attention. Social pain is characterized as the emotional reaction to the perception of the loss or devaluation of desired relationships. These are argued to comprise a pain type and are explicitly intended to include the everyday sub-types grief, jealousy, heartbreak, rejection, and hurt feelings. Social pain is accordingly posited as a nested type of pain encompassing (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  49. Do Plants Feel Pain?Adam Hamilton & Justin McBrayer - 2020 - Disputatio 12 (56):71-98.
    Many people are attracted to the idea that plants experience phenomenal conscious states like pain, sensory awareness, or emotions like fear. If true, this would have wide-ranging moral implications for human behavior, including land development, farming, vegetarianism, and more. Determining whether plants have minds relies on the work of both empirical disciplines and philosophy. Epistemology should settle the standards for evidence of other minds, and science should inform our judgment about whether any plants meet those standards. We argue that evidence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  31
    Pains are in the head, not the spine.Valerie Gray Hardcastle - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (3):451-452.
    The authors presume that activity in the dorsal horn or nociceptors is well correlated with pain sensations and behavior. This overlooks the myriad of interactions between cortex and our spinothalamic tract. It is better to think of our nociceptors, the dorsal horn, and the pain centers in our brain as all components in one larger and complex pain sensory system. [berkley; blumberg et al.; coderre & katz; dickenson; mcmahon; wiesenfeld-hallin et al.].
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 991