Results for 'Nicholas Gooding'

995 found
Order:
  1.  18
    Grammar" from Diderot's "Encyclopedie.Nicholas Rand & Kathleen F. Good - 1984 - Substance 13 (2):66.
  2.  25
    Images of Anarchy: The Rhetoric and Science in Hobbes’s State of Nature, written by Evrigenis, Ioannis.Nicholas Gooding - 2015 - Hobbes Studies 28 (2):175-183.
  3.  2
    2 Identifying Good and Evil.Nicholas Wolterstorff - 2005 - In Predrag Cicovacki (ed.), Destined for evil?: the twentieth-century responses. Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Press. pp. 45-58.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Faith and Reason From Plato to Plantinga: An Introduction to Reformed Epistemology by Dewey J. Hoitenga, Jr.Nicholas P. Wolterstorff - 1993 - The Thomist 57 (3):542-546.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:542 BOOK REVIEWS sires. Rather, the Subjects need to want to do those things that bring about the Bosses' satisfaction. And this raises the question of the control of the imagination. explores the subtle power relations between controllers and the controlled, to the end of exploring ways that imagination offers control over power relationships. Yet Rorty ends with a bleak vision: we are a basically conservative species, whose capacities (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Evil and Explanation.Nicholas L. Sturgeon - 1995 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 21:155-185.
    In the first part of this paper I want to consider the relation between two familiar philosophical views that have not to my knowledge been considered in any depth together, even by philosophers who are well known for defending each separately. These views have a certain natural affinity, in that each has been attractive to philosophers of a generally naturalistic bent. Thus, since I intend to argue that there is a difficulty in reconciling them, I will be pointing out a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Imperatives in Greek Ethics.Nicholas White - 2002 - In Nicholas P. White (ed.), Individual and conflict in Greek ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    A common theme in the historiography of Greek ethics says that modern ethics is characterized by imperative notions such as ‘duty’—and with a Judeo‐Christian notion of imperatives or commands issued by god—whereas ancient ethics supposedly deals mainly with ‘attractive notions such as ‘good’ and ‘virtue’. This thought is often juxtaposed with the idea that imperative notions betoken a conflict between one's duty and one's good, because an imperative seems to be required only to command people to do what they do (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Brief Account of How Nicholas Maxwell Came to Argue for the Urgent Need for a Revolution in Universities.Nicholas Maxwell - manuscript
    We need urgently to bring about a revolution in universities around the world, wherever possible, so that they take their fundamental task to be, not to acquire and apply knowledge, but rather to help humanity learn how to resolve conflicts and problems of living in increasingly cooperatively rational ways, so that we may make progress towards a good, genuinely civilized, wise world. The pursuit of knowledge would be a vital but subsidiary task. I have argued for the urgent need for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  88
    Goodness And Beauty In Plato.Nicholas Riegel - 2014 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 12:143-154.
    In the first part of this paper I argue that beauty and goodness are at least coextensive for Plato. That means that at least with respect to concrete particulars, everything that is good is beautiful and everything that is beautiful is good. Though the good and the beautiful are coextensive, there is evidence that they are not identical. In the second part of the paper I show significance of this relation. In ethics it implies that the good is the right. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  28
    The Good Life and the Life That’s Good for You: A Response to the Experience Machine.Nicholas Kreuder - forthcoming - Journal of Value Inquiry:1-19.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. What Kind of Inquiry Can Best Help Us Create a Good World?Nicholas Maxwell - 1992 - Science, Technology and Human Values 17:205-227.
    In order to create a good world, we need to learn how to do it - how to resolve our appalling problems and conflicts in more cooperative ways than at present. And in order to do this, we need traditions and institutions of learning rationally devoted to this end. When viewed from this standpoint, what we have at present - academic inquiry devoted to the pursuit of knowledge and technological know-how - is an intellectual and human disaster. We urgently need (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  11.  51
    The classification of goods in Plato's.Nicholas P. White - 1984 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 22 (4):393-421.
  12.  18
    Rachana Kamtekar, Plato’s Moral Psychology: Intellectualism, the Divided Soul, and the Desire for the Good (review).Nicholas D. Smith - 2018 - Ethics 129 (2):404-408.
  13. Trash talking, respect for opponents and good competition.Nicholas Dixon - 2007 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 1 (1):96 – 106.
  14.  25
    Reason, Tradition, and the Good: Macintyre's Tradition-Constituted Reason and Frankfurt School Critical Theory.Jeffery Nicholas - 2012 - University of Notre Dame Press.
    Introduction: the question of reason -- The Frankfurt School critique of reason -- Habermas's communicative rationality -- Macintyre's tradition-constituted reason -- A substantive reason -- Beyond relativism: reasonable progress and learning from -- Conclusion: toward a Thomistic-Aristotelian critical theory of society.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15.  16
    Reason, Tradition, and the Good: Alasdair MacIntyre's Reason of Tradition and Frankfurt School Critical Theory.Jeffery L. Nicholas - unknown
    In Reason, Tradition, and the Good, Jeffery L. Nicholas addresses the failure of reason in modernity to bring about a just society, a society in which people can attain fulfillment. Developing the critical theory of the Frankfurt School, Nicholas argues that we rely too heavily on a conception of rationality that is divorced from tradition and, therefore, incapable of judging ends. Without the ability to judge ends, we cannot engage in debate about the good life or the proper (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  21
    The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy.Nicholas P. White - 1989 - Noûs 23 (2):254-256.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  17.  7
    Plato's Concept of Goodness.Nicholas White - 2006 - In Hugh H. Benson (ed.), A Companion to Plato. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 356–372.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Note.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Sun and line: The role of the good.Nicholas Denyer - 2007 - In G. R. F. Ferrari (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s R Epublic. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 284--309.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19.  57
    Do Christians Have Good Reason for Supporting Liberal Democracy?Nicholas Wolterstorff - 2001 - Modern Schoolman 78 (2-3):229-248.
  20.  51
    The Classification of Goods in Plato's Republic.Nicholas P. White - 1984 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 22 (4):393-421.
  21.  34
    Objective goodness and Aristotle's dilemma.Nicholas Sleigh - 1992 - Journal of Value Inquiry 26 (3):341-351.
  22. Individual Good and Deliberative Conflict through the Time of Plato.Nicholas White - 2002 - In Nicholas P. White (ed.), Individual and conflict in Greek ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Before Plato there are ample cases in which Greek poets, philosophers, and politicians recognize the possibility that individual and social good can conflict. Nor does Plato think that a full understanding of the notion of one's good must demonstrate that it cannot conflict with standards of justice. On the contrary, Plato holds that such conflicts can occur even in the case of the rulers of his ideal city‐state. This idea is not contradicted by evidence of other works, such as the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Miscarriage Is Not a Cause of Death: A Response to Berg’s “Abortion and Miscarriage”.Nicholas Colgrove - 2021 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 46 (4):394-413.
    Some opponents of abortion claim that fetuses are persons from the moment of conception. Following Berg (2017), let us call these individuals “Personhood-At-Conception” (or PAC), opponents of abortion. Berg argues that if fetuses are persons from the moment of conception, then miscarriage kills far more people than abortion. As such, PAC opponents of abortion face the following dilemma: They must “immediately” and “substantially” shift their attention, resources, etc., toward preventing miscarriage or they must admit that they do not actually believe (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  24. Naturalising Representational Content.Nicholas Shea - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (5):496-509.
    This paper sets out a view about the explanatory role of representational content and advocates one approach to naturalising content – to giving a naturalistic account of what makes an entity a representation and in virtue of what it has the content it does. It argues for pluralism about the metaphysics of content and suggests that a good strategy is to ask the content question with respect to a variety of predictively successful information processing models in experimental psychology and cognitive (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  25.  24
    ‘We good Europeans’: Nietzsche's new Europe in beyond good and evil.Nicholas Martin - 1995 - History of European Ideas 20 (1-3):141-144.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  32
    The Proper Place for External Motivations for Sport and Why They Need Not Subvert Its Internal Goods.Nicholas Dixon - 2018 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 12 (4):361-374.
  27. The Common Good, Rights, and Catholic Social Thought: Prolegomena to Any Future Account of Common Goods.Jeffery L. Nicholas - 2015 - Solidarity: The Journal for Catholic Social Thought and Secular Ethics 5 (1):Article 4.
    The argument between Jacques Maritain and Charles de Koninck over the primacy of the common good is well known. Yet, even though Mary Keys has carefully arbitrated this debate, it still remains problematic for Alasdair MacIntyre, particularly because of the role rights play in both Maritain and Catholic Social Thought. I examine Keys’ argument and, in addition, Deborah Wallace’s account of MacIntyre’s criticism of rights in Catholic social thought. I argue, in the end, that what Maritain, and in consequence Keys (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  23
    Pretending to be Good: Explaining Wei 偽 in the Xunzi.Nicholas Constantino - 2022 - Philosophy East and West 72 (3):671-692.
    Abstract:Throughout the Zhanguo period, wei 偽 referred to "inauthenticity" or "falseness." However, such interpretations are difficult to apply to Xunzi's use of the term, in which wei becomes a key component of ethical cultivation. Since the Tang, Xunzi's use of wei has served as a focal point of debates regarding how to evaluate his teachings. These debates largely concluded during the Qing, when exegetes argued that the graphs for wei 偽 (inauthenticity) and wei 為 (efforts) were interchangeable in pre-Han texts, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Nominalist Realism.Nicholas K. Jones - 2018 - Noûs 52 (4):808-835.
    This paper explores the impact of quantification into predicate position on the metaphysics of properties, arguing that two familiar debates about properties are fundamentally altered by recasting them in a second-order setting. Two theories of properties are outlined, differing over whether the existence of properties is expressed using first-order or second-order quantifiers. It is argued that the second-order theory: provides good reason to regard debate about the locations of properties as contentless; resolves debate about whether properties are particulars or universals (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  30. From the idea of the good to some ideas of Goodman.Nicholas White - 1997 - Philosophia Scientiae 2 (2):313-330.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Kant on Judgment and Feeling.Nicholas Dunn - 2024 - Kant Studien 115 (1):46-70.
    It is well known that Kant connects judgment and feeling in the third Critique. However, the precise relationship between these two faculties remains virtually unexplored, in large part due to the unpopularity of Kant’s faculty psychology. This paper considers why, for Kant, judgment and feeling go together, arguing that he had good philosophical reasons for forging this connection. The discussion begins by situating these faculties within Kant’s mature faculty psychology. While the ‘power of judgment’ [Urteilskraft] is fundamentally reflective, feeling [Gefühl] (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  4
    Good as Goal.Nicholas P. White - 1989 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 (S1):169-193.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Individual Good and Deliberative Conflict in Aristotle.Nicholas White - 2002 - In Nicholas P. White (ed.), Individual and conflict in Greek ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Although Aristotle's ethics is rightly characterized as eudaimonist, in making the happiness of an individual his preeminent aim, it does not adopt the harmonizing eudaimonist position that all constituents of human happiness are consistent with each other. For one thing, he holds that there can be conflicts between friends. In addition, he maintains that conflicts within happiness can break out, between the value of acting in a morally virtuous way and that of pursuing intellectual virtue or contemplation. Aristotle thus admits (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  31
    Good as goal.Nicholas P. White - 1989 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 (S1):169-193.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  13
    Reorienting Locus of Control in Individuals Who Have Offended Through Strengths-Based Interventions: Personal Agency and the Good Lives Model.Nichola Tyler, Roxanne Heffernan & Clare-Ann Fortune - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Conflict and Individual Good in Hellenistic Ethics.Nicholas White - 2002 - In Nicholas P. White (ed.), Individual and conflict in Greek ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Contrary to the hegelian thought that harmonizing eudaimonism was manifested most fully in the Classical period of Greek ethics, it is in fact the Hellenistic period after Aristotle that shows the most forthright attempts to produce ethical views that do not generate conflicts between rational aims. This is partly the result of the Hellenistic attempts to generate positions that, unlike the doctrines of Plato and Aristotle, possess a high degree of systematic coherence. Epicurean hedonism is a case in point, as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. In Praise of Natural Philosophy: A Revolution for Thought and Life.Nicholas Maxwell - 2017 - Montreal, Canada: McGill-Queen's University Press.
    The central thesis of this book is that we need to reform philosophy and join it to science to recreate a modern version of natural philosophy; we need to do this in the interests of rigour, intellectual honesty, and so that science may serve the best interests of humanity. Modern science began as natural philosophy. In the time of Newton, what we call science and philosophy today – the disparate endeavours – formed one mutually interacting, integrated endeavour of natural philosophy: (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  38.  56
    Partnership with God: a partial solution to the problem of petitionary prayer.Nicholas D. Smith & Andrew C. Yip - 2010 - Religious Studies 46 (3):395-410.
    Why would God make us ask for some good He might supply, and why would it be right for God to withhold that good unless and until we asked for it? We explain why present defences of petitionary prayer are insufficient, but argue that a world in which God makes us ask for some goods and then supplies them in response to our petitions adds value to the world that would not be available in worlds in which God simply supplied (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39. The Devil in the Details.Nicholas Colgrove - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (12):18-20.
    McCarthy et al.’s proposal gains much of its plausibility by relying on a superficial treatment of justice, human dignity, sin, and the common good within the Christian tradition. Upon closer inspection of what these terms mean within the context of Christianity, it becomes clear that despite using the same phrases (e.g., a commitment to “protecting vulnerable populations,” the goal of “promoting justice,” etc.) contemporary secular bioethical goals are often deeply at odds with goals of Christian bioethics. So, while the authors (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  57
    Why Only Perfection Is Good Enough.Nicholas Everitt - 2000 - Philosophical Papers 29 (3):155-158.
    Abstract I argue that the traditional problem of evil mislocates the problem which confronts the theist. The real problem arises not from the evil in the world, but from the non-perfection of the world. Given that a perfect God could create only a perfect world, and given that the world is not in fact perfect, I construct an argument for atheism. I show that the argument is not open to the objections which theists standardly bring against the traditional objection from (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  66
    Educational Pacifism and Montessori.Nicholas Parkin - 2024 - Journal of Montessori Research 10 (1):25-37.
    Education – typically and rightly held to be an incontrovertible good – has for some time now been dominated by mass formal schooling systems. These systems routinely harm and oppress many students. I argue that they do so impermissibly, and I call this stance “educational pacifism”. I propose that Maria Montessori’s views on mass formal schooling systems broadly align with educational pacifism and that, therefore, she can be considered an educational pacifist. Finally, I claim that contemporary Montessorians ought to be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Hypnotic behavior: A social-psychological interpretation of amnesia, analgesia, and “trance logic”.Nicholas P. Spanos - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):449-467.
    This paper examines research on three hypnotic phenomena: suggested amnesia, suggested analgesia, and “trance logic.” For each case a social-psychological interpretation of hypnotic behavior as a voluntary response strategy is compared with the traditional special-process view that “good” hypnotic subjects have lost conscious control over suggestion-induced behavior. I conclude that it is inaccurate to describe hypnotically amnesic subjects as unable to recall the material they have been instructed to forget. Although amnesics present themselves as unable to remember, they in fact (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  43.  31
    Moving beyond content‐specific computation in artificial neural networks.Nicholas Shea - 2021 - Mind and Language 38 (1):156-177.
    A basic deep neural network (DNN) is trained to exhibit a large set of input–output dispositions. While being a good model of the way humans perform some tasks automatically, without deliberative reasoning, more is needed to approach human‐like artificial intelligence. Analysing recent additions brings to light a distinction between two fundamentally different styles of computation: content‐specific and non‐content‐specific computation (as first defined here). For example, deep episodic RL networks draw on both. So does human conceptual reasoning. Combining the two takes (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  31
    Alasdair MacIntyre, universities, and the common good.Nicholas H. Smith & Andrew Dunstall - 2021 - European Journal of Philosophy 30 (3):1173-1186.
    Best known as a political philosopher, Alasdair MacIntyre is also a critic of the modern university. The paper examines the grounds of MacIntyre's criticism of modern universities; it offers an assessment of the philosophical debate occasioned by MacIntyre's writings on the topic; and it proposes a way of taking this debate forward. The debate is shown to be centred around three objections to MacIntyre's normative idea of the university: that it is overly intellectualist, parochial, and moralizing. The merits of these (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Propositions and Cognitive Relations.Nicholas K. Jones - 2019 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 119 (2):157-178.
    There are two broad approaches to theorizing about ontological categories. Quineans use first-order quantifiers to generalize over entities of each category, whereas type theorists use quantification on variables of different semantic types to generalize over different categories. Does anything of import turn on the difference between these approaches? If so, are there good reasons to go type-theoretic? I argue for positive answers to both questions concerning the category of propositions. I also discuss two prominent arguments for a Quinean conception of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  46.  28
    Conditionals.Nicholas Rescher - 2007 - Bradford.
    This book by distinguished philosopher Nicholas Rescher seeks to clarify the idea of what a conditional says by elucidating the information that is normally transmitted by its utterance. The result is a unified treatment of conditionals based on epistemological principles rather than the semantical principles in vogue over recent decades. This approach, argues Rescher, makes it easier to understand how conditionals actually function in our thought and discourse. In its concern with what language theorists call pragmatics--the study of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  47. Concept‐metacognition.Nicholas Shea - 2019 - Mind and Language 35 (5):565-582.
    Concepts are our tools for thinking. They enable us to engage in explicit reasoning about things in the world. Like physical tools, they can be more or less good, given the ways we use them – more or less dependable for categorisation, learning, induction, action-planning, and so on. Do concept users appreciate, explicitly or implicitly, that concepts vary in dependability? Do they feel that some concepts are in some way defective? If so, we metacognize our concepts. One example that has (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48. Science, Knowledge, Wisdom and the Public Good.Nicholas Maxwell - 2003 - Scientists for Global Responsibility Newsletter 1 (26 February 2003):7-9.
    What kind of science – or, more generally, what kind of academic inquiry – can best contribute to the public good? Two answers are considered: knowledge-inquiry and wisdom-inquiry. The former is what we have at present. It is, however, damagingly irrational. The latter is more rigorous and, potentially, of greater value in human and intellectual terms. It arises as a result of putting the Enlightenment Programme properly into practice. We urgently need to bring about a revolution in academia, so that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Selfless assertions and the Knowledge Norm.Nicholas Tebben - 2020 - Synthese (12):1-20.
    If a speaker selflessly asserts that p, the speaker has good evidence that p is true, asserts that p on the basis of that evidence, but does not believe that p. Selfless assertions are widely thought to be acceptable, and therefore to pose a threat to the Knowledge Norm of Assertion. Advocates for the Knowledge Norm tend to respond to this threat by arguing that there are no such things as selfless assertions. They argue that those who appear to be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  22
    Nudge Economics as Libertarian Paternalism.Nicholas Gane - forthcoming - Theory, Culture and Society:026327642199944.
    Given the growing prominence of nudge economics both within and beyond the academy, it is a timely moment to reassess the philosophical and political arguments that sit at its core, and in particular what Richard Thaler and Cass Sunstein call libertarian paternalism. The first half of this paper provides a detailed account of the main features of this form of paternalism, before moving, in the second half, to a critical evaluation of the nudge agenda that questions, among other things, the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 995