Results for 'pure geometry'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. From practical to pure geometry and back.Mario Bacelar Valente - 2020 - Revista Brasileira de História da Matemática 20 (39):13-33.
    The purpose of this work is to address the relation existing between ancient Greek practical geometry and ancient Greek pure geometry. In the first part of the work, we will consider practical and pure geometry and how pure geometry can be seen, in some respects, as arising from an idealization of practical geometry. From an analysis of relevant extant texts, we will make explicit the idealizations at play in pure geometry (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  37
    Peirce's Potential Continuity and Pure Geometry.Jean-Louis Hudry - 2004 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 40 (2):229 - 243.
  3.  42
    Ni « pure » ni « appliquée » : les usages de la géométrie chez Wittgenstein et Poincaré.Élie During - 2005 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 2 (2):197-214.
    Wittgenstein n'a eu de cesse de critiquer la distinction entre géométrie pure et géométrie appliquée. Cette distinction a été notoirement défendue par les positivistes logiques qui, dans le cadre d'une théorie renouvelée de l'a priori, entendaient marquer une séparation nette entre les mathématiques (systèmes formels non interprétés) et la physique (systèmes interprétés, dotés d'une signification factuelle ou empirique). Les raisons de ce partage perdent leur évidence si l'on envisage la géométrie en action, comme une pratique où les règles ne (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. Pure and applied geometries from a synthetic-axiomatic approach to theories. [Spanish].Germán Guerrero Pino - 2005 - Eidos: Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad Del Norte 3:60-82.
    En este artículo se traza una distinción clara y precisa entre geometría pura y geometría aplicada dentro del marco de las reflexiones sobre los fundamentos de la geometría promovidas por la aparición de geometrías no-euclidianas y en el contexto de las discusiones mantenidas por los empiristas lógicos sobre la estructura general de las teorías empíricas. De manera más particular, se defiende, tal y como proponen los empiristas lógicos, que una geometría pura es un sistema formal que no nos dice nada (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Pure and Applied Geometry in Kant.Marissa Bennett - manuscript
  6.  36
    From the Geometry of Pure Spinors with Their Division Algebras to Fermion Physics.Paolo Budinich - 2002 - Foundations of Physics 32 (9):1347-1398.
    The Cartan equations defining simple spinors (renamed “pure” by C. Chevalley) are interpreted as equations of motion in compact momentum spaces, in a constructive approach in which at each step the dimensions of spinor space are doubled while those of momentum space increased by two. The construction is possible only in the frame of the geometry of simple or pure spinors, which imposes contraint equations on spinors with more than four components, and then momentum spaces result compact, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  8
    L’invention d’une géométrie pure au 17 e siècle: Pascal et son lecteur Leibniz.Debuiche Valérie - 2016 - Studia Leibnitiana 48 (1):42-67.
  8. Le développement des mathématiques pures au XIXe siècle. Iere Partie: La géométrie. De la géométrie descriptive à la géométrie énumérative.G. Loria - 1929 - Scientia 23 (45):du Supplém. 83.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Le développement des mathématiques pures au XIXe siècle. IIeme Partie: La géométrie. De la géométrie différentielle à l'Analysis situs.G. Loria - 1929 - Scientia 23 (45):du Supplém. 107.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Geometrical objects and figures in practical, pure, and applied geometry.Mario Bacelar Valente - 2020 - Disputatio. Philosophical Research Bulletin 9 (15):33-51.
    The purpose of this work is to address what notion of geometrical object and geometrical figure we have in different kinds of geometry: practical, pure, and applied. Also, we address the relation between geometrical objects and figures when this is possible, which is the case of pure and applied geometry. In practical geometry it turns out that there is no conception of geometrical object.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11. Riemann’s Philosophy of Geometry and Kant’s Pure Intuition.Dinçer çevik - 2024 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 31 (2):114-140.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. The Constitution of Weyl’s Pure Infinitesimal World Geometry.C. D. McCoy - 2022 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 12 (1):189–208.
    Hermann Weyl was one of the most important figures involved in the early elaboration of the general theory of relativity and its fundamentally geometrical spacetime picture of the world. Weyl’s development of “pure infinitesimal geometry” out of relativity theory was the basis of his remarkable attempt at unifying gravitation and electromagnetism. Many interpreters have focused primarily on Weyl’s philosophical influences, especially the influence of Husserl’s transcendental phenomenology, as the motivation for these efforts. In this article, I argue both (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  10
    La théorie des Würfe de von Staudt – Une irruption de l’algèbre dans la géométrie pure.Philippe Nabonnand - 2008 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 62 (3):201-242.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14.  94
    Natural Geometry in Descartes and Kepler.Gary Hatfield - 2015 - Res Philosophica 92 (1):117-148.
    According to Kepler and Descartes, the geometry of the triangle formed by the two eyes when focused on a single point affords perception of the distance to that point. Kepler characterized the processes involved as associative learning. Descartes described the processes as a “ natural geometry.” Many interpreters have Descartes holding that perceivers calculate the distance to the focal point using angle-side-angle, calculations that are reduced to unnoticed mental habits in adult vision. This article offers a purely psychophysiological (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15.  15
    Space, Geometry, and Kant's Transcendental Deduction of the Categories.Thomas C. Vinci - 2014 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Thomas C. Vinci argues that Kant's Deductions demonstrate Kant's idealist doctrines and have the structure of an inference to the best explanation for correlated domains. With the Deduction of the Categories the correlated domains are intellectual conditions and non-geometrical laws of the empirical world. With the Deduction of the Concepts of Space, the correlated domains are the geometry of pure objects of intuition and the geometry of empirical objects.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  40
    The geometry of state space.M. Adelman, J. V. Corbett & C. A. Hurst - 1993 - Foundations of Physics 23 (2):211-223.
    The geometry of the state space of a finite-dimensional quantum mechanical system, with particular reference to four dimensions, is studied. Many novel features, not evident in the two-dimensional space of a single spin, are found. Although the state space is a convex set, it is not a ball, and its boundary contains mixed states in addition to the pure states, which form a low-dimensional submanifold. The appropriate language to describe the role of the observer is that of flag (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. On the relationship between geometric objects and figures in Euclidean geometry.Mario Bacelar Valente - 2021 - In Diagrammatic Representation and Inference. 12th International Conference, Diagrams 2021. pp. 71-78.
    In this paper, we will make explicit the relationship that exists between geometric objects and geometric figures in planar Euclidean geometry. That will enable us to determine basic features regarding the role of geometric figures and diagrams when used in the context of pure and applied planar Euclidean geometry, arising due to this relationship. By taking into account pure geometry, as developed in Euclid’s Elements, and practical geometry, we will establish a relation between geometric (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  91
    Husserl on Geometry and Spatial Representation.Jairo José da Silva - 2012 - Axiomathes 22 (1):5-30.
    Husserl left many unpublished drafts explaining (or trying to) his views on spatial representation and geometry, such as, particularly, those collected in the second part of Studien zur Arithmetik und Geometrie (Hua XXI), but no completely articulate work on the subject. In this paper, I put forward an interpretation of what those views might have been. Husserl, I claim, distinguished among different conceptions of space, the space of perception (constituted from sensorial data by intentionally motivated psychic functions), that of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  17
    Jan von Plato. The axioms of constructive geometry. Annals of pure and applied logic, vol. 76 , pp. 169–200.Wolfgang Rautenberg - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):687-688.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Kant on geometry and spatial intuition.Michael Friedman - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):231-255.
    I use recent work on Kant and diagrammatic reasoning to develop a reconsideration of central aspects of Kant’s philosophy of geometry and its relation to spatial intuition. In particular, I reconsider in this light the relations between geometrical concepts and their schemata, and the relationship between pure and empirical intuition. I argue that diagrammatic interpretations of Kant’s theory of geometrical intuition can, at best, capture only part of what Kant’s conception involves and that, for example, they cannot explain (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  21.  12
    Geometry and arithmetic in the medieval traditions of Euclid’s Elements: a view from Book II.Leo Corry - 2013 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 67 (6):637-705.
    This article explores the changing relationships between geometric and arithmetic ideas in medieval Europe mathematics, as reflected via the propositions of Book II of Euclid’s Elements. Of particular interest is the way in which some medieval treatises organically incorporated into the body of arithmetic results that were formulated in Book II and originally conceived in a purely geometric context. Eventually, in the Campanus version of the Elements these results were reincorporated into the arithmetic books of the Euclidean treatise. Thus, while (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  22.  41
    The synthetic nature of geometry, and the role of construction in intuition.Anja Jauernig - 2013 - In Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht: Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant Kongresses 2010 in Pisa, Volume V. Berlin/New York: pp. 89-100.
    Most commentators agree that (part of what) Kant means by characterizing the propositions of geometry as synthetic is that they are not true merely in virtue of logic or meaning, and that this characterization has something to do with his views about the construction of geometrical concepts in intuition. Many commentators regard construction in intuition as an essential part of geometrical proofs on Kant’s view. On this reading, the propositions of geometry are synthetic because the geometrical theorems cannot (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  31
    Geometry, mechanics, and experience: a historico-philosophical musing.Olivier Darrigol - 2022 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 12 (4):1-36.
    Euclidean geometry, statics, and classical mechanics, being in some sense the simplest physical theories based on a full-fledged mathematical apparatus, are well suited to a historico-philosophical analysis of the way in which a physical theory differs from a purely mathematical theory. Through a series of examples including Newton’s Principia and later forms of mechanics, we will identify the interpretive substructure that connects the mathematical apparatus of the theory to the world of experience. This substructure includes models of experiments, models (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  61
    Husserl on Geometry and Spatial Representation.Jairo José Silva - 2012 - Axiomathes 22 (1):5-30.
    Husserl left many unpublished drafts explaining (or trying to) his views on spatial representation and geometry, such as, particularly, those collected in the second part of Studien zur Arithmetik und Geometrie (Hua XXI), but no completely articulate work on the subject. In this paper, I put forward an interpretation of what those views might have been. Husserl, I claim, distinguished among different conceptions of space, the space of perception (constituted from sensorial data by intentionally motivated psychic functions), that of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25. Hume on space, geometry, and diagrammatic reasoning.Graciela De Pierris - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):169-189.
    Hume’s discussion of space, time, and mathematics at T 1.2 appeared to many earlier commentators as one of the weakest parts of his philosophy. From the point of view of pure mathematics, for example, Hume’s assumptions about the infinite may appear as crude misunderstandings of the continuum and infinite divisibility. I shall argue, on the contrary, that Hume’s views on this topic are deeply connected with his radically empiricist reliance on phenomenologically given sensory images. He insightfully shows that, working (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  26.  26
    Islamic Geometries: Spiritual Affects Against a Secularist Grid.Wendy M. K. Shaw - 2022 - Sophia 61 (1):41-59.
    Discussions of surface pattern in Islamic art resonate within broader tensions about the role of figural representation in communicating meaning. The question of whether geometric pattern communicates—whether it functions as a language without a code—reflects broader tensions about the relationship between secular and spiritual communication. Poised between discussions of modernism and Islam, the attribution of linguistic capacity to geometry serves as a measure for the possibility of abstracting pure reason from the religious roots of representationalism. This paper explores (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  24
    Visual Geometry of Classical Japanese Gardens.Gert Jakobus van Tonder - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (5):841-868.
    The concept of geometry may evoke a world of pure platonic shapes, such as spheres and cubes, but a deeper understanding of visual experience demands insight into the perceptual organization of naturalistic form. Japanese gardens excel as designed environments where the complex fractal geometry of nature has been simplified to a structural core that retains the essential properties of the natural landscape, thereby presenting an ideal opportunity for investigating the geometry and perceptual significance of such naturalistic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Geometry and Experimental Method in Locke, Newton and Kant.Mary Domski - 2003 - Dissertation, Indiana University
    Historians of modern philosophy have been paying increasing attention to contemporaneous scientific developments. Isaac Newton's Principia is of course crucial to any discussion of the influence of scientific advances on the philosophical currents of the modern period, and two philosophers who have been linked especially closely to Newton are John Locke and Immanuel Kant. My dissertation aims to shed new light on the ties each shared with Newtonian science by treating Newton, Locke, and Kant simultaneously. I adopt Newton's philosophy of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  60
    Hume on Space and Geometry': A Rejoinder to Flew's 'One Reservation.Rosemary Newman - 1982 - Hume Studies 8 (1):66-69.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:66. ' HUME ON SPACE AND GEOMETRY * : A REJOINDER TO FLEW ' S 'ONE RESERVATION '.? Flew' s reservation about my assertion that the Enquiry contains no significant revision of the Treatise conception of geometry as a body of necessary and synthetic knowledge, appears to involve two charges. Firstly, he alleges that I dismiss but offer no substantial argument against his own view that the (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Kant's "argument from geometry".Lisa Shabel - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (2):195-215.
    : Kant's 'argument from geometry' is usually interpreted to be a regressive transcendental argument in support of the claim that we have a pure intuition of space. In this paper I defend an alternative interpretation of this argument according to which it is rather a progressive synthetic argument meant to identify and establish the essential role of pure spatial intuition in geometric cognition. In the course of reinterpreting the 'argument from geometry' I reassess the arguments of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  31.  63
    Frege’s philosophy of geometry.Matthias Schirn - 2019 - Synthese 196 (3):929-971.
    In this paper, I critically discuss Frege’s philosophy of geometry with special emphasis on his position in The Foundations of Arithmetic of 1884. In Sect. 2, I argue that that what Frege calls faculty of intuition in his dissertation is probably meant to refer to a capacity of visualizing geometrical configurations structurally in a way which is essentially the same for most Western educated human beings. I further suggest that according to his Habilitationsschrift it is through spatial intuition that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  41
    Geometry as an aspect of dynamics.A. L. L. Videira, A. L. Rocha Barros & N. C. Fernandes - 1985 - Foundations of Physics 15 (12):1247-1262.
    Contrary to the predominant way of doing physics, we claim that the geometrical structure of a general differentiable space-time manifold can be determined from purely dynamical considerations. Anyn-dimensional manifoldV a has associated with it a symplectic structure given by the2n numbersp andx of the2n-dimensional cotangent fiber bundle TVn. Hence, one is led, in a natural way, to the Hamiltonian description of dynamics, constructed in terms of the covariant momentump (a dynamical quantity) and of the contravariant position vectorx (a geometrical quantity). (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  6
    Geometry and analysis in Anastácio da Cunha’s calculus.João Caramalho Domingues - 2023 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 77 (6):579-600.
    It is well known that over the eighteenth century the calculus moved away from its geometric origins; Euler, and later Lagrange, aspired to transform it into a “purely analytical” discipline. In the 1780 s, the Portuguese mathematician José Anastácio da Cunha developed an original version of the calculus whose interpretation in view of that process presents challenges. Cunha was a strong admirer of Newton (who famously favoured geometry over algebra) and criticized Euler’s faith in analysis. However, the fundamental propositions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  26
    Geometry of Robinson consistency in Łukasiewicz logic.Manuela Busaniche & Daniele Mundici - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 147 (1):1-22.
    We establish the Robinson joint consistency theorem for the infinite-valued propositional logic of Łukasiewicz. As a corollary we easily obtain the amalgamation property for MV-algebras—the algebras of Łukasiewicz logic: all pre-existing proofs of this latter result make essential use of the Pierce amalgamation theorem for abelian lattice-ordered groups together with the categorical equivalence Γ between these groups and MV-algebras. Our main tools are elementary and geometric.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35. Space, points and mereology. On foundations of point-free Euclidean geometry.Rafał Gruszczyński & Andrzej Pietruszczak - 2009 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 18 (2):145-188.
    This article is devoted to the problem of ontological foundations of three-dimensional Euclidean geometry. Starting from Bertrand Russell’s intuitions concerning the sensual world we try to show that it is possible to build a foundation for pure geometry by means of the so called regions of space. It is not our intention to present mathematically developed theory, but rather demonstrate basic assumptions, tools and techniques that are used in construction of systems of point-free geometry and topology (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  36.  49
    'Hume on Space and Geometry': One Reservation.Antony Flew - 1982 - Hume Studies 8 (1):62-65.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:62. 'HUME ON SPACE AND GEOMETRY': ONE RESERVATION In so far as Rosemary Newman disagrees with any2 thing said in my 'Infinite Divisibility in Hume's Treatise ' - which seems, happily, not to be so very far - I hasten to report that I am now persuaded. Thus my suggested reason for refusing to allow that an impression of blackness could give rise to the idea of extension (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  61
    'Hume on Space and Geometry': One Reservation.Antony Flew - 1982 - Hume Studies 8 (1):62-65.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:62. 'HUME ON SPACE AND GEOMETRY': ONE RESERVATION In so far as Rosemary Newman disagrees with any2 thing said in my 'Infinite Divisibility in Hume's Treatise ' - which seems, happily, not to be so very far - I hasten to report that I am now persuaded. Thus my suggested reason for refusing to allow that an impression of blackness could give rise to the idea of extension (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  23
    Projective geometries of algebraically closed fields of characteristic zero.Kitty L. Holland - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 60 (3):237-260.
    Fix an algebraically closed field of characteristic zero and let G be its geometry of transcendence degree one extensions. Let X be a set of points of G. We show that X extends to a projective subgeometry of G exactly if the partial derivatives of the polynomials inducing dependence on its elements satisfy certain separability conditions. This analysis produces a concrete representation of the coordinatizing fields of maximal projective subgeometries of G.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  46
    On Natural Geometry and Seeing Distance Directly in Descartes.Gary Hatfield - 2015 - In Vincenzo De Risi (ed.), Mathematizing Space: The Objects of Geometry from Antiquity to the Early Modern Age. Birkhäuser. pp. 157-91.
    As the word “optics” was understood from antiquity into and beyond the early modern period, it did not mean simply the physics and geometry of light, but meant the “theory of vision” and included what we should now call physiological and psychological aspects. From antiquity, these aspects were subject to geometrical analysis. Accordingly, the geometry of visual experience has long been an object of investigation. This chapter examines accounts of size and distance perception in antiquity (Euclid and Ptolemy) (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  19
    Free Variation and the Intuition of Geometric Essences: Some Reflections on Phenomenology and Modern Geometry.Richard Tieszen - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):153-173.
    Edmund Husserl has argued that we can intuit essences and, moreover, that it is possible to formulate a method for intuiting essences. Husserl calls this method ‘ideation’. In this paper I bring a fresh perspective to bear on these claims by illustrating them in connection with some examples from modern pure geometry. I follow Husserl in describing geometric essences as invariants through different types of free variations and I then link this to the mapping out of geometric invariants (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  41.  41
    Space, Geometry and Kant’s Transcendental Deduction of the Categories by Thomas C. Vinci.Mary Domski - 2016 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (1):174-175.
    Those familiar with the Critique of Pure Reason will not at all be surprised that Thomas C. Vinci has found it fitting to dedicate an entire book to the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories, a chapter of the CPR that is as important to Kant’s argument for Transcendental Idealism as it is difficult to decipher. The purpose of that section is to establish the objective validity of the categories—to show, that is, that the pure concepts of the understanding (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  47
    The geometry of Hrushovski constructions, I: The uncollapsed case.David M. Evans & Marco S. Ferreira - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (6):474-488.
    An intermediate stage in Hrushovski’s construction of flat strongly minimal structures in a relational language L produces ω-stable structures of rank ω. We analyze the pregeometries given by forking on the regular type of rank ω in these structures. We show that varying L can affect the isomorphism type of the pregeometry, but not its finite subpregeometries. A sequel will compare these to the pregeometries of the strongly minimal structures.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43. Free variation and the intuition of geometric essences: Some reflections on phenomenology and modern geometry.Richard Tieszen - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):153–173.
    Edmund Husserl has argued that we can intuit essences and, moreover, that it is possible to formulate a method for intuiting essences. Husserl calls this method 'ideation'. In this paper I bring a fresh perspective to bear on these claims by illustrating them in connection with some examples from modern pure geometry. I follow Husserl in describing geometric essences as invariants through different types of free variations and I then link this to the mapping out of geometric invariants (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  44.  33
    The axioms of constructive geometry.Jan von Plato - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 76 (2):169-200.
    Elementary geometry can be axiomatized constructively by taking as primitive the concepts of the apartness of a point from a line and the convergence of two lines, instead of incidence and parallelism as in the classical axiomatizations. I first give the axioms of a general plane geometry of apartness and convergence. Constructive projective geometry is obtained by adding the principle that any two distinct lines converge, and affine geometry by adding a parallel line construction, etc. Constructive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  45. Visual geometry.James Hopkins - 1982 - In Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker (ed.), Kant on Pure Reason. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  17
    Physiological Optics and Physical Geometry.David Jalal Hyder - 2001 - Science in Context 14 (3):419-456.
    ArgumentHermann von Helmholtz’s distinction between “pure intuitive” and “physical” geometry must be counted as the most influential of his many contributions to the philosophy of science. In a series of papers from the 1860s and 70s, Helmholtz argued against Kant’s claim that our knowledge of Euclidean geometry was an a priori condition for empirical knowledge. He claimed that geometrical propositions could be meaningful only if they were taken to concern the behaviors of physical bodies used in measurement, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47.  62
    Matter Creation by Geometry in an Integrable Weyl-Dirac Theory.Mark Israelit - 1999 - Foundations of Physics 29 (8):1303-1322.
    An integrable version of the Weyl-Dirac geometry is presented. This framework is a natural generalization of the Riemannian geometry, the latter being the basis of the classical general relativity theory. The integrable Weyl-Dirac theory is both coordinate covariant and gauge covariant (in the Weyl sense), and the field equations and conservation laws are derived from an action integral. In this framework matter creation by geometry is considered. It is found that a spatially confined, spherically symmetric formation made (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48. Kant on Euclid: Geometry in Perspective.Stephen R. Palmquist - 1990 - Philosophia Mathematica (1-2):88-113.
    There is a common assumption among philosophers, shared even by many Kant scholars, that Kant had a naive faith in the absolute valid­ity of Euclidean geometry, Aristotelian logic, and Newtonian physics, and that his primary goal in the Critique of Pure Reason was to pro­vide a rational foundation upon which these classical scientific theories could be based. This, it might be thought, is the essence of his attempt to solve the problem which, as he says in a footnote (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49. A 2-dimensional geometry for biological time.Francis Bailly, Giuseppe Longo & Maël Montévil - 2011 - Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 106:474 - 484.
    This paper proposes an abstract mathematical frame for describing some features of biological time. The key point is that usual physical (linear) representation of time is insufficient, in our view, for the understanding key phenomena of life, such as rhythms, both physical (circadian, seasonal …) and properly biological (heart beating, respiration, metabolic …). In particular, the role of biological rhythms do not seem to have any counterpart in mathematical formalization of physical clocks, which are based on frequencies along the usual (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  78
    Bridging the gap between analytic and synthetic geometry: Hilbert’s axiomatic approach.Eduardo N. Giovannini - 2016 - Synthese 193 (1):31-70.
    The paper outlines an interpretation of one of the most important and original contributions of David Hilbert’s monograph Foundations of Geometry , namely his internal arithmetization of geometry. It is claimed that Hilbert’s profound interest in the problem of the introduction of numbers into geometry responded to certain epistemological aims and methodological concerns that were fundamental to his early axiomatic investigations into the foundations of elementary geometry. In particular, it is shown that a central concern that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000