Related categories

152 found
Order:
1 — 50 / 152
  1. Die Dritte Moeglichkeit: The Neo-Kantian 'Raum' Controversy, From Trendelenburg to Vaihinger.Christopher Stephen Adair-Toteff - 1992 - Dissertation, University of South Florida
    In the "Transcendental Aesthetic" section of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft Kant dismisses both the Newtonian and the Leibnizian notions of space. In their place he offers his own view that space is a "pure intuition" which is both empirically real and transcendentally ideal. Kant means by this that space is objectively valid and is applicable to things as they appear to us, but that it is not something that either exists independently of humans or as a relation that pertains (...)
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  2. Kant's Neglected Alternative: Neither Neglected nor An Alternative.Necip Fikri Alican - 2017 - Philosophical Forum 48 (1):69–90.
    This is a defense of Kant against the allegedly neglected alternative in his formulation of transcendental idealism. What sets it apart from the contributions of others who have spoken for Kant in this regard is the construction of a general interpretive framework — a reconstruction of the one Kant provides for transcendental idealism — as opposed to the development of an ad hoc defensive strategy for refuting the charges. Hence, comprehensive clarification instead of pointed rebuttal. The difference is between focusing (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  3. Kant, Non-Conceptual Content and the Representation of Space.Lucy Allais - 2009 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (3):pp. 383-413.
    :Space is not an empirical concept that has been drawn from outer experiences. For in order for certain sensations to be related to something outside me , thus in order for me to represent them as outside and next to one another, thus not merely different but as in different places, the representation of space must already be their ground. Thus the representation of space cannot be obtained from the relations of outer appearance through experience, but this outer experience is (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   22 citations  
  4. The Non-Spatiality of Things in Themselves for Kant.Henry E. Allison - 1976 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 14 (3):313-321.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   6 citations  
  5. A Hitherto Unknown Critique of Kant Theory of Time and Space by Eberhard.A. Altmann - 1988 - Kant-Studien 79 (3):329-341.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  6. Eine bisher unbekannte frühe Kritik Eberhards an Kants Raum-und Zeitlehre.Alexander Altmann - 1988 - Kant-Studien 79 (3):329-341.
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  7. Acerca de las parejas incongruentes y las figuras simétricas.Carlos Álvarez - 2003 - Critica 35 (104):31-68.
    Kant plantea el problema de las parejas incongruentes en 1768, posteriormente en 1770 y 1783. Este problema, relacionado con su concepción acerca de la naturaleza del espacio, se vincula también con su idea sobre la naturaleza del conocimiento geométrico. Mi objetivo en este texto es analizar las observaciones de Kant sobre este punto--tres de las cuales son, a nuestro juicio, de suma relevancia--a partir de la geometría sólida euclidiana, la que constituye precisamente el marco teórico en el cual él pretende (...)
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  8. Las nociones de espacio y tiempo en la obra pre-crítica de Kant.Antonio J. Pacheco Amitesarove - 2010 - Dikaiosyne: Revista Semestral de Filosofía Práctica 24 (13):89-124.
    El propósito de este trabajo es únicamente esclarecer el sentido de las nociones de espacio y tiempo, tal como Kant las entiende en esta obra precrítica suya de 1763. El propósito del trabajo se enmarca dentro de uno más amplio que examina estas nociones desde el primer escrito de Kant de 1747 , a través de todo el período precrítico, hasta concluir con la obra de 1770 , punto de inflexión y de partida de las reflexiones que once años después (...)
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  9. L'espace dans ses dimensions transcendantale et pragmatiste.Manuel Bächtold - 2011 - Kant-Studien 102 (2):145-167.
    This article examines the Kantian thesis of the a priori nature of our knowledge of space. Because it makes the representation of objects possible as external to us and all others, and consequently, as distinct and individualized, space (whatever its structure may be) claims the status as necessary condition and as apriori possibility of all knowledge. However, in the light of various physical, psychological and philosophical considerations, it seems that the particular structure allocated by Kant to space (i.e. uniqueness, infinity, (...)
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  10. The Space in its Transcendental and Pragmatist Dimensions.Manuel Baechtold - 2011 - Kant-Studien 102 (2).
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  11. Space, Time and Mind-Dependence.Sorin Baiasu - 2011 - Kantian Review 16 (2):175-190.
  12. Henry More and Kant: A Note to the Second Argument on Space in the Transcendental Aesthetic.John Tull Baker - 1937 - Philosophical Review 46 (3):298-306.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  13. Kant, Herbart and Riemann.Erik C. Banks - 2005 - Kant-Studien 96 (2):208-234.
    A look at the dynamical concept of space and space-generating processes to be found in Kant, J.F. Herbart and the mathematician Bernhard Riemann's philosophical writings.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  14. Raum, Zeit und Kausalität im System des kritischen Realismus.B. Bavink - 1927 - Kant-Studien 32 (1-3):264-272.
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  15. Pure and Applied Geometry in Kant.Marissa Bennett - manuscript
  16. Kant on Spatial Orientation.Sven Bernecker - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (4):519-533.
    This paper develops a novel interpretation of Kant's argument from incongruent counterparts to the effect that the representations of space and time are intuitions rather than concepts. When properly understood, the argument anticipates the contemporary position whereby the meaning of indexicals cannot be captured by descriptive contents.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  17. Reply to Edward Kanterian.Graham Bird - 2013 - Kantian Review 18 (2):289-300.
    The reply to Kanterian offers a rebuttal of his central criticisms. It reaffirms the difference between Kant's arguments in the Aesthetic and at B 148-9; it rejects the alleged error of logic in Fischer's (and my) arguments; and it rejects Kanterian's reading of passages in the Preface (A xx-xxii) and of the Amphiboly. Beyond these specific points Kanterian assumes that Kant's project in the first Critique cannot be understood as a and so begs the question at issue.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  18. Kant et la matière de l'espace.Henny Blomme - forthcoming - Georg Olms Verlag.
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  19. Kants Raumbegriff in der Diskussion.Henny Blomme - 2013 - Philosophische Rundschau 60 (3):225-239.
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  20. Können wir den ursprünglichen Raum erkennen?Henny Blomme - 2013 - In Dieter Hüning, Stefan Klingner & Carsten Olk (eds.), Das Leben der Vernunft. Beiträge zur Philosophie Kants. De Gruyter. pp. 30-39.
    Mit dem Terminus 'ursprünglicher Raum' wird der Raum bezeichnet, der Kant innerhalb der transzendentalen Ästhetik als reine subjektive Form der Anschauung des äußeren Sinnes bestimmt. Man könnte ihn auch den 'ästhetischen Raum' nennen. Auf jeden Fall muss er vom (proto-)geometrischen Raum unterschieden werden, da letzterer eine Einheit voraussetzt die auf einer Synthesis beruht, und dadurch – weil bei Kant alle Synthesis unter den Kategorien steht – weniger ursprünglich zum Anschauungsvermögen gehört. Es ist diese Unterscheidung zwischen dem ursprünglichen Raum, der „Form (...)
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  21. The Completeness of Kant's Metaphysical Exposition of Space.Henny Blomme - 2012 - Kant-Studien 103 (2):139-162.
    In the first edition of his book on the completeness of Kant’s table of judgments, Klaus Reich shortly indicates that the B-version of the metaphysical exposition of space in the Critique of pure reason is structured following the inverse order of the table of categories. In this paper, I develop Reich’s claim and provide further evidence for it. My argumentation is as follows: Through analysis of our actually given representation of space as some kind of object (the formal intuition of (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  22. Non-Euclidean Geometry, the Philosophical Problem of Space, and the Origins of the Transcendental: Helmholtz and Kant, the Neo-Kantians, Einstein, Poincare, and Mach.L. Boi - 1996 - Kant-Studien 87 (3):257-289.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  23. Les géométries non euclidiennes, le problème philosophique de l'espace et la conception transcendantale; Helmholtz et Kant, les néo-kantiens, Einstein, Poincaré et Mach.Luciano Boi - 1996 - Kant-Studien 87 (3):257-289.
  24. Über den Begriff des Unendlichen und der intelligibeln Ausdehnung bei Malebranche und die Beziehung des letzteren zum Kantischen Raumbegriff.Artur Buchenau - 1909 - Kant-Studien 14 (1-3):440-467.
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  25. Review: Falkenstein, Kant's Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic. [REVIEW]Jill Vance Buroker - 1997 - Kantian Review 1 (1):162-171.
  26. A Remark on Kant's Argument From Incongruent Counterparts.Jeremy Byrd - 2008 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16 (4):789 – 800.
    I argue that, by the time of his essay "Concerning the Ultimate Ground of the Differentiation of Directions in Space" (1768), Kant had come to question the status of the Principle of Sufficient Reason as a result, at least in part, of his recognition of the existence of incongruent counterparts. Though Kant's argument against absolute space based on the existence of incongruent counterparts has been much discussed in recent years, its importance as a useful benchmark by which to judge the (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  27. Contemporary Kantian Metaphysics: New Essays on Space and Time.John J. Callanan - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (1):144-148.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  28. Über die Abhängigkeit der Eigenschaften des Raumes von denen der Zeit.Rudolf Carnap - 1925 - Kant-Studien 30 (1-2):331-345.
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   3 citations  
  29. Kant's Relational Theory of Absolute Space.Martin Carrier - 1992 - Kant-Studien 83 (4):399-416.
  30. Que sont donc l'espace et le temps? Les hypothèses considérées par Kant et la lancinante objection de la «troisième possibilité».François-Xavier Chenet - 1993 - Kant-Studien 84 (2):129-153.
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  31. Van Cleve and the Neglected Alternative.Jeremy Delong - 2009 - Auslegung 30 (1).
    In Van Cleve's "Problems from Kant," it is suggested that his interpretation of Kant's metaphysics resolves the problem of "The Neglected Alternative"--the worry that Kant failed to consider that space and time, while perhaps necessary for sensible intuition, could also be objectively real in-themselves. However, it is far from clear how Van Cleve is supposed to have solved this objection. This paper examines why Van Cleve might have thought the problem resolved on his view, and argues that there is no (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  32. Le Statut de l'espace esthétique dans la philosophie kantienne.Éric Dufour & Julien Servois - 2005 - Kant-Studien 96 (2):161-181.
    Il semble tout autant irrecevable de comprendre l’Esthétique à l’aune de la Logique que de mettre sur le même plan les écrits des différentes périodes de Kant : on nie par là même le sens positif de l’Esthétique, puisque, en expliquant ce passage en rapport à ce qui suit, on en gomme la spécificité. C’est alors l’irréductibilité de la passivité et la signification véritable de l’espace et du temps qui se trouvent anéanties. Or cette passivité est pourtant attestée par l’expression (...)
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  33. Review: Buroker, Space and Incongruence: The Origin of Kant's Idealism. [REVIEW]Howard Duncan - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (2):346-.
  34. Tetens as a Reader of Kant's Inaugural Dissertation.Corey W. Dyck - forthcoming - In Violetta L. Waibel & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Akten des 12. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses “Natur und Freiheit” in Wien vom 21.–25. September 2015.
    In this paper I consider Tetens' reaction to Kant's Inaugural Dissertation in his two most important philosophical works, the essay “Über die allgemeine speculativische Philosophie” of 1775 and the two-volume Philosophische Versuche of 1777. In particular, I focus on Tetens’ critical discussion of Kant's account of the acquisition of concepts of space and time.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  35. Mendelssohn Versus Kant--Early Evidence of a Confrontation with Kant's Doctrine of Time and Space in the Dissertation of 1770.E. J. Engel - 2004 - Kant-Studien 95 (3):269-282.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  36. Kant 2nd Antinomy and Physics.B. Falkenburg - 1995 - Kant-Studien 86 (1):4-25.
  37. Kant's Argument for the Non-Spatiotemporality of Things in Themselves.Lorne Falkenstein - 1989 - Kant-Studien 80 (1-4):265-283.
  38. 'L'espace est représenté comme une grandeur infinie donnée': La radicalité de l'esthétique.Michel Fichant - 1997 - Philosophie 56:20-48.
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   1 citation  
  39. Space and the Schematism.Gregg E. Franzwa - 1978 - Kant-Studien 69 (1-4):149-159.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  40. Multi-Spatial Myths: Kant and the Dreamer.Peter A. French - 1973 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 11 (3):167-174.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  41. Perspectivas modernas: Leibniz, Newton y Kant.Martin F. Fricke - 2012 - In Rosario Gómez, Adam Sellen & Arturo Taracena Arriola (eds.), Diálogos sobre los espacios: imaginados, percibidos y construidos. UNAM. pp. 47-78.
    El capítulo introduce al debate sobre la naturaleza del espacio entre Leibniz y Clarke/Newton y a la posición que adopta Kant más tarde. En particular, se exponen los dos principales argumentos de Leibniz, basados en los Principios de Razón Suficiente e Identidad de Indiscernibles, en favor del relacionismo así como algunas respuestas de Clarke/Newton. También se presenta el argumento basado en la orientación del espacio que propuso Kant en 1768 para refutar al relacionismo de Leibniz. Se concluye con una breve (...)
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  42. Geometria e Intuição espacial em Kant: Série 2.Michael Friedman - 2012 - Kant E-Prints 7:02-32.
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
     
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  43. Kant on Geometry and Spatial Intuition.Michael Friedman - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):231-255.
    I use recent work on Kant and diagrammatic reasoning to develop a reconsideration of central aspects of Kant’s philosophy of geometry and its relation to spatial intuition. In particular, I reconsider in this light the relations between geometrical concepts and their schemata, and the relationship between pure and empirical intuition. I argue that diagrammatic interpretations of Kant’s theory of geometrical intuition can, at best, capture only part of what Kant’s conception involves and that, for example, they cannot explain why Kant (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography   8 citations  
  44. Kant on Space, the Understanding, and the Law of Gravitation.Michael Friedman - 1989 - The Monist 72 (2):236-284.
  45. Kant's Theory of Geometry.Michael Friedman - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (4):455-506.
  46. Review: Hatfield, The Natural and the Normative. [REVIEW]S. P. Fullinwider - 1993 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 24 (3):485-491.
  47. Leibnizens Philosophie der Zeit und des Raumes.W. Gent - 1926 - Kant-Studien 31 (1-3):61-88.
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  48. Who Was the 'Great Man', Who Prepared the Theory of Space of Transcendental Idealism? (Kant, Moses Mendelssohn).B. Gerlach - 1998 - Kant-Studien 89 (1):1-34.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  49. Leibniz, Kant und der moderne Symmetriebegriff.Marco Giovanelli - 2011 - Kant-Studien 102 (4):422-454.
    The paper analyses the significance of the modern concept of „symmetry“ for the understanding of the concept of „intuition“ in Kant's philosophy of geometry. A symmetry transformation or automorphism is a structure preserving mapping of the space into itself that leaves all relevant structure intact so that the result is always like the original, in all relevant respects. Hermann Weyl was the first to show that this idea can be drawn on Leibniz's definition of similarity: two figures are similar if (...)
    Remove from this list  
    Translate
      Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
  50. On the Transcendental Ideality of Space and Time in Modern Physics.Shahen Hacyan - 2006 - Kant-Studien 97 (3):382-395.
    In Newtonian physics, all phenomena take place in absolute space, which is a fixed scenario, and are referred to absolute time, which rules all processes. Motion is governed by a set of basic differential equations, and it is possible, at least in principle, to deduce future events from present initial conditions.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    My bibliography  
1 — 50 / 152