Results for 'Virtue ethics, Aristotle’s ethics, unity of the virtues, Anthropocene, planetary virtues'

990 found
Order:
  1. The Unity of the Moral Virtues in Aristotle's "Nicomachean Ethics".Elizabeth Telfer - 1990 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90:35 - 48.
    Elizabeth Telfer; III*—The Unity of the Moral Virtues in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics1, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 90, Issue 1, 1 June 19.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  2. The unity of the virtues in Aristotle, in Alexander of Aphrodisias, and in the Byzantine commentators.R. Sharples - 2000 - Etica E Politica 2 (2).
    Aristotle’s argument in Nicomachean Ethics 6 for the mutual implication of the virtues by one another is developed, and others added to it, in a repertory of arguments for this thesis in section 18 of the De anima libri mantissa attributed to Alexander of Aphrodisias. The last part of this is echoed in no.22 of the Ethical Problems attributed to Alexander; nos. 8 and 28 of the same collection are also relevant. A distinction can be drawn between the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  54
    Aristotle’s Conception of Ethical and Natural Virtue: How the Unity Thesis sheds light on the Doctrine of the Mean.Anselm Winfried Müller - 2004 - In Matthias Lutz-Bachmann & Jan Szaif (eds.), Was Ist Das Für den Menschen Gute? / What is Good for a Human Being?: Menschliche Natur Und Güterlehre / Human Nature and Values. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 18-53.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  4. Aristotle's Basic and Non-Basic Virtues.Stephen M. Gardiner - 2001 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 20:261-95.
    The structure of Aristotelian virtue ethics has been misunderstood. Conventional wisdom has it that Aristotle, as indeed all of the major philosophers of ancient Greece, believed that the virtues are reciprocally entailing (RV): a person can have one of the virtues of character if and only if she has them all. But this is false. Instead, Aristotle distinguishes between a set of basic and a set of nonbasic virtues, and claims that only the basic virtues (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  12
    Should We Embrace a “New,” Expansionist Agenda for the Virtues?Stephen M. Gardiner - 2021 - In Anne Siegetsleitner, Andreas Oberprantacher, Marie-Luisa Frick & Ulrich Metschl (eds.), Crisis and Critique: Philosophical Analysis and Current Events: Proceedings of the 42nd International Wittgenstein Symposium. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 331-342.
    Abstract: Does the evolving influence of humanity on the Earth’s environment call for new virtues? How might such virtues be seen as contributing to human flourishing? In this paper, I develop Aristotle’s discussion of magnificence and magnanimity to provide a framework within which to discuss such claims. I also defend the controversial view that even if genuinely new virtues may be involved, these may be virtues to which we should not aspire (now, or perhaps ever).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Aristotle's Basic and Non-basic Virtues.Stephen M. Gardiner - 2001 - In David Sedley (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy: Volume Xx Summer 2001. Clarendon Press.
    The structure of Aristotelian virtue ethics has been misunderstood. Conventional wisdom has it that Aristotle, as indeed all of the major philosophers of ancient Greece, believed that the virtues are reciprocally entailing (RV): a person can have one of the virtues of character if and only if she has them all. But this is false. Instead, Aristotle distinguishes between a set of basic and a set of nonbasic virtues, and claims that only the basic virtues (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. The Activity of Happiness In Aristotle’s Ethics.S. J. Gary M. Gurtler - 2003 - Review of Metaphysics 56 (4):801-834.
    One group of commentators takes book 10 as determinative and thus tortures the text in book 1 to say the same thing. This position is described as intellectualist or exclusivist and produces certain puzzles in reading Aristotle’s ethical theory. These puzzles are not benign since the privileged position given wisdom in book 10 seems at odds with the discussion of virtue in book 1 and its development in the Nicomachean Ethics as a whole. Indeed, Aristotle appears inconsistent or (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. The structure of Aristotle's ethical theory: Is it teleological or a virtue ethics?Gerasimos Santas - 1996 - Topoi 15 (1):59-80.
  9.  40
    III*—The Unity of the Moral Virtues in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics1.Elizabeth Telfer - 1990 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 90:35-48.
    Elizabeth Telfer; III*—The Unity of the Moral Virtues in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics1, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 90, Issue 1, 1 June 19.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  10.  51
    The Unity of the Virtues and the Ambiguity of Goodness: A Reappraisal of Aquinas's Theory of the Virtues.Jean Porter - 1993 - Journal of Religious Ethics 21 (1):137 - 163.
    This paper examines Aquinas's contention that the virtues are necessarily connected, in such a way that anyone who fully possesses one of them, necessarily possesses them all. It is argued that this claim, as Aquinas develops it in the "Summa Theologiae", is more complex, interesting, and plausible than it is often taken to be. On his view, the cardinal virtues can be said to be connected in two senses, corresponding to the two senses in which certain virtues (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11. Review of Gottlieb, The Virtue of Aristotle’s Ethics. [REVIEW]Thornton C. Lockwood Jr - 2011 - International Philosophical Quarterly 51 (3):418-420.
    In his Metaphysics of Morals, Kant famously wrote “The distinction between virtue and vice can never be sought in the degree to which one follows certain maxims…In other words, the well-known principle (Aristotle’s) that locates virtue in the mean between two vices is false.” Kant is not the first (or the last) thinker to take to task Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean, but he is representative of a line of criticism of Aristotle’s doctrine which argues (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Aristotle's republic or, why Aristotle's ethics is not virtue ethics.Stephen Buckle - 2002 - Philosophy 77 (4):565-595.
    Modern virtue ethics is commonly presented as an alternative to Kantian and utilitarian views—to ethics focused on action and obligations—and it invokes Aristotle as a predecessor. This paper argues that the Nichomachean Ethics does not represent virtue ethics thus conceived, because the discussion of the virtues of character there serves a quasi-Platonic psychology: it is an account of how to tame the unruly (non-rational) elements of the human soul so that they can be ruled by reason and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  13.  37
    The Nicomachean Ethics.Aristotle . (ed.) - 1926 - New York, N.Y.: Oxford University Press UK.
    Happiness, then, is the best, noblest, and most pleasant thing in the world.'In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle's guiding question is: what is the best thing for a human being? His answer is happiness, but he means, not something we feel, but rather a specially good kind of life. Happiness is made up of activities in which we use the best human capacities, both ones that contribute to our flourishing as members of a community, and ones that allow us to engage (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  14. Phronesis as Ethical Expertise: Naturalism of Second Nature and the Unity of Virtue.Mario De Caro, Maria Silvia Vaccarezza & Ariele Niccoli - 2018 - Journal of Value Inquiry 52 (3):287-305.
    This paper has a twofold aim. On the one hand, we will discuss the much debated question of the source of normativity (which traditionally has nature and practical reason as the two main contenders to this role) and propose a new answer to it. Second, in answering this question, we will present a new account of practical wisdom, which conceives of the ethical virtues as ultimately unified in the chief virtue of phronesis, understood as ethical expertise. To do (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  15.  53
    Cognition of Value in Aristotle’s Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction.Deborah Achtenberg - 2002 - State University of New York Press.
    Argues that the central cognitive component of ethical virtue for Aristotle is awareness of the value of particulars.
  16.  14
    Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Aristotle - 1951 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This new edition of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics is an accurate, readable and accessible translation of one of the world's greatest ethical works. Based on lectures Aristotle gave in Athens in the fourth century BCE, Nicomachean Ethics is one of the most significant works in moral philosophy, and has profoundly influenced the whole course of subsequent philosophical endeavour. It offers seminal, practically oriented discussions of many central ethical issues, including the role of luck in human well-being, moral education, responsibility, courage, justice, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17.  19
    The Golden Age of Virtue:Aristotle's Ethics.Gerasimos Santas - 1995 - Philosophical Books 36 (3):173-174.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  62
    Kalokagathia and the Unity of the Virtues in the Eudemian Ethics.Giulia Bonasio - 2020 - Apeiron 53 (1):27-57.
    In this paper, I argue that in the Eudemian Ethics, Aristotle proposes a strong version of the unity of the virtues. Evidence in favor of this strong version of the unity of the virtues results from reading the common books within the EE rather than as part of the Nicomachean Ethics. The unity of the virtues as defended in the EE includes not only practical wisdom and the character virtues, but also all the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  30
    The Politics of the Anthropocene.John S. Dryzek & Jonathan Pickering - 2018 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This is a book about how politics, government - and much else - needs to change in response to the transition from the Holocene to the Anthropocene, the emerging epoch of human-induced instability in the Earth system and its life-support capacities.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  20. Physis and Nomos in Aristotle's Ethics.Thornton Lockwood - 2005 - Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12.
    The relationship between nature and normativity in Aristotle’s practical philosophy is problematic. On the one hand, Aristotle insists that ethical virtue arises through the habitual repetition of ethically good actions, and thus no one is good or virtuous by nature. Phusikê aretê or “natural virtue” is more like cleverness (demotes) than prudence (phronêsis) and it can result in wrong actions. Yet on the other hand, at times Aristotle appears to use nature to justify normative claims. Thus the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. External Goods and the Complete Exercise of Virtue in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.Sukaina Hirji - 2021 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 103 (1):29-53.
    In Nicomachean Ethics 1.8, Aristotle seems to argue that certain external goods are needed for happiness because, in the first place, they are needed for virtuous activity. This has puzzled scholars. After all, it seems possible for a virtuous agent to exercise her virtuous character even under conditions of extreme hardship or deprivation. Indeed, it is natural to think these are precisely the conditions under which one's virtue shines through most clearly. Why then does Aristotle think that a wide (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  34
    The Golden Age of Virtue: Aristotle's Ethics.Vasilis Politis & Theodore Scaltsas - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (179):258.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  55
    On the Heavens.384-322 B. C. Aristotle - 1939 - Heinemann Harvard University Press.
    Aristotle, great Greek philosopher, researcher, reasoner, and writer, born at Stagirus in 384 BCE, was the son of Nicomachus, a physician, and Phaestis. He studied under Plato at Athens and taught there ; subsequently he spent three years at the court of a former pupil, Hermeias, in Asia Minor and at this time married Pythias, one of Hermeias's relations. After some time at Mitylene, in 343?2 he was appointed by King Philip of Macedon to be tutor of his teen-aged son (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  24. The Dialectic of Political and Private Senses of Ethical Virtue in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics.John Tutuska - 2013 - Interpretation 40 (1):3-24.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  8
    Cognition of Value in Aristotle’s Ethics: Promise of Enrichment,Threat of Destruction.Deborah Achtenberg - 2012 - SUNY Press.
    Argues that the central cognitive component of ethical virtue for Aristotle is awareness of the value of particulars.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  55
    Aristotle's Ethics A. Tessitore: Reading Aristotle's Ethics: Virtue, Rhetoric, and Political Philosophy. Pp. xi + 155. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996. Cased (Paper, $17.95). ISBN: 0-7914-3047-2 (0-7914-3048-0 pbk). [REVIEW]Trevor J. Saunders - 1997 - The Classical Review 47 (02):330-332.
  27. The Virtues (and a Few Vices) of Daniel Russell's Practical Intelligence and the Virtues.Christopher Toner - 2011 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (3):453-468.
    Daniel Russell's Practical Intelligence and the Virtues is principally a defense of the Aristotelian claim that phronesis is part of every unqualified virtue—a defense of what Russell calls "hard virtue theory" and "hard virtue ethics." The main support for this is the further claim that we would be unable to act well reliably, or form our character reliably, without phronesis performing its "twin roles": correctly identifying the mean of each virtue, and integrating the mean of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  13
    Lawgivers, Virtue, and the Mixed Regime: Reflections on Richard Bodéüs’s The Political Dimensions of Aristotle’s Ethics.Kevin Cherry - 2020 - Dialogue 59 (1):31-50.
    Dans cet article, je considère les travaux de Richard Bodéüs qui traitent de la manière dont Aristote envisage la relation entre loi, vertu, et éducation. Je soutiens qu’il y a une différence importante entre les exigences de la loi et celles de la raison, en particulier dans les régimes défectueux, qui sont aussi les plus communs. Cette différence existe aussi dans le meilleur régime possible pour la plupart des cités, le régime mixte qu’Aristote nomme «politie», parce qu’il représente un mélange (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  7
    Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction (review).Roderick T. Long - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):411-412.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.3 (2003) 411-412 [Access article in PDF] Deborah Achtenberg. Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction. Albany: The State University of New York Press, 2002. Pp. xiii + 218. Paper, $20.95.Deborah Achtenberg argues that, for Aristotle, virtue is a disposition to respond to situations with the appropriate emotions, where emotions are understood as perceptions of the value (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. The Role of Potentiality in Aristotle’s Ethics.Jacob Blumenfeld - 2022 - Journal of Human Values 28 (forthcoming):1-10.
    What I will argue here is that the ethical potentiality of the human being that Aristotle cites in the Nicomachean Ethics refers to the general, rational capacity for someone to appropriate and develop their own specific, natural capacities which make them human; the name of this ability is called virtue, which, when expressed in actions, we call good. To separate out the concepts at work here demands an exegesis of the two kinds of dunamis in Metaphysics Theta, that is, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Moral Knowledge and the Acquisition of Virtue in Aristotle's "Nicomachean" and "Eudemian Ethics".Alex John London - 2001 - Review of Metaphysics 54 (3):553 - 583.
    IN BOTH THE EUDEMIAN ETHICS AND THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Aristotle says that the aim of ethical inquiry is a practical one; we want to know what virtue is so that we may become good ourselves and thereby do well and be happy. By classifying ethical inquiry as a practical endeavor, Aristotle is rejecting a view that he attributes to Socrates according to which ethics is a kind of theoretical science. In theoretical sciences, such as geometry or astronomy, the knowledge (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  17
    The Eudemian Ethics.Aristotle . (ed.) - 2011 - Oxford: Oxford University Press UK.
    'We are looking for the things that enable us to live a noble and happy life...and what prospects decent people will have of acquiring any of them.'The Eudemian Ethics is a major treatise on moral philosophy whose central concern is what makes life worth living. Aristotle considers the role of happiness, and what happiness consists of, and he analyses various factors that contribute to it: human agency, the relation between action and virtue, and the concept of virtue itself. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  58
    The Virtues of Aristotle’s Ethics.Paula Gottlieb - 2009 - Cambridge University Press.
    While Aristotle's account of the happy life continues to receive attention, many of his claims about virtue of character seem so puzzling that modern philosophers have often discarded them, or have reworked them to fit more familiar theories that do not make virtue of character central. In this book, Paula Gottlieb takes a fresh look at Aristotle's claims, particularly the much-maligned doctrine of the mean. She shows how they form a thought-provoking ethic of virtue, one that deserves (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  34. Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle's "Nicomachean Ethics".Gabriel Richardson Lear - 2005 - Princeton University Press.
    Gabriel Richardson Lear presents a bold new approach to one of the enduring debates about Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics: the controversy about whether it coherently argues that the best life for humans is one devoted to a single activity, namely philosophical contemplation. Many scholars oppose this reading because the bulk of the Ethics is devoted to various moral virtues--courage and generosity, for example--that are not in any obvious way either manifestations of philosophical contemplation or subordinated to it. They argue that (...)
  35. Nicomachean Ethics. Aristotle & John M. Armstrong - manuscript
    A new English translation of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. This ongoing project aims to translate accurately the meaning of Aristotle's terse Greek into readable American English for students and the general reader.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  28
    Athletic virtue and aesthetic values in Aristotle’s ethics.Heather Reid - 2019 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 47 (1):63-74.
    ABSTRACTWhen Aristotle praises pentathletes’ beauty at Rhetoric 1361b, it is not the idle observation of a sports fan. In fact, the balanced and harmonious beauty of athletes’ bodies reflects Aristotle’s ideal of a virtuous soul in the Nicomachean Ethics: one which discerns noble ends and means, then acts accordingly. At Eudemian Ethics 1248b, he takes it a step further, characterizing kalokagathia as ‘the virtue that arises from a combination’ of virtues. These passages raise important questions about the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  12
    The Virtues of Aristotle.D. S. Hutchinson - 1986 - Ethics 99 (2):428-429.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  38. Ethics for Rational Animals. The Moral Psychology at the Basis of Aristotle's Ethics.Elena Cagnoli Fiecconi - 2024 - Oxford University Press.
    Ethics for Rational Animals brings to light a novel account of akrasia, practical wisdom, and character virtue through an original and comprehensive study of the moral psychology at the basis of Aristotle's ethics. It argues that practical wisdom is a persuasive rational excellence, that virtue is a listening excellence, and that the ignorance involved in akrasia is in fact a failure of persuasion. Aristotle's moral psychology emerges from this reconstruction as a qualified intellectualism. The view is intellectualistic because (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  30
    Reading Aristotle’s Ethics. Virtue, Rhetoric, and Political Philosophy.Aristide Tessitore - 1996 - State University of New York Press.
    Presents the Nicomachean Ethics as a work of political philosophy, emphasizing the interplay between its practical political concerns and its underlying philosophic perspective and arguing that it is rhetorical in the precise Aristotelian meaning of the term.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40.  35
    Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction (review).Roderick T. Long - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):411-412.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.3 (2003) 411-412 [Access article in PDF] Deborah Achtenberg. Cognition of Value in Aristotle's Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction. Albany: The State University of New York Press, 2002. Pp. xiii + 218. Paper, $20.95.Deborah Achtenberg argues that, for Aristotle, virtue is a disposition to respond to situations with the appropriate emotions, where emotions are understood as perceptions of the value (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  39
    Virtue, Knowledge, and Political Instability in Aristotle’s Politics: Lessons from the Eudemian Ethics.Benjamin Miller - 2021 - Polis 38 (2):261-276.
    I argue that we cannot fully understand Aristotle’s position on political stability and state preservation in the Politics with paying close attention to his Eudemian Ethics. We learn from considering the Politics and the Eudemian Ethics in concert that even ‘correct’ regimes are unstable when citizens do not possess full virtue. Aristotle introduces his formal account of the knowledge requirements for virtue in Eudemian Ethics 8.3, and he applies these knowledge requirements as an explanation for state decline (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  12
    Can virtue be unified? An Aristotelian justification on “unity of virtue”.Manik Konch - 2024 - South African Journal of Philosophy 43 (1):30-41.
    This article explores two contrasting theories of virtue ethics, namely the unity theory of virtue and the disunity theory of virtue. The unity thesis asserts that virtues are unified in some sense, or that possession of one virtue is inextricably related to the possession of all others. Meanwhile, the disunity thesis argues that virtues are disunited, or that there is a lack of unity among the virtues. But still, there are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  91
    Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics on the Sameness of Friendship and Justice.Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - 2023 - Apeiron 56 (3):395-429.
    In the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle claims that friendship and justice are the same, apparently flouting the not uncommon contrast between friendship and justice. I start by assessing Aristotle’s principle of equality: friends of equal standing engage in exact reciprocity in goods and friends of unequal standing engage in proportional reciprocity. In a number of ways that have gone unnoticed, the equalization principle is a requirement for understanding the sameness of friendship and justice. Just relations and friendship share the same (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Wisdom and Action Guidance in the Agent-Based Virtue Ethics of Aristotle.S. Thomas Sherman - 2006 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 80 (4):481-506.
    While Aristotle in the Nicomachean Ethics does not provide a guide for action in the form of rules for a decision process as deontological or consequentialistethical theories purport to do, he does present a description of the virtuous agent and the virtues that this agent exercises in his choices of action. In this paper Iargue that Aristotle’s mature virtuous agent characteristically exercises the virtue of wisdom (sophia) as well as the practical virtues of character and intelligence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. The Activity of Happiness In Aristotle’s Ethics.Gary M. Gurtler - 2003 - Review of Metaphysics 56 (4):801-834.
    This article examines happiness as an activity, modeled on pleasure in NE 10, 1-5. Aristotle is not proposing a choice, but defining the formal nature of happiness. Contemplation, as the activity of wisdom, constitutes happiness in the strict and formal sense. It has all the attributes of happiness, highest, most continuous, most pleasant, most self-sufficient, leisured, and an end in itself. Practical virtues are formally secondary, as including elements outside the activity of the best part and having leisure as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  62
    Virtue in Aristotle's Rhetoric: A Metaphysical and Ethical Capacity.Susan K. Allard-Nelson - 2001 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 34 (3):245 - 259.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Rhetoric 34.3 (2001) 245-259 [Access article in PDF] Virtue in Aristotle's Rhetoric: A Metaphysical and Ethical Capacity Susan K. Allard-Nelson It has been argued that Aristotle's description of excellence (aretê) as a capacity (dynamis) in Rhetoric 1.9 is inconsistent with his treatment of excellence in Nicomachean Ethics 2.5, where he specifically argues that aretê is not a dynamis, but a hexis (i.e., a state or condition). (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Contemplating the Beautiful: The Practical Importance of Theoretical Excellence in Aristotle’s Ethics.James L. Wood - 2011 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 49 (4):391-412.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Contemplating the Beautiful: The Practical Importance of Theoretical Excellence in Aristotle’s EthicsJames L. Wood (bio)Aristotle, unlike plato, famously distinguishes φρόνησις from, practical from theoretical wisdom, in Book VI of the Nicomachean Ethics. He distinguishes them on the basis of both their objects and their psychic spheres: is the excellence or virtue (ἀρετή) of the scientific faculty, τὸ ἐπιστημονικόν, “by which we contemplate [θεωρου̑μεν] the sort of beings (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Virtue and argument in Aristotle's ethics.Iakovos Vasiliou - 2007 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 94 (1):37-78.
  49. The Virtue of Aristotle's Ethics.Paula Gottlieb - 2009 - Cambridge University Press.
    While Aristotle's account of the happy life continues to receive attention, many of his claims about virtue of character seem so puzzling that modern philosophers have often discarded them, or have reworked them to fit more familiar theories that do not make virtue of character central. In this book, Paula Gottlieb takes a fresh look at Aristotle's claims, particularly the much-maligned doctrine of the mean. She shows how they form a thought-provoking ethic of virtue, one that deserves (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50.  35
    The Ethics (P.) Gottlieb The Virtue of Aristotle's Ethics. Pp. xx + 241. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. Cased, £45. ISBN: 978-0-521-76176-5. [REVIEW]Thomas M. Tuozzo - 2011 - The Classical Review 61 (2):408-410.
1 — 50 / 990