Switch to: References

Citations of:

Tractatus logico-philosophicus

New York: Routledge. Edited by Luciano Bazzocchi & P. M. S. Hacker (1994)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A plea for logical objects.Matthew William McKeon - 2009 - Synthese 167 (1):163-182.
    An account of validity that makes what is invalid conditional on how many individuals there are is what I call a conditional account of validity. Here I defend conditional accounts against a criticism derived from Etchemendy’s well-known criticism of the model-theoretic analysis of validity. The criticism is essentially that knowledge of the size of the universe is non-logical and so by making knowledge of the extension of validity depend on knowledge of how many individuals there are, conditional accounts fail to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein and Internal Relations.Marie McGinn - 2010 - European Journal of Philosophy 18 (4):495-509.
    Abstract: Interpretations of the Tractatus divide into what might be called a metaphysical and an anti-metaphysical approach to the work. The central issue between the two interpretative approaches has generally been characterised in terms of the question whether the Tractatus is committed to the idea of ‘things’ that cannot be said in language, and thus to the idea of a distinctive kind of nonsense: nonsense that is an attempt to say what can only be shown. In this paper, I look (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Between metaphysics and nonsense: Elucidation in Wittgenstein's tractatus.Marie McGinn - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (197):491-513.
    There are currently two readings of Tractatus, the metaphysical and the therapeutic. I argue that neither of these is satisfactory. I develop a third reading, the elucidatory reading. This shares the therapeutic interpretation’s emphasis on the idea that Wittgenstein’s remarks are intended to work on the reader, but instead of seeing these remarks as directed (problematically) at revealing their own nonsensical status, I take the remarks to be aimed at bringing a certain order to the reader’s perception of language. The (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Interrogating philosophy?Graham McFee - 1997 - Res Publica 3 (2):239-246.
  • The Philosophical Psychologism of the Tractatus.Richard McDonough - 1993 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (4):425-447.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Propositions: Individuation and Invirtuation.Kris McDaniel - 2015 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (4):757-768.
    The pressure to individuate propositions more finely than intensionally—that is, hyper-intensionally—has two distinct sources. One source is the philosophy of mind: one can believe a proposition without believing an intensionally equivalent proposition. The second source is metaphysics: there are intensionally equivalent propositions, such that one proposition is true in virtue of the other but not vice versa. I focus on what our theory of propositions should look like when it's guided by metaphysical concerns about what is true in virtue of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The philosophy of logical wholism.David Charles Mccarty - 1991 - Synthese 87 (1):51 - 123.
    The present paper is one installment in a lengthy task, the replacement of atomistic interpretations of Wittgenstein's Tractatus by a wholistic interpretation on which the world-in-logical-space is not constructed out of objects but objects are abstracted from out of that space. Here, general arguments against atomism are directed toward a specific target, the four aspects of the atomistic reading of Tractatus given in the Hintikkas' Investigating Wittgenstein (Hintikka & Hintikka 1986). The aspects in question are called the semantical, metaphysical, epistemological (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • One pain is enough.Wallace I. Matson - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):67-67.
  • Wittgenstein and finitism.Mathieu Marion - 1995 - Synthese 105 (2):141 - 176.
    In this paper, elementary but hitherto overlooked connections are established between Wittgenstein's remarks on mathematics, written during his transitional period, and free-variable finitism. After giving a brief description of theTractatus Logico-Philosophicus on quantifiers and generality, I present in the first section Wittgenstein's rejection of quantification theory and his account of general arithmetical propositions, to use modern jargon, as claims (as opposed to statements). As in Skolem's primitive recursive arithmetic and Goodstein's equational calculus, Wittgenstein represented generality by the use of free (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Revisiting the Task/achievement Analysis of Teaching in Neo‐Liberal Times.James D. Marshall - 2009 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 41 (1):79-90.
    In 1975 I published an article on Gilbert Ryle's task/achievement analysis of teaching (), arguing that teaching was in Ryle's sense of the distinction a task verb. Philosophers of education were appealing to a distinction between tasks and achievements in their discussions of teaching, but they were often also appealing to Ryle's work on the analysis of task and achievement verbs. Many philosophers of education misunderstood Ryle's distinction as teaching was often claimed to be a term with both an achievement (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On The (Double) Bind of Representation: From Gregory Bateson to Wim Wenders.Carmelo Marabello & Martino Doni - 2009 - World Futures 65 (8):596-604.
    What follows is the elaboration of a series of discussions held by the two authors at a seminar during which we tried to “read” Wim Wenders's Lisbon Story starting from Gregory Bateson's double bind theory. These discussions then developed into writings that were intertwined, hybridized, corrected, extended, and cut. We experimented directly with the game of relationships, the “mess that works” of the difficult distinction between map and territory, between epistemology and cinematography. Emerging from general considerations on cinema is the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Correct data base: Wrong model?Alexander Marshack - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):767-768.
  • An Evolutionary Approach to Emergence and Social Causation.Nuno Martins - 2011 - Journal of Critical Realism 10 (2):192-218.
    Rom Harré criticizes critical realism for ascribing causal powers to social structures, arguing that it is human individuals, and not social structures, that possess causal powers, and that a false conception of structural causation undermines the emancipatory potential of critical realism. I argue that an interpretation of the category of process as the spatio-temporalization of the category of structure, which underpins much evolutionary theory, provides the conceptual tools to explain how the critical realist transformational model of social activity can escape (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Cambridge Revolt Against Idealism: Was There Ever an Eden?Fraser Macbride - 2012 - Metaphilosophy 43 (1-2):135-146.
    According to one creation myth, analytic philosophy emerged in Cambridge when Moore and Russell abandoned idealism in favour of naive realism: every word stood for something; it was only after “the Fall,” Russell's discovery of his theory of descriptions, that they realized some complex phrases (“the present King of France”) didn't stand for anything. It has become a commonplace of recent scholarship to object that even before the Fall, Russell acknowledged that such phrases may fail to denote. But we need (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On teaching critical thinking.Jim Mackenzie - 1991 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 23 (1):56–78.
  • Kitching's Trouble with Theory: ‘The tree is known by its fruit’ (Mt. 12.33).Jim Mackenzie - 2009 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 41 (3):240-244.
  • Extreme Metaphysics: Hossack on Logical Objects, Facts, Propositions and Universals.Fraser MacBride - 2011 - Dialectica 65 (1):87-101.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Christopher Winch on the Representational Theory of Language and its Pedagogic Relevance.Jim Mackenzie - 2001 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 33 (1):35-56.
    In his recent paper, Winch attacks a group of theories he calls cognitivism. These theories agree in holding that ‘the ability to think, both consciously and subconsciously, amounts to an ability to internally manipulate symbolic representations of that which we think about.The relevance of this attack to education is that ‘Cognitivism’ supplies plausible‐looking reasons for thinking that learning can take place without instruction, practice, memorisation or training and its prestige as a theory of learning devalues those activities within education.Its rejection (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Can structuralism solve the ‘access’ problem?Fraser MacBride - 2004 - Analysis 64 (4):309–317.
  • Lessons from evolution for artificial intelligence?Rudi Lutz - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):766-766.
  • Some formal ontological relations.E. J. Lowe - 2004 - Dialectica 58 (3):297–316.
    Some formal ontological relations are identified, in the context of an account of ontological categorization. It is argued that neither formal ontological relations nor ontological categories should themselves be regarded as elements of being, but that this does not undermine the claim of formal ontology to be a purely objective science. It is also argued that some formal ontological relations, like some ontological categories, are more basic than others. A four‐category ontology is proposed, in which two basic categories of universals (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Criticizing the data: some concerns about empirical approaches to ethics.Michael Loughlin - 2011 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 17 (5):970-975.
  • Wittgenstein's rule-following considerations and moral particularism.Shidan Lotfi - 2009 - Theoria 75 (2):100-116.
    Moral particularists have seen Wittgenstein as a close ally. One of the main reasons for this is that particularists such as Jonathan Dancy and John McDowell have argued that Wittgenstein's so-called "rule-following considerations" (RFCs) provide support for their skepticism about the existence and/or role of rules and principles in ethics. In this paper, I show that while Wittgenstein's RFCs challenge the notion that competence with language, i.e., the ability to apply concepts properly, is like mechanically following a rule, he does (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ontology, semantics and philosophy of mind in Wittgenstein's tractatus: A formal reconstruction. [REVIEW]Gert Jan Lokhorst - 1988 - Erkenntnis 29 (1):35 - 75.
    The paper presents a formal explication of the early Wittgenstein's views on ontology, the syntax and semantics of an ideal logical language, and the propositional attitudes. It will be shown that Wittgenstein gave a language of thought analysis of propositional attitude ascriptions, and that his ontological views imply that such ascriptions are truth-functions of (and supervenient upon) elementary sentences. Finally, an axiomatization of a quantified doxastic modal logic corresponding to Tractarian semantics will be given.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Functional behaviorism: Where the pain is does not matter.A. W. Logue - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):66-66.
  • Sensible Atoms: A Techno-aesthetic Approach to Representation. [REVIEW]Sacha Loeve - 2011 - NanoEthics 5 (2):203-222.
    This essay argues that nano-images would be best understood with an aesthetical approach rather than with an epistemological critique. For this aim, I propose a ‘techno-aesthetical’ approach: an enquiry into the way instruments and machines transform the logic of the sensible itself and not just the way by which it represents something else. Unlike critical epistemology, which remains self-evidently grounded on a representationalist philosophy, the approach developed here presents the advantage of providing a clear-cut distinction between image-as-representation and other modes (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Against dichotomizing pain.John D. Loeser - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):65-65.
  • 'Meaning is use' in the tractatus.Paul Livingston - 2004 - Philosophical Investigations 27 (1):34–67.
    Frege ridiculed the formalist conception of mathematics by saying that the formalists confused the unimportant thing, the sign, with the important, the meaning. Surely, one wishes to say, mathematics does not treat of dashes on a bit of paper. Frege’s idea could be expressed thus: the propositions of mathematics, if they were just complexes of dashes, would be dead and utterly uninteresting, whereas they obviously have a kind of life. And the same, of course, could be said of any proposition: (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Wittgenstein and logic.Montgomery Link - 2009 - Synthese 166 (1):41-54.
    In his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951) presents the concept of order in terms of a notational iteration that is completely logical but not part of logic. Logic for him is not the foundation of mathematical concepts but rather a purely formal way of reflecting the world that at the minimum adds absolutely no content. Order for him is not based on the concepts of logic but is instead revealed through an ideal notational series. He states that logic is “transcendental”. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Bifurcated Subject.Lilian Alweiss - 2009 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17 (3):415-434.
    Michel Henry wishes to salvage Descartes’s first principle ‘I think, I am’ by claiming that there is no need to appeal to the world or others to make sense of the self. One of his main targets is Edmund Husserl, who claims that thought is necessarily intentional and thus necessarily about something that is other to thought. To show that this is not so, Henry draws on passages from Descartes’s texts which emphasize that we should not equate the cogito with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What is Darwinian naturalism?Tim Lewens - 2005 - Biology and Philosophy 20 (4):901-912.
  • Prior, Berkeley, and the Barcan formula.James Levine - 2016 - Synthese 193 (11):3551-3565.
    This paper presents structural similarities and historical connections between Prior’s rejection of the Barcan formula and his critique of Berkeley’s master argument for idealism in his 1955 paper “Berkeley in Logical Form”. Making use of Mackie’s paper “Self-Refutation—A Formal Analysis”, it concludes with some suggestions concerning what is at stake in the debate between Prior and Berkeley and in structurally similar debates such as whether to accept the Barcan formula.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the “Gray’s Elegy” Argument and its Bearing on Frege’s Theory of Sense.James Levine - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (2):251–295.
    In his recent book, "The Metaphysicians of Meaning" (2000), Gideon Makin argues that in the so-called "Gray's Elegy" argument (the GEA) in "On Denoting", Russell provides decisive arguments against not only his own theory of denoting concepts but also Frege's theory of sense. I argue that by failing to recognize fundamental differences between the two theories, Makin fails to recognize that the GEA has less force against Frege's theory than against Russell's own earlier theory. While I agree with many aspects (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Les fonctions de probabilité: la question de leur définissabilité récursive.Hugues Leblanc & Peter Roeper - 1992 - Dialogue 31 (4):643-.
    Pensons aux divers énoncés qui peuvent être composés à partir d'un ensemble fini ou dénombrable d'énoncés atomiques à l'aide de, disons, ‘˜’ et ‘&’; soit A n'importe lequel de ces énoncés; et soit l'ensemble SA des composantes atomiques de A. La valeur de vérité de A dépend évidemment des valeurs de vérité de certains membres de SA. En effet, si aux valeurs de vérité Vrai et Faux sont substitués les entiers 1 et 0, respectivement; la valeur de vérité VVV d'une (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Private language: recognizing a useful nonsense. [REVIEW]Laxminarayan Lenka - 2007 - AI and Society 21 (1-2):14-26.
  • Positivism and philosophy of religion.Ronald S. Laura - 1972 - Sophia 11 (3):13-20.
    I propose to show that the use that has often been made of wittgenstein's work in the philosophy of religion is innocuous. the notion that the meaning of a word or a sentence is the use to which it is put has been exploited in such a way that it neither does justice to religious belief nor to wittgenstein's thought. i endeavour to show that the burden of the positivist programme was not to withold from religious language the accolade of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • New frontiers in the philosophy of science and new age education.Ronald S. Laura - 1988 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 20 (1):63–69.
  • Pain behavior: How to define the operant.Hugh Lacey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):64-65.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language equals mimesis plus speech.Aarre Laakso - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):765-766.
  • Logic for morals, morals from logic.Charlie Kurth - 2011 - Philosophical Studies 155 (2):161-180.
    The need to distinguish between logical and extra-logical varieties of inference, entailment, validity, and consistency has played a prominent role in meta-ethical debates between expressivists and descriptivists. But, to date, the importance that matters of logical form play in these distinctions has been overlooked. That’s a mistake given the foundational place that logical form plays in our understanding of the difference between the logical and the extra-logical. This essay argues that descriptivists are better positioned than their expressivist rivals to provide (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The reality of absences.Boris Kukso - 2006 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (1):21 – 37.
    In this paper, I make a contribution to a naturalistically-minded theory of truthmakers by proposing a solution to the nasty problem of truthmakers for negative truths. After formulating the difficulty, I consider and reject a number of solutions to the problem, including Armstrong's states of affairs of totality, incompatibility accounts, and JC Beall 's polarity view. I then defend the position that absences of truthmakers are real and are responsible for making negative truths true. According to the positive account of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The Promise That Love Will Last.Camilla Kronqvist - 2011 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 54 (6):650 - 668.
    Abstract What sense are we to make of the promise of love against the contingency of human life? I discuss two replies to this question: (1) the suggestion that marriage, based on the probable success of this kind of relationship, is a more or less worthwhile endeavour (cf. Moller and Landau), and (2) Martha Nussbaum's Aristotelian proposal that we only live life fully if we embrace aspects of life, such as loving relationships, that are vulnerable to fortune. I show that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Emergence of Logical Formalization in the Philosophy of Religion: Genesis, Crisis, and Rehabilitation.Anders Kraal - 2013 - History and Philosophy of Logic 34 (4):351 - 366.
    The paper offers a historical survey of the emergence of logical formalization in twentieth-century analytically oriented philosophy of religion. This development is taken to have passed through three main ?stages?: a pioneering stage in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries (led by Frege and Russell), a stage of crisis in the 1920s and early 1930s (occasioned by Wittgenstein, logical positivists such as Carnap, and neo-Thomists such as Maritain), and a stage of rehabilitation in the 1930s, 1940s, and 1950s (led (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle’s On Sophistical Refutations.Erik C. W. Krabbe - 2012 - Topoi 31 (2):243-248.
  • Philosophy of Conceptual Network.Bernard Korzeniewski - 2014 - Open Journal of Philosophy 4 (4):451-491.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Music education, performativity and aestheticization.Constantijn Koopman - 2005 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 37 (1):119–131.
    This paper discusses the phenomena of performativity and aestheticization and their implications for education. The forces of performativity pose a threat to music and the other arts, even though some advocators try to justify music education by appealing to their alleged performative results. At first sight, aestheticization seems to accord much better with music education but closer analysis of this many‐sided phenomenon also yields negative points: superficiality often reigns, overfeeding leads to anaesthesia, and the aesthetic itself is often controlled by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The difficulty with the well-formedness of ontological statements.Guido Küng - 1983 - Topoi 2 (1):111-119.
    When Russell argued for his ontological convictions, for instance that there are negative facts or that there are universals, he expressed himself in English. But Wittgenstein must have noticed that from the point of view of Russell's ideal language these ontological statements appear to be pseudo-propositions. He believed therefore that what these statements pretend to say, could not really be said but only shown. Carnap discovered a way out of this mutism: what in the material mode of speech of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The functions of Russell’s no class theory.Kevin C. Klement - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):633-664.
    Certain commentators on Russell's “no class” theory, in which apparent reference to classes or sets is eliminated using higher-order quantification, including W. V. Quine and (recently) Scott Soames, have doubted its success, noting the obscurity of Russell’s understanding of so-called “propositional functions”. These critics allege that realist readings of propositional functions fail to avoid commitment to classes or sets (or something equally problematic), and that nominalist readings fail to meet the demands placed on classes by mathematics. I show that Russell (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • “True” as Ambiguous.Max Kölbel - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (2):359-384.
    In this paper, I argue (a) that the predicate "true" is ambiguously used to express a deflationary and a substantial concept of truth and (b) that the two concepts are systematically related in that substantial truths are deflationary truths of a certain kind. Claim (a) allows one to accept the main insights of deflationism but still take seriously, and participate in, the traditional debate about the nature of truth. Claim (b) is a contribution to that debate. The overall position is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The accountability of hand-drawn maps and rendering practices.Yutaka Kitazawa - 1999 - Human Studies 22 (2-4):299-314.
    This paper presents an ethnomethodological analysis of the representation of space in hand-drawn maps. The rendering practice of hand drawn maps includes some systematic devices by which real space is transformed into two-dimensional space on paper and a map is recognized as the map representing a certain space. In other words, members use these devices not only to trace real space but also to enable the recognition of space in a specific mode. The paper deals with three distinctive patterns affording (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation