Results for 'Spectral geometry'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  61
    Missing the point in noncommutative geometry.Nick Huggett, Tushar Menon & Fedele Lizzi - unknown - Synthese 199 (1-2):4695-4728.
    Noncommutative geometries generalize standard smooth geometries, parametrizing the noncommutativity of dimensions with a fundamental quantity with the dimensions of area. The question arises then of whether the concept of a region smaller than the scale—and ultimately the concept of a point—makes sense in such a theory. We argue that it does not, in two interrelated ways. In the context of Connes’ spectral triple approach, we show that arbitrarily small regions are not definable in the formal sense. While in the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  16
    De nouvelles géométries et dynamiques au cœur de la nature et du vivant? Vers un renouveau de la philosophie de la nature.Luciano Boi - 2021 - Rue Descartes 99 (1):112-133.
    « Les sciences s’éloignent de plus en plus de leur motivation première, d’une part parce qu’elles s’enferment dans leurs spécialisations respectives, de l’autre, parce qu’elles se réduisent à une pratique utilitariste ou purement calculatoire. Il faudrait s’employer à réhabiliter une pensée exigeante et transversale capable de repérer les similitudes à l’œuvre dans les disciplines et les phénomènes les plus différents. La compréhension spatiale et temporelle des phénomènes est le dénominateur commun capable de les unifier, tout en en reconnaissant les différences (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  17
    Quantum Gravity on a Quantum Computer?Achim Kempf - 2014 - Foundations of Physics 44 (5):472-482.
    EPR-type measurements on spatially separated entangled spin qubits allow one, in principle, to detect curvature. Also the entanglement of the vacuum state is affected by curvature. Here, we ask if the curvature of spacetime can be expressed entirely in terms of the spatial entanglement structure of the vacuum. This would open up the prospect that quantum gravity could be simulated on a quantum computer and that quantum information techniques could be fully employed in the study of quantum gravity.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  10
    Points. Lack thereof.Fedele Lizzi - 2019 - Philosophical Problems in Science 66:35-60.
    I will discuss some aspects of the concept of “point” in quantum gravity, using mainly the tool of noncommutative geometry. I will argue that at Planck’s distances the very concept of point may lose its meaning. I will then show how, using the spectral action and a high momenta expansion, the connections between points, as probed by boson propagators, vanish. This discussion follows closely.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  18
    L'«École de l'ETH» dans l'œuvre de Gaston Bachelard.Charles Alunni - 2005 - Revue de Synthèse 126 (2):367-389.
    Il s'agit de retracer ici la présence spectrale dans l'oeuvre de Gaston Bachelard de ce que nous appelons «École de l'ETH ». Nous en avons choisi trois figures fondamentales: Hermann Weyl, Wolfgang Pauli et Gustave Juvet. Pour le premier, nous traitons de sa place centrale et permanente dans la constitution bachelardienne d'une philosophie qui se veut à hauteur de la nouvelle « géométrie physique » rigoureusement construite dans un esprit riemannien. Quant à Pauli, nous montrons une insoupçonnable affinité qui est (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  3
    Verallgemeinerte gravitationstheorie.Ulrich Hoyer - 1989 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 20 (2):287-302.
    Proceeding from the principles of Euclidean geometry and absolute time a generalization of the classical theory of gravitation for high velocities is given. The new theory is applied to the redshift of spectral lines, the deviation of light passing the sun, and the secular motion of the perihelion of Mercury. A comparison with the results obtained from the theory of general relativity, though not beyond any doubt, seems to be favourable for the new theory, and to support the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  13
    A Modified Lorentz-Transformation–Based Gravity Model Confirming Basic GRT Experiments.Jan Broekaert - 2005 - Foundations of Physics 35 (5):839-864.
    Implementing Poincaré’s geometric conventionalism a scalar Lorentz-covariant gravity model is obtained based on gravitationally modified Lorentz transformations (or GMLT). The modification essentially consists of an appropriate space-time and momentum-energy scaling (“normalization”) relative to a nondynamical flat background geometry according to an isotropic, nonsingular gravitational affecting function Φ(r). Elimination of the gravitationally unaffected S 0 perspective by local composition of space–time GMLT recovers the local Minkowskian metric and thus preserves the invariance of the locally observed velocity of light. The associated (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Harald Schwaetzer.Bunte Geometrie - 2009 - In Klaus Reinhardt, Harald Schwaetzer & Franz-Bernhard Stammkötter (eds.), Heymericus de Campo: Philosophie Und Theologie Im 15. Jahrhundert. Roderer. pp. 28--183.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Vigier III.Spin Foam Spinors & Fundamental Space-Time Geometry - 2000 - Foundations of Physics 30 (1).
  10.  4
    D'Erehwon à l'Antre du Cyclope.Géométrie de L'Incommunicable & La Folie - 1988 - In Barry Smart (ed.), Michel Foucault: critical assessments. New York: Routledge.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  8
    Geometry intuitions without vision? A study in blind children and adults.Cathy Marlair, Elisa Pierret & Virginie Crollen - 2021 - Cognition 216 (C):104861.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  17
    Frigyes Riesz and the emergence of general topology: The roots of ‘topological space’ in geometry.Laura Rodríguez - 2015 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 69 (1):55-102.
    In 1906, Frigyes Riesz introduced a preliminary version of the notion of a topological space. He called it a mathematical continuum. This development can be traced back to the end of 1904 when, genuinely interested in taking up Hilbert’s foundations of geometry from 1902, Riesz aimed to extend Hilbert’s notion of a two-dimensional manifold to the three-dimensional case. Starting with the plane as an abstract point-set, Hilbert had postulated the existence of a system of neighbourhoods, thereby introducing the notion (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  61
    Time and physical geometry.Hilary Putnam - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (8):240-247.
  14. Instruction to Authors 279–283 Index to Volume 20 285–286.Christian Lotz, Corinne Painter, Sebastian Luft, Harry P. Reeder, Semantic Texture, Luciano Boi, Questions Regarding Husserlian Geometry, James R. Mensch & Postfoundational Phenomenology Husserlian - 2004 - Husserl Studies 20:285-286.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Recalcitrant Disagreement in Mathematics: An “Endless and Depressing Controversy” in the History of Italian Algebraic Geometry.Silvia De Toffoli & Claudio Fontanari - 2023 - Global Philosophy 33 (38):1-29.
    If there is an area of discourse in which disagreement is virtually absent, it is mathematics. After all, mathematicians justify their claims with deductive proofs: arguments that entail their conclusions. But is mathematics really exceptional in this respect? Looking at the history and practice of mathematics, we soon realize that it is not. First, deductive arguments must start somewhere. How should we choose the starting points (i.e., the axioms)? Second, mathematicians, like the rest of us, are fallible. Their ability to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  5
    The Foundations of Geometry.David Hilbert - 1899 - Open Court Company (This Edition Published 1921).
    §30. Significance of Desargues's theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 64 CHAPTER VI. PASCAL'S THEOREM. §31. ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  17.  57
    Algebraic Fields and the Dynamical Approach to Physical Geometry.Tushar Menon - 2019 - Philosophy of Science 86 (5):1273-1283.
    Brown and Pooley’s ‘dynamical approach’ to physical theories asserts, in opposition to the orthodox position on physical geometry, that facts about physical geometry are grounded in, or explained by, facts about dynamical fields, not the other way round. John Norton has claimed that the proponent of the dynamical approach is illicitly committed to spatiotemporal presumptions in ‘constructing’ space-time from facts about dynamical symmetries. In this article, I present an abstract, algebraic formulation of field theories and demonstrate that the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18. Universal Agent Mixtures and the Geometry of Intelligence.Samuel Allen Alexander, David Quarel, Len Du & Marcus Hutter - 2023 - Aistats.
    Inspired by recent progress in multi-agent Reinforcement Learning (RL), in this work we examine the collective intelligent behaviour of theoretical universal agents by introducing a weighted mixture operation. Given a weighted set of agents, their weighted mixture is a new agent whose expected total reward in any environment is the corresponding weighted average of the original agents' expected total rewards in that environment. Thus, if RL agent intelligence is quantified in terms of performance across environments, the weighted mixture's intelligence is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. On the relationship between plane and solid geometry.Andrew Arana & Paolo Mancosu - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):294-353.
    Traditional geometry concerns itself with planimetric and stereometric considerations, which are at the root of the division between plane and solid geometry. To raise the issue of the relation between these two areas brings with it a host of different problems that pertain to mathematical practice, epistemology, semantics, ontology, methodology, and logic. In addition, issues of psychology and pedagogy are also important here. To our knowledge there is no single contribution that studies in detail even one of the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  20.  11
    The Completeness of Scientific Theories: On the Derivation of Empirical Indicators within a Theoretical Framework: The Case of Physical Geometry.Martin Carrier - 2012 - Springer.
    Earlier in this century, many philosophers of science (for example, Rudolf Carnap) drew a fairly sharp distinction between theory and observation, between theoretical terms like 'mass' and 'electron', and observation terms like 'measures three meters in length' and 'is _2° Celsius'. By simply looking at our instruments we can ascertain what numbers our measurements yield. Creatures like mass are different: we determine mass by calculation; we never directly observe a mass. Nor an electron: this term is introduced in order to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  21.  31
    Frege and the origins of model theory in nineteenth century geometry.Günther Eder - 2019 - Synthese 198 (6):5547-5575.
    The aim of this article is to contribute to a better understanding of Frege’s views on semantics and metatheory by looking at his take on several themes in nineteenth century geometry that were significant for the development of modern model-theoretic semantics. I will focus on three issues in which a central semantic idea, the idea of reinterpreting non-logical terms, gradually came to play a substantial role: the introduction of elements at infinity in projective geometry; the study of transfer (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  7
    The quantized geometry of visual space: The coherent computation of depth, form, and lightness.Stephen Grossberg - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):625.
  23. Objectivity and Rigor in Classical Italian Algebraic Geometry.Silvia De Toffoli & Claudio Fontanari - 2022 - Noesis 38:195-212.
    The classification of algebraic surfaces by the Italian School of algebraic geometry is universally recognized as a breakthrough in 20th-century mathematics. The methods by which it was achieved do not, however, meet the modern standard of rigor and therefore appear dubious from a contemporary viewpoint. In this article, we offer a glimpse into the mathematical practice of the three leading exponents of the Italian School of algebraic geometry: Castelnuovo, Enriques, and Severi. We then bring into focus their distinctive (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Space–time philosophy reconstructed via massive Nordström scalar gravities? Laws vs. geometry, conventionality, and underdetermination.J. Brian Pitts - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 53:73-92.
    What if gravity satisfied the Klein-Gordon equation? Both particle physics from the 1920s-30s and the 1890s Neumann-Seeliger modification of Newtonian gravity with exponential decay suggest considering a "graviton mass term" for gravity, which is _algebraic_ in the potential. Unlike Nordström's "massless" theory, massive scalar gravity is strictly special relativistic in the sense of being invariant under the Poincaré group but not the 15-parameter Bateman-Cunningham conformal group. It therefore exhibits the whole of Minkowski space-time structure, albeit only indirectly concerning volumes. Massive (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  25.  25
    On the Foundations of Geometry.Henri Poincaré - 1898 - The Monist 9 (1):1-43.
  26. A 2-dimensional geometry for biological time.Francis Bailly, Giuseppe Longo & Maël Montévil - 2011 - Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 106:474 - 484.
    This paper proposes an abstract mathematical frame for describing some features of biological time. The key point is that usual physical (linear) representation of time is insufficient, in our view, for the understanding key phenomena of life, such as rhythms, both physical (circadian, seasonal …) and properly biological (heart beating, respiration, metabolic …). In particular, the role of biological rhythms do not seem to have any counterpart in mathematical formalization of physical clocks, which are based on frequencies along the usual (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  14
    What can geometry explain?Graham Nerlich - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (1):69-83.
  28.  18
    Orthogonality and Spacetime Geometry.Robert Goldblatt - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (2):335-336.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  29.  9
    Axiomatizability of geometry without points.Andrzej Grzegorczyk - 1960 - Synthese 12 (2-3):228 - 235.
  30.  19
    Free Variation and the Intuition of Geometric Essences: Some Reflections on Phenomenology and Modern Geometry.Richard Tieszen - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):153-173.
    Edmund Husserl has argued that we can intuit essences and, moreover, that it is possible to formulate a method for intuiting essences. Husserl calls this method ‘ideation’. In this paper I bring a fresh perspective to bear on these claims by illustrating them in connection with some examples from modern pure geometry. I follow Husserl in describing geometric essences as invariants through different types of free variations and I then link this to the mapping out of geometric invariants in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  31.  20
    Mathematizing Space: The Objects of Geometry from Antiquity to the Early Modern Age.Vincenzo De Risi (ed.) - 2015 - Birkhäuser.
    This book brings together papers of the conference on 'Space, Geometry and the Imagination from Antiquity to the Modern Age' held in Berlin, Germany, 27-29 August 2012. Focusing on the interconnections between the history of geometry and the philosophy of space in the pre-Modern and Early Modern Age, the essays in this volume are particularly directed toward elucidating the complex epistemological revolution that transformed the classical geometry of figures into the modern geometry of space. Contributors: Graciela (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  11
    The Primacy of Geometry.Meir Hemmo & Amit Hagar - 2013 - Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 (3):357-364.
    We argue that current constructive approaches to the special theory of relativity do not derive the geometrical Minkowski structure from the dynamics but rather assume it. We further argue that in current physics there can be no dynamical derivation of primitive geometrical notions such as length. By this we believe we continue an argument initiated by Einstein.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  33. Frege on the Foundation of Geometry in Intuition.Jeremy Shipley - 2015 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 3 (6).
    I investigate the role of geometric intuition in Frege’s early mathematical works and the significance of his view of the role of intuition in geometry to properly understanding the aims of his logicist project. I critically evaluate the interpretations of Mark Wilson, Jamie Tappenden, and Michael Dummett. The final analysis that I provide clarifies the relationship of Frege’s restricted logicist project to dominant trends in German mathematical research, in particular to Weierstrassian arithmetization and to the Riemannian conceptual/geometrical tradition at (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34. Natural number and natural geometry.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2011 - In Stanislas Dehaene & Elizabeth Brannon (eds.), Space, Time and Number in the Brain: Searching for the Foundations of Mathematical Thought. Oxford University Press. pp. 287--317.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  35.  13
    Mario Pieri’s View of the Symbiotic Relationship between the Foundations and the Teaching of Elementary Geometry in the Context of the Early Twentieth Century Proposals for Pedagogical Reform.Elena Anne Corie Marchisotto & Ana Millán Gasca - 2021 - Philosophia Scientiae 25:157-183.
    In this paper, we discuss a proposal for reform in the teaching of Euclidean geometry that reveals the symbiotic relationship between axiomatics and pedagogy. We examine the role of intuition in this kind of reform, as expressed by Mario Pieri, a prominent member of the Schools of Peano and Segre at the University of Turin. We are well aware of the centuries of attention paid to the notion of intuition by mathematicians, mathematics educators, philosophers, psychologists, historians, and others. To (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  11
    Analysis in greek geometry.Richard Robinson - 1936 - Mind 45 (180):464-473.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  37.  14
    How euclidean geometry has misled metaphysics.Graham Nerlich - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):169-189.
  38.  30
    The Determinate World: Kant and Helmholtz on the Physical Meaning of Geometry.David Jalal Hyder - 2009 - Berlin and New York: De Gruyter.
    This book offers a new interpretation of Hermann von Helmholtz's work on the epistemology of geometry. A detailed analysis of the philosophical arguments of Helmholtz's Erhaltung der Kraft shows that he took physical theories to be constrained by a regulative ideal. They must render nature "completely comprehensible", which implies that all physical magnitudes must be relations among empirically given phenomena. This conviction eventually forced Helmholtz to explain how geometry itself could be so construed. Hyder shows how Helmholtz answered (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  39.  21
    Diagrams, Conceptual Space and Time, and Latent Geometry.Lorenzo Magnani - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (6):1483-1503.
    The “origins” of (geometric) space is examined from the perspective of the so-called “conceptual space” or “semantic space”. Semantic space is characterized by its fundamental “locality” that generates an “implicit” mode of geometrizing. This view is examined from within three perspectives. First, the role that various diagrammatic entities play in the everyday life and pragmatic activities of selected ethnic groups is illustrated. Secondly, it is shown how conceptual spaces are fundamentally linked to the meaning effects of particular natural languages and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  27
    Kant on real definitions in geometry.Jeremy Heis - 2014 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44 (5-6):605-630.
    This paper gives a contextualized reading of Kant's theory of real definitions in geometry. Though Leibniz, Wolff, Lambert and Kant all believe that definitions in geometry must be ‘real’, they disagree about what a real definition is. These disagreements are made vivid by looking at two of Euclid's definitions. I argue that Kant accepted Euclid's definition of circle and rejected his definition of parallel lines because his conception of mathematics placed uniquely stringent requirements on real definitions in (...). Leibniz, Wolff and Lambert thus accept definitions that Kant rejects because they assign weaker roles to real definitions. (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  41.  2
    New Trends in Geometry, and its Role in the Natural and Life Sciences.Claudio Bartocci, Luciano Boi & Corrado Sinigaglia (eds.) - 2011 - World Scientific.
    This volume focuses on the interactions between mathematics, physics, biology and neuroscience by exploring new geometrical and topological modeling in these fields. Among the highlights are the central roles played by multilevel and scale-change approaches in these disciplines. The integration of mathematics with physics, molecular and cell biology, and the neurosciences, will constitute the new frontier and challenge for 21st century science, where breakthroughs are more likely to span across traditional disciplines.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Cassirer and the Structural Turn in Modern Geometry.Georg Schiemer - 2018 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 6 (3).
    The paper investigates Ernst Cassirer’s structuralist account of geometrical knowledge developed in his Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff. The aim here is twofold. First, to give a closer study of several developments in projective geometry that form the direct background for Cassirer’s philosophical remarks on geometrical concept formation. Specifically, the paper will survey different attempts to justify the principle of duality in projective geometry as well as Felix Klein’s generalization of the use of geometrical transformations in his Erlangen program. The (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  11
    Less cybernetics, more geometry….René Thom - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):166-167.
  44.  89
    Poincaré on the Foundations of Arithmetic and Geometry. Part 1: Against “Dependence-Hierarchy” Interpretations.Katherine Dunlop - 2016 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 6 (2):274-308.
    The main goal of part 1 is to challenge the widely held view that Poincaré orders the sciences in a hierarchy of dependence, such that all others presuppose arithmetic. Commentators have suggested that the intuition that grounds the use of induction in arithmetic also underlies the conception of a continuum, that the consistency of geometrical axioms must be proved through arithmetical induction, and that arithmetical induction licenses the supposition that certain operations form a group. I criticize each of these readings. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  13
    A Note on Penrose’s Spin-Geometry Theorem and the Geometry of ‘Empirical Quantum Angles’.László B. Szabados - 2022 - Foundations of Physics 52 (4):1-12.
    In the traditional formalism of quantum mechanics, a simple direct proof of the Spin Geometry Theorem of Penrose is given; and the structure of a model of the ‘space of the quantum directions’, defined in terms of elementary SU-invariant observables of the quantum mechanical systems, is sketched.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  9
    Rigidity, Force and Physical Geometry.Carlton B. Weinberg - 1941 - Philosophy of Science 8 (4):506-532.
    From the desire to find support and confirmation for our personal sensory observations, and from the human interest in sharing our experiences with others, there emerges a basic principle of scientific method: We demand the possibility of intelligible communication and agreement concerning individuals' sensory perceptions in particular and their experiences in general. This requirement is made both for the natural and social sciences. The raw material offered for logical organization must be capable of exhibiting an inter-subjective character—such material, or protocols, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  53
    Frege on intuition and objecthood in projective geometry.Günther Eder - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):6523-6561.
    In recent years, several scholars have been investigating Frege’s mathematical background, especially in geometry, in order to put his general views on mathematics and logic into proper perspective. In this article I want to continue this line of research and study Frege’s views on geometry in their own right by focussing on his views on a field which occupied center stage in nineteenth century geometry, namely, projective geometry.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  27
    How Problematic is the Near-Euclidean Spatial Geometry of the Large-Scale Universe?M. Holman - 2018 - Foundations of Physics 48 (11):1617-1647.
    Modern observations based on general relativity indicate that the spatial geometry of the expanding, large-scale Universe is very nearly Euclidean. This basic empirical fact is at the core of the so-called “flatness problem”, which is widely perceived to be a major outstanding problem of modern cosmology and as such forms one of the prime motivations behind inflationary models. An inspection of the literature and some further critical reflection however quickly reveals that the typical formulation of this putative problem is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  22
    Tarski and geometry.L. W. Szczerba - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (4):907-912.
  50.  16
    Kant's theory of geometry.Michael Friedman - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (4):455-506.
1 — 50 / 1000