Results for 'Kripke'

(not author) ( search as author name )
914 found
Order:
  1. Kripke’s Wittgenstein and Ginsborg’s Reductive Dispositionalism (In Persian).Ali Hossein Khani - forthcoming - Metaphysics (University of Isfahan).
    Kripke in his famous book on Wittgenstein’s later philosophy argues, on behalf of Wittgenstein, that there can be no fact of the matter as to what a speaker means by her words, that is, no fact that can meet the Constitution Demand and the Normativity Demand. He particularly argues against the dispositional view, according to which meaning facts are constituted by facts about the speaker's dispositions to respond in a certain way on certain occasions. He argues that facts about (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Kripke's knowledge argument against materialism.Adriana Renero - 2023 - Philosophical Perspectives 37 (1):370-387.
    In his unpublished 1979 Lectures on the Philosophy of Mind, Saul Kripke offers a knowledge argument against materialism focusing on deaf people who lack knowledge of auditory experience. Kripke's argument is a precursor of Frank Jackson's better‐known knowledge argument against materialism (1982). The paper sets out Kripke's argument, brings out its interest and philosophical importance, and explores some similarities and differences between Kripke's knowledge argument and Jackson's.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. Axiomatizing Kripke’s Theory of Truth.Volker Halbach & Leon Horsten - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (2):677 - 712.
    We investigate axiomatizations of Kripke's theory of truth based on the Strong Kleene evaluation scheme for treating sentences lacking a truth value. Feferman's axiomatization KF formulated in classical logic is an indirect approach, because it is not sound with respect to Kripke's semantics in the straightforward sense: only the sentences that can be proved to be true in KF are valid in Kripke's partial models. Reinhardt proposed to focus just on the sentences that can be proved to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  4. Kripke, the necessary a posteriori, and the two-dimensionalist heresy.Scott Soames - 2006 - In Garc (ed.), Two-Dimensional Semantics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 272--292.
  5. Saul Kripke.Arif Ahmed - 2007 - London: Bloomsbury Academic.
    Saul Kripke is one of the most important and original post-war analytic philosophers. His work has undeniably had a profound impact on the philosophy of language and the philosophy of mind. Yet his ideas are amongst the most challenging frequently encountered by students of philosophy. In this informative and accessible book, Arif Ahmed provides a clear and thorough account of Kripke's philosophy, his major works and ideas, providing an ideal guide to the important and complex thought of this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6. Kripke’s Normativity Argument.José L. Zalabardo - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (4):467-488.
    In Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language, Saul Kripke rejects some of the most popular accounts of what meaning facts consist in on the grounds that they fail to accommodate the normative character of meaning. I argue that a widespread interpretation of Kripke's argument is incorrect. I contend that the argument does not rest on the contrast between descriptive and normative facts, but on the thought that speakers' uses of linguistic expressions have to be justified. I suggest that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  7. Kripke’s sole route to the necessary a posteriori.Erin Eaker - 2014 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44 (3-4):388-406.
    In ‘Kripke on epistemic and metaphysical possibility: two routes to the necessary a posteriori’, Scott Soames identifies two arguments for the existence of necessary a posteriori truths in Naming and Necessity . He argues that Kripke's second argument relies on either of two principles, each of which leads to contradiction. He also claims that it has led to ‘two-dimensionalist’ approaches to the necessary a posteriori which are fundamentally at odds with the insights about meaning and modality expressed in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  59
    Kripke & the existential complaint.Greg Ray - 1994 - Philosophical Studies 74 (2):121 - 135.
    Famously, Saul Kripke proposes that there are contingent a priori truths, and has offered a number of examples to illustrate his claim. The most well-known example involves the standard meter bar in Paris. Purportedly, a certain agent knows a priori that the bar is one meter long. However, in response to a long-standing objection to such examples - the "existential complaint" - generally only modified examples having a conditional form are now considered candidates for the contingent a priori. Gareth (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  18
    Kripke submodels and universal sentences.Ben Ellison, Jonathan Fleischmann, Dan McGinn & Wim Ruitenburg - 2007 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 53 (3):311-320.
    We define two notions for intuitionistic predicate logic: that of a submodel of a Kripke model, and that of a universal sentence. We then prove a corresponding preservation theorem. If a Kripke model is viewed as a functor from a small category to the category of all classical models with morphisms between them, then we define a submodel of a Kripke model to be a restriction of the original Kripke model to a subcategory of its domain, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  10. Kripke, Saul Aaron.Nathan Salmón - 1999 - In Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy (2nd Edition). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. pp. 476.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  26
    Saul Kripke.G. W. Fitch - 2004 - Acumen Publishing.
    Saul Kripke is one of the most original and creative philosophers writing today. His work has had a tremendous impact on the direction that philosophy has taken in the last thirty years and continues to dominate some of its most fundamental aspects. Given Kripke's importance it is perhaps surprising that there is no introduction to his philosophy available to the general student. This book fills that gap. As much of Kripke's work is highly technical, the book's central (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  12.  1
    Kripke’s Newton/George Smith problem and a naming-using-practice-based theory. 이풍실 - 2018 - Cheolhak-Korean Journal of Philosophy 137:185-217.
    본 논고에서는 크립키가 『명명과 필연(Naming and Necessity)』에서 논의했던 두 사례를 소개한다. 이 사례들에서 문제가 되는 것은 특정인을 지칭하는 고유명을 알고 있는 사람이 그렇지 못한 사람에게 처음으로 그 이름을 사용하는 발화이다. 여기서 크립키가 주목하는 현상은 어떤 고유명의 사용은 명백한 오정보와 결합됨에도 불구하고 그 지시체에 대한 거짓 믿음을 성공적으로 야기하는 반면에, 다른 고유명의 사용은 오정보와 결합되어 발화될 경우에 청자로 하여금 그 고유명의 지시체에 대한 거짓 믿음을 야기하는 데 실패할 수 있는 것처럼 보인다는 것이다. 만일 이러한 믿음의 야기가 실패한다면 왜 동일한 인과적 체인의 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  48
    Kripke’s Wittgenstein’s Sceptical Solution and Donald Davidson’s Philosophy of Language.Ali Hossein Khani - 2017 - Dissertation, University of Otago
    This thesis is an attempt to investigate the relation between the views of Wittgenstein as presented by Kripke and Donald Davidson on meaning and linguistic understanding. Kripke’s Wittgenstein, via his sceptical argument, argues that there is no fact about which rule a speaker is following in using a linguistic expression. Now, if one urges that meaning something by a word is essentially a matter of following one rule rather than another, the sceptical argument leads to the radical sceptical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14. Kripke's account of the rule‐following considerations.Andrea Guardo - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (3):366-388.
    This paper argues that most of the alleged straight solutions to the sceptical paradox which Kripke ascribed to Wittgenstein can be regarded as the first horn of a dilemma whose second horn is the paradox itself. The dilemma is proved to be a by‐product of a foundationalist assumption on the notion of justification, as applied to linguistic behaviour. It is maintained that the assumption is unnecessary and that the dilemma is therefore spurious. To this end, an alternative conception of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15. On Kripke’s and Goodman’s Uses of ”Grue’.Ian Hacking - 1993 - Philosophy 68 (265):269-295.
    Kripke's lectures, published as Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language , posed a sceptical problem about following a rule, which he cautiously attributed to Wittgenstein. He briefly noticed an analogy between his new kind of scepticism and Goodman's riddle of induction. ‘Grue’, he said, could be used to formulate a question not about induction but about meaning: the problem would not be Goodman's about induction—‘Why not predict that grass, which has been grue in the past, will be grue in (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  16. Kripke models for linear logic.Gerard Allwein & J. Michael Dunn - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (2):514-545.
    We present a Kripke model for Girard's Linear Logic (without exponentials) in a conservative fashion where the logical functors beyond the basic lattice operations may be added one by one without recourse to such things as negation. You can either have some logical functors or not as you choose. Commutatively and associatively are isolated in such a way that the base Kripke model is a model for noncommutative, nonassociative Linear Logic. We also extend the logic by adding a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  17.  92
    Kripke-Platek Set Theory and the Anti-Foundation Axiom.Michael Rathjen - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (4):435-440.
    The paper investigates the strength of the Anti-Foundation Axiom, AFA, on the basis of Kripke-Platek set theory without Foundation. It is shown that the addition of AFA considerably increases the proof theoretic strength.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18. Kripke on epistemic and metaphysical possibility: Two routes to the necessary aposteriori.Scott Soames - 2011 - In Alan Berger (ed.), Saul Kripke. Cambridge University Press. pp. 167-188.
    Saul Kripke’s discussion of the necessary aposteriori in Naming and Necessity and “Identity and Necessity” -- in which he lays the foundation for distinguishing epistemic from metaphysical possibility, and explaining the relationship between the two – is, in my opinion, one of the outstanding achievements of twentieth century philosophy.1 My aim in this essay is to extract the enduring lessons of his discussion, and disentangle them from certain difficulties which, alas, can also be found there. I will argue that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  19. Kripke’s Revenge.Theodore Sider & David Braun - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (3):669-682.
    Kripke's objections to descriptivism may be modified to apply to Scott Soames's pragmatic account from his book Beyond Rigidity. Further, intuitions about argument-validity threaten any theory in the vicinity of Soames's.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20. Kripke and Putnam on natural kind terms.Keith S. Donnellan - 1983 - In C. Ginet & S. Shoemaker (eds.), Knowledge and Mind. Oxford Univresity Press. pp. 84-104.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  21. Kripke, Quine, the ‘Adoption Problem’ and the Empirical Conception of Logic.Paul Boghossian & Crispin Wright - 2024 - Mind 133 (529):86-116.
    Recently, there has been a significant upsurge of interest in what has come to be known as the 'Adoption Problem', first developed by Saul Kripke in 1974. The problem purports to raise a difficulty for Quine’s anti-exceptionalist conception of logic. In what follows, we first offer a statement of the problem and argue that, so understood, it depends upon natural but resistible assumptions. We then use that discussion as a springboard for developing a different adoption problem, arguing that, for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  96
    Kripke semantics for modal substructural logics.Norihiro Kamide - 2002 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 11 (4):453-470.
    We introduce Kripke semantics for modal substructural logics, and provethe completeness theorems with respect to the semantics. Thecompleteness theorems are proved using an extended Ishihara's method ofcanonical model construction (Ishihara, 2000). The framework presentedcan deal with a broad range of modal substructural logics, including afragment of modal intuitionistic linear logic, and modal versions ofCorsi's logics, Visser's logic, Méndez's logics and relevant logics.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23.  86
    Kripke on Necessity : A Metaphysical Investigation.Kyriakos Theodoridis - unknown
    I undertake a metaphysical investigation of Saul Kripke's modern classic, Naming and Necessity . The general problem of my study may be expressed as follows: What is the metaphysical justification of the validity and existence of the pertinent classes of truths, the necessary a posteriori and the contingent a priori, according to the Kripke Paradigm? My approach is meant to disclose the logical and ontological principles underlying Kripke's arguments for the necessary a posteriori and the contingent a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  48
    Kripke-Style Models for Logics of Evidence and Truth.Henrique Antunes, Walter Carnielli, Andreas Kapsner & Abilio Rodrigues - 2020 - Axioms 9 (3).
    In this paper, we propose Kripke-style models for the logics of evidence and truth LETJ and LETF. These logics extend, respectively, Nelson’s logic N4 and the logic of first-degree entailment with a classicality operator ∘ that recovers classical logic for formulas in its scope. According to the intended interpretation here proposed, these models represent a database that receives information as time passes, and such information can be positive, negative, non-reliable, or reliable, while a formula ∘A means that the information (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  25.  72
    Algebraic Kripke-Style Semantics for Relevance Logics.Eunsuk Yang - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (4):803-826.
    This paper deals with one kind of Kripke-style semantics, which we shall call algebraic Kripke-style semantics, for relevance logics. We first recall the logic R of relevant implication and some closely related systems, their corresponding algebraic structures, and algebraic completeness results. We provide simpler algebraic completeness proofs. We then introduce various types of algebraic Kripke-style semantics for these systems and connect them with algebraic semantics.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26. Incarnating Kripke’s Skepticism About Meaning.Eisuke Sakakibara - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (2):277-291.
    Although Kripke’s skepticism leads to the conclusion that meaning does not exist, his argument relies upon the supposition that more than one interpretation of words is consistent with linguistic evidence. Relying solely on metaphors, he assumes that there is a multiplicity of possible interpretations without providing any strict proof. In his book The Taming of the True, Neil Tennant pointed out that there are serious obstacles to this thesis and concluded that the skeptic’s nonstandard interpretations are “will o’ wisps.” (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Kripke on functionalism and automata.Edward P. Stabler - 1987 - Synthese 70 (January):1-22.
    Saul Kripke has proposed an argument to show that there is a serious problem with many computational accounts of physical systems and with functionalist theories in the philosophy of mind. The problem with computational accounts is roughly that they provide no noncircular way to maintain that any particular function with an infinite domain is realized by any physical system, and functionalism has the similar problem because of the character of the functional systems that are supposed to be realized by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28. Kripke's modal argument is challenged by his implausible conception of introspection.Alexander Heinzel & Georg Northoff - 2009 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 22 (1):13-31.
    Kripke presented one of the most inuential modal arguments against psycho-physical identities. His argument as exemplified by the identity of pain and its respective neural correlates will be analysed in detail. It shall be argued that his reasoning relies on an implausible conception of introspection implying an implausible conception of mental phenomena such as pain. His account does not consider possible interaction of pain and attention as well as the interaction of pain with other psychological factors. Theoretical and empirical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  34
    The Kripke schema in metric topology.Robert Lubarsky, Fred Richman & Peter Schuster - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (6):498-501.
    A form of Kripke's schema turns out to be equivalent to each of the following two statements from metric topology: every open subspace of a separable metric space is separable; every open subset of a separable metric space is a countable union of open balls. Thus Kripke's schema serves as a point of reference for classifying theorems of classical mathematics within Bishop-style constructive reverse mathematics.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Kripke: names, necessity, and identity.Christopher Hughes - 2004 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Saul Kripke, in a series of classic writings of the 1960s and 1970s, changed the face of metaphysics and philosophy of language. Christopher Hughes offers a careful exposition and critical analysis of Kripke's central ideas about names, necessity, and identity. He clears up some common misunderstandings of Kripke's views on rigid designation, causality and reference, and the necessary a posteriori and contingent a priori. Through his engagement with Kripke's ideas Hughes makes a significant contribution to ongoing (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  31.  34
    Kripke-style semantics for many-valued logics.Franco Montagna & Lorenzo Sacchetti - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (6):629.
    This paper deals with Kripke-style semantics for many-valued logics. We introduce various types of Kripke semantics, and we connect them with algebraic semantics. As for modal logics, we relate the axioms of logics extending MTL to properties of the Kripke frames in which they are valid. We show that in the propositional case most logics are complete but not strongly complete with respect to the corresponding class of complete Kripke frames, whereas in the predicate case there (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  32. Kripke: modalità e verità.Achille C. Varzi - 2010 - In Andrea Borghini (ed.), (ed.), Il genio compreso. La filosofia di Saul Kripke. Carocci Editore. pp. 21–76, 186–191.
    An introduction to Kripke’s semantics for propositional and quantified modal logic (with special reference to its historical development from the original 1959 version to the extended versions of 1963 and 1965) and to his theory of truth.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  34
    Kripke Completeness of Infinitary Predicate Multimodal Logics.Yoshihito Tanaka - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (3):326-340.
    Kripke completeness of some infinitary predicate modal logics is presented. More precisely, we prove that if a normal modal logic above is -persistent and universal, the infinitary and predicate extension of with BF and BF is Kripke complete, where BF and BF denote the formulas pi pi and x x, respectively. The results include the completeness of extensions of standard modal logics such as , and its extensions by the schemata T, B, 4, 5, D, and their combinations. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  34. Kripke's account of the argument against private language.Crispin Wright - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (12):759-78.
  35. Wittgenstein, Kripke, and the rule following paradox.Adam M. Croom - 2010 - Dialogue 52 (3):103-109.
    In?201 of Philosophical Investigations, Ludwig Wittgenstein puts forward his famous? rule - following paradox.? The paradox is how can one follow in accord with a rule? the applications of which are potentially infinite? when the instances from which one learns the rule and the instances in which one displays that one has learned the rule are only finite? How can one be certain of rule - following at all? In Wittgenstein: On Rules and Private Language, Saul Kripke concedes the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  27
    Kripke’s Gödel case: Descriptive ambiguity and its experimental interpretation.Chao Ding & Chuang Liu - 2022 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 37 (3):291-308.
    Kripke has taken the Gödel case as a counterexample for reference descriptivism. Machery et al. question the validity of Kripke’s case and had conducted empirical studies to show its inadequacy. Experimental data suggest intuitions on this matter vary both across and within cultures. However, there is a descriptive ambiguity, we argue, in Kripke’s Gödel case, for people associate different types of descriptions with proper names, such as the description of brute facts and the description of social facts. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  60
    Saul Kripke.Alan Berger (ed.) - 2011 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    This collection of essays, based on Saul Kripke's published and unpublished works, represents the most comprehensive analysis of his philosophy and writings available.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  95
    Kripke’s Wittgenstein’s Sceptical Paradox: A Trilemma for Davidson.Ali Hossein Khani - 2019 - International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 9 (1):21–37.
    Davidson’s later philosophy of language has been inspired by Wittgenstein’s Investigations, but Davidson by no means sympathizes with the sceptical problem and solution Kripke attributes to Wittgenstein. Davidson criticizes the sceptical argument for relying on the rule-following conception of meaning, which is, for him, a highly problematic view. He also casts doubt on the plausibility of the sceptical solution as unjustifiably bringing in shared practices of a speech community. According to Davidson, it is rather success in mutual interpretation that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  39.  95
    Kripke on Wittgenstein on Regulation.Virgil C. Aldrich - 1987 - Philosophy 62 (241):375 - 384.
    Kripke's own view of the 'inner life' as comprised of '"qualia"' that have no 'natural "external" manifestation' leads him into misinterpreting wittgenstein's denials on this count. so kripke gives wittgenstein's account a paradoxical and sceptical cast which misrepresents it, making it look as if it called for a sceptical solution and a 'warranted assertibility' theory of truth. but wittgenstein was making sport of the 'inner-outer' (subjective-objective) distinction with the rapier of his suggestion that psychological talk is not regulated (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Kripke.Bryan Frances - 2011 - In Barry Lee (ed.), Key Thinkers in the Philosophy of Language. Continuum. pp. 249-267.
    This chapter introduces Kripke's work to advanced undergraduates, mainly focussing on his "A Puzzle About Belief" and "Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language".
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  47
    Kripke.John P. Burgess - 2012 - Malden, MA: Polity.
    Saul Kripke has been a major influence on analytic philosophy and allied fields for a half-century and more. His early masterpiece, _Naming and Necessity_, reversed the pattern of two centuries of philosophizing about the necessary and the contingent. Although much of his work remains unpublished, several major essays have now appeared in print, most recently in his long-awaited collection _Philosophical Troubles_. In this book Kripke’s long-time colleague, the logician and philosopher John P. Burgess, offers a thorough and self-contained (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  97
    A Kripke-style semantics for R-Mingle using a binary accessibility relation.J. Michael Dunn - 1976 - Studia Logica 35 (2):163 - 172.
  43.  88
    Generalized Kripke Frames.Mai Gehrke - 2006 - Studia Logica 84 (2):241-275.
    Algebraic work [9] shows that the deep theory of possible world semantics is available in the more general setting of substructural logics, at least in an algebraic guise. The question is whether it is also available in a relational form.This article seeks to set the stage for answering this question. Guided by the algebraic theory, but purely relationally we introduce a new type of frames. These structures generalize Kripke structures but are two-sorted, containing both worlds and co-worlds. These latter (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  44. Kripke y las descripciones rígidas.Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra - 1993 - Revista Latinoamericana de Filosofia 19 (1):109-113.
    In this paper I discuss a passage from *Naming and Necessity* where Kripke assumes that the essential properties by means of which a definite description designates are a sufficient condition of its rigidity. I put forward two examples that show the falsity of this assumption. Then I examine the non-rigid character of definite descriptions that designate by means of properties that are sufficient conditions of identity of the objects designated by those descriptions. I conclude that the properties by means (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Kripke and Fixing the References of “God”.Aviezer Tucker - 2002 - International Studies in Philosophy 34 (4):155-160.
    An examination of the similarities between Kripke's treatment of the references of proper names, and Halevi's discussion of the reference of 'God'.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  28
    An algebraic and Kripke-style approach to a certain extension of intuitionistic logic.Cecylia Rauszer - 1980 - Warszawa: [available from Ars Polona].
  47. Kripke on Wittgenstein on rules.Warren D. Goldfarb - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (September):471-488.
  48. Kripke's Second Paragraph of Philosophical Investigations 201.Samuel Weir - 2007 - Philosophical Investigations 30 (2):172–178.
    The received view of Kripke's Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language is that it fails as an interpretation because, inter alia, it ignores or overlooks what Wittgenstein has to say in the second paragraph of Philosophical Investigations 201. In this paper, I demonstrate that the paragraph in question is in fact fully accommodated within Kripke's reading, and cannot therefore be reasonably utilised to object to it. -/- In part one I characterise the objection; in part two I explain (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  65
    Simplified Kripke style semantics for some very weak modal logics.Andrzej Pietruszczak - 2009 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 18 (3-4):271-296.
    In the present paper we examine very weak modal logics C1, D1, E1, S0.5◦, S0.5◦+(D), S0.5 and some of their versions which are closed under replacement of tautological equivalents (rte-versions). We give semantics for these logics, formulated by means of Kripke style models of the form , where w is a «distinguished» world, A is a set of worlds which are alternatives to w, and V is a valuation which for formulae and worlds assigns the truth-vales such that: (i) (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50. Kripke's argument against the identity thesis.Michael E. Levin - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (March):149-67.
1 — 50 / 914